Antisthenes

Last updated
Antisthenes
Antisthenes Pio-Clementino Inv288.jpg
Portrait bust of Antisthenes, found at the Villa of Cassius at Tivoli, 1774 (Museo Pio-Clementino)
Bornc. 446 BC [1]
Athens
Diedc. 366 BC [2] (aged approx. 80)
Athens
Era Ancient philosophy
Region Western philosophy
School Cynicism
Main interests
Asceticism, ethics, language, literature, logic
Notable ideas
Laying the foundations of Cynic philosophy
Distinction between sense and reference

Antisthenes ( /ænˈtɪsθɪnz/ ; [3] Greek : Ἀντισθένης; c. 446 c. 366 BC) [4] was a Greek philosopher and a pupil of Socrates. Antisthenes first learned rhetoric under Gorgias before becoming an ardent disciple of Socrates. He adopted and developed the ethical side of Socrates' teachings, advocating an ascetic life lived in accordance with virtue. Later writers regarded him as the founder of Cynic philosophy.

Contents

Life

Antisthenes was born c. 445 BC and was the son of Antisthenes, an Athenian. His mother was a Thracian. [5] In his youth he fought at Tanagra (426 BC), and was a disciple first of Gorgias, and then of Socrates; so eager was he to hear the words of Socrates that he used to walk daily from Peiraeus to Athens, and persuaded his friends to accompany him. [6] Eventually he was present at Socrates's death. [7] He never forgave his master's persecutors, and is said to have been instrumental in procuring their punishment. [8] He survived the Battle of Leuctra (371 BC), as he is reported to have compared the victory of the Thebans to a set of schoolboys beating their master. [9] Although Eudokia Makrembolitissa supposedly tells us that he died at the age of 70, [10] he was apparently still alive in 366 BC, [11] and he must have been nearer to 80 years old when he died at Athens, c. 365 BC. He is said to have lectured at the Cynosarges, [12] a gymnasium for the use of Athenians born of foreign mothers, near the temple of Heracles. Filled with enthusiasm for the Socratic idea of virtue, he founded a school of his own in the Cynosarges, where he attracted the poorer classes by the simplicity of his life and teaching. He wore a cloak and carried a staff and a wallet, and this costume became the uniform of his followers. [6]

Diogenes Laërtius says that his works filled ten volumes, but of these, only fragments remain. [6] His favourite style seems to have been dialogues, some of them being vehement attacks on his contemporaries, as on Alcibiades in the second of his two works entitled Cyrus, on Gorgias in his Archelaus and on Plato in his Satho. [13] His style was pure and elegant, and Theopompus even said that Plato stole from him many of his thoughts. [14] Cicero, after reading some works by Antisthenes, found his works pleasing and called him "a man more intelligent than learned". [15] He possessed considerable powers of wit and sarcasm, and was fond of playing upon words; saying, for instance, that he would rather fall among crows (korakes) than flatterers (kolakes), for the one devour the dead, but the other the living. [16] Two declamations have survived, named Ajax and Odysseus, which are purely rhetorical.

Antisthenes' nickname was the (Absolute) Dog (ἁπλοκύων, Diog. Laert.6.13) [17] [18] [19]

Philosophy

Marble bust of Antisthenes based on the same original (British Museum) Antisthenes BM 1838.jpg
Marble bust of Antisthenes based on the same original (British Museum)

According to Diogenes Laertius

In his "Lives of the Eminent Philosophers," Diogenes Laertius lists the following as the favorite themes of Antisthenes: "He would prove that virtue can be taught; and that nobility belongs to none other than the virtuous. And he held virtue to be sufficient in itself to ensure happiness, since it needed nothing else except the strength of a Socrates. And he maintained that virtue is an affair of deeds and does not need a store of words or learning; that the wise man is self-sufficing, for all the goods of others are his; that ill repute is a good thing and much the same as pain; that the wise man will be guided in his public acts not by the established laws but by the law of virtue; that he will also marry in order to have children from union with the handsomest women; furthermore that he will not disdain to love, for only the wise man knows who are worthy to be loved". [20]

Ethics

Antisthenes was a pupil of Socrates, from whom he imbibed the fundamental ethical precept that virtue, not pleasure, is the end of existence. Everything that the wise person does, Antisthenes said, conforms to perfect virtue, [21] and pleasure is not only unnecessary, but a positive evil. He is reported to have held pain [22] and even ill-repute (Greek : ἀδοξία) [23] to be blessings, and said that "I'd rather be mad than feel pleasure". [24] It is, however, probable that he did not consider all pleasure worthless, but only that which results from the gratification of sensual or artificial desires, for we find him praising the pleasures which spring "from out of one's soul," [25] and the enjoyments of a wisely chosen friendship. [26] The supreme good he placed in a life lived according to virtue virtue consisting in action, which when obtained is never lost, and exempts the wise person from error. [27] It is closely connected with reason, but to enable it to develop itself in action, and to be sufficient for happiness, it requires the aid of Socratic strength (Greek : Σωκρατικὴ ἱσχύς). [21]

Physics

His work on Natural Philosophy (the Physicus) contained a theory of the nature of the gods, in which he argued that there were many gods believed in by the people, but only one natural God. [28] He also said that God resembles nothing on earth, and therefore could not be understood from any representation. [29]

Logic

In logic, Antisthenes was troubled by the problem of universals. As a proper nominalist, he held that definition and predication are either false or tautological, since we can only say that every individual is what it is, and can give no more than a description of its qualities, e. g. that silver is like tin in colour. [30] Thus he disbelieved the Platonic system of Ideas. "A horse I can see," said Antisthenes, "but horsehood I cannot see". [31] Definition is merely a circuitous method of stating an identity: "a tree is a vegetable growth" is logically no more than "a tree is a tree".

Philosophy of language

Antisthenes apparently distinguished "a general object that can be aligned with the meaning of the utterance” from “a particular object of extensional reference." This "suggests that he makes a distinction between sense and reference." [32] The principal basis of this claim is a quotation in Alexander of Aphrodisias's “Comments on Aristotle's 'Topics'” with a three-way distinction:

  1. the semantic medium, δι' ὧν λέγουσι
  2. an object external to the semantic medium, περὶ οὗ λέγουσιν
  3. the direct indication of a thing, σημαίνειν … τὸ … [33]

Antisthenes and the Cynics

Antisthenes, part of a fresco in the National University of Athens Antisthenes Lebiedzki Rahl.jpg
Antisthenes, part of a fresco in the National University of Athens

In later times, Antisthenes came to be seen as the founder of the Cynics, but it is by no means certain that he would have recognized the term. Aristotle, writing a generation later refers several times to Antisthenes [34] and his followers "the Antistheneans," [30] but makes no reference to Cynicism. [35] There are many later tales about the infamous Cynic Diogenes of Sinope dogging Antisthenes' footsteps and becoming his faithful hound, [36] but it is similarly uncertain that the two men ever met. Some scholars, drawing on the discovery of defaced coins from Sinope dating from the period 350–340 BC, believe that Diogenes only moved to Athens after the death of Antisthenes, [37] and it has been argued that the stories linking Antisthenes to Diogenes were invented by the Stoics in a later period in order to provide a succession linking Socrates to Zeno, via Antisthenes, Diogenes, and Crates. [38] These tales were important to the Stoics for establishing a chain of teaching that ran from Socrates to Zeno. [39] Others argue that the evidence from the coins is weak, and thus Diogenes could have moved to Athens well before 340 BC. [40] It is also possible that Diogenes visited Athens and Antisthenes before his exile, and returned to Sinope. [37]

Antisthenes certainly adopted a rigorous ascetic lifestyle, [41] and he developed many of the principles of Cynic philosophy which became an inspiration for Diogenes and later Cynics. It was said that he had laid the foundations of the city which they afterwards built. [42]

Notes

  1. Luz, Menahem (2019). "Antisthenes' Portrayal of Socrates" from "Brill's Companion to the Reception of Socrates". Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands: Brill. p. 124. ISBN   978-90-04-39674-6.
  2. Luz, Menahem (2019). "Antisthenes' Portrayal of Socrates" from "Brill's Companion to the Reception of Socrates". Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands: Brill. p. 124. ISBN   978-90-04-39674-6.
  3. Jones, Daniel; Roach, Peter James; Hartman, James; Setter, Jane, eds. (2006). Cambridge English Pronouncing Dictionary (17th ed.). Cambridge UP.
  4. Luz, Menahem (2019). "Antisthenes' Portrayal of Socrates" from "Brill's Companion to the Reception of Socrates". Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands: Brill. p. 124. ISBN   978-90-04-39674-6.
  5. Suda , Antisthenes.; Laërtius 1925 , § 1.
  6. 1 2 3 Wikisource-logo.svg One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain : Chisholm, Hugh, ed. (1911). "Antisthenes". Encyclopædia Britannica . 2 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. p. 146.
  7. Plato, Phaedo, 59b.
  8. Laërtius 1925, § 9.
  9. Plutarch, Lycurgus, 30.
  10. Eudocia, Violarium, 96
  11. Diodorus Siculus, xv. 76.4
  12. Laërtius 1925, § 13.
  13. Athenaeus, v. 220c-e
  14. Athenaeus, xi. 508c-d
  15. "Κῦρος δ᾽, ε᾽ mihi sic placuit ut cetera Antisthenis, hominis acuti magis quam eruditi". Cicero, Epistulae ad Atticum, Book XII, Letter 38, section 2. In English translation: "Books four (δ᾽) and five (ε᾽) of Cyrus I found as pleasing as the others composed by Antisthenes, he is a man who is sharp rather than learned".
  16. Laërtius 1925, § 4.
  17. Prince, Susan (Dept. of Classics, University of Colorado, Boulder). Review of LE. Navia - Antisthenes of Athens: Setting the World Aright . Retrieved 6 August 2017.Navia, Luis E. Antisthenes of Athens: Setting the World Aright. Westport: Greenwood Press. pp. xii, 176. ISBN   0-313-31672-4.
  18. Magill, Frank N. (2003). The Ancient World: Dictionary of World Biography. Routledge. p.  89. ISBN   978-1-135-45740-2.
  19. Judge, Harry George; Blake, Robert (1988). World history. Oxford University Press. p.  104. ISBN   978-0-19-869135-8.
  20. Laërtius 1925, § 10.
  21. 1 2 Laërtius 1925, § 11.
  22. Julian, Oration, 6.181b
  23. Laërtius 1925, § 3, 7.
  24. Laërtius 1925, § 3.
  25. Xenophon, Symposium, iv. 41.
  26. Laërtius 1925, § 12.
  27. Laërtius 1925, § 11–12, 104–105.
  28. Cicero, De Natura Deorum, i. 13.
  29. Clement of Alexandria, Stromata, v.
  30. 1 2 Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1043b24
  31. Simplicius, in Arist. Cat. 208, 28
  32. Prince, Susan (2015). Antisthenes of Athens: Texts, Translations, and Commentary. University of Michigan Press. p. 20
  33. Prince 2015, pp. 518–522 (Antisthenes' literary remains: t. 153B.1).
  34. Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1024b26; Rhetoric, 1407a9; Topics, 104b21; Politics, 1284a15
  35. Long 1996, page 32
  36. Laërtius 1925 , § 6, 18, 21; Dio Chrysostom, Orations, viii. 1–4; Aelian, x. 16; Stobaeus, Florilegium, 13.19
  37. 1 2 Long 1996, page 45
  38. Dudley 1937, pages 2-4
  39. Navia, Diogenes the Cynic, page 100
  40. Navia, Diogenes the Cynic, pages 34, 112-3
  41. Xenophon, Symposium, iv. 34–44.
  42. Laërtius 1925, § 15.

Related Research Articles

Zeno of Citium Ancient Greek Stoic philosopher

Zeno of Citium was a Hellenistic philosopher of Phoenician origin from Citium, Cyprus. Zeno was the founder of the Stoic school of philosophy, which he taught in Athens from about 300 BC. Based on the moral ideas of the Cynics, Stoicism laid great emphasis on goodness and peace of mind gained from living a life of Virtue in accordance with Nature. It proved very popular, and flourished as one of the major schools of philosophy from the Hellenistic period through to the Roman era.

Crates of Thebes Cynic philosopher

Crates of Thebes was a Cynic philosopher. Crates gave away his money to live a life of poverty on the streets of Athens. He married Hipparchia of Maroneia who lived in the same manner that he did. Respected by the people of Athens, he is remembered for being the teacher of Zeno of Citium, the founder of Stoicism. Various fragments of Crates' teachings survive, including his description of the ideal Cynic state.

Zeno of Elea Ancient Greek philosopher best known for his paradoxes

Zeno of Elea was a pre-Socratic Greek philosopher of Magna Graecia and a member of the Eleatic School founded by Parmenides. Aristotle called him the inventor of the dialectic. He is best known for his paradoxes, which Bertrand Russell described as "immeasurably subtle and profound".

Diogenes ancient Greek Cynic philosopher from Sinope

Diogenes, also known as Diogenes the Cynic, was a Greek philosopher and one of the founders of Cynic philosophy. He was born in Sinope, an Ionian colony on the Black Sea, in 412 or 404 BC and died at Corinth in 323 BC.

Menippus ancient Greek philosopher and satirist

Menippus of Gadara was a Cynic satirist. His works, all of which are lost, were an important influence on Varro and Lucian. The Menippean satire genre is named after him.

Aristippus 4th-century BC Greek philosopher

Aristippus of Cyrene was the founder of the Cyrenaic school of Philosophy. He was a pupil of Socrates, but adopted a very different philosophical outlook, teaching that the goal of life was to seek pleasure by circumstances to oneself and by maintaining proper control over both adversity and prosperity. His outlook came to be called "ethical hedonism." Among his pupils was his daughter Arete.

Cyrenaics ancient Greek philosophical movement

The Cyrenaics or Kyrenaics were a sensual hedonist Greek school of philosophy founded in the 4th century BCE, supposedly by Aristippus of Cyrene, although many of the principles of the school are believed to have been formalized by his grandson of the same name, Aristippus the Younger. The school was so called after Cyrene, the birthplace of Aristippus. It was one of the earliest Socratic schools. The Cyrenaics taught that the only intrinsic good is pleasure, which meant not just the absence of pain, but positively enjoyable sensations. Of these, momentary pleasures, especially physical ones, are stronger than those of anticipation or memory. They did, however, recognize the value of social obligation and that pleasure could be gained from altruistic behaviour. The school died out within a century and was replaced by the philosophy of Epicureanism.

Euclid of Megara Greek philosopher

Euclid of Megara was a Greek Socratic philosopher who founded the Megarian school of philosophy. He was a pupil of Socrates in the late 5th century BC, and was present at his death. He held the supreme good to be one, eternal and unchangeable, and denied the existence of anything contrary to the good. Editors and translators in the Middle Ages often confused him with Euclid of Alexandria when discussing the latter's Elements.

Stilpo Greek philosopher of the Megarian school

Stilpo was a Greek philosopher of the Megarian school. He was a contemporary of Theophrastus, Diodorus Cronus, and Crates of Thebes. None of his writings survive, he was interested in logic and dialectic, and he argued that the universal is fundamentally separated from the individual and concrete. His ethical teachings approached that of the Cynics and Stoics. His most important followers were Pyrrho, the founder of Pyrrhonism, and Zeno of Citium, the founder of Stoicism.

Megarian school Ancient socratic school

The Megarian school of philosophy, which flourished in the 4th century BC, was founded by Euclides of Megara, one of the pupils of Socrates. Its ethical teachings were derived from Socrates, recognizing a single good, which was apparently combined with the Eleatic doctrine of Unity. Some of Euclides' successors developed logic to such an extent that they became a separate school, known as the Dialectical school. Their work on modal logic, logical conditionals, and propositional logic played an important role in the development of logic in antiquity.

Bion of Borysthenes ancient greek philosopher

Bion of Borysthenes was a Greek philosopher. After being sold into slavery, and then released, he moved to Athens, where he studied in almost every school of philosophy. It is, however, for his Cynic-style diatribes that he is chiefly remembered. He satirized the foolishness of people, attacked religion, and eulogized philosophy.

Simon the Shoemaker was an associate of Socrates, and a 'working-philosopher'. He is known mostly from the account given in Diogenes Laërtius' Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers. He is also mentioned in passing by Plutarch and Synesius; a pupil of Socrates, Phaedo of Elis, is known to have written a dialogue called Simon.

Meletus was an ancient Athenian Greek from the Pithus deme known for his prosecuting role in the trial and eventual execution of the philosopher Socrates.

Aeschines of Sphettus or Aeschines Socraticus, son of Lysanias, of the deme Sphettus of Athens, was a philosopher who in his youth a follower of Socrates. Historians call him Aeschines Socraticus—"the Socratic Aeschines"—to distinguish him from the more historically influential Athenian orator also named Aeschines. His name is sometimes but now rarely written as Aischines or Æschines

Hipparchia of Maroneia Cynic philosopher

Hipparchia of Maroneia was a Cynic philosopher, and wife of Crates of Thebes. She was born in Maroneia, but her family moved to Athens, where Hipparchia came into contact with Crates, the most famous Cynic philosopher in Greece at that time. She fell in love with him, and, despite the disapproval of her parents, she married him. She went on to live a life of Cynic poverty on the streets of Athens with her husband.

Plato was an ancient Greek philosopher, the second of the trio of ancient Greeks including Socrates and Aristotle said to have laid the philosophical foundations of Western culture.

Hellenistic philosophy is the period of Western philosophy and Middle Eastern philosophy that was developed in the Hellenistic period following Aristotle and ending with the beginning of Neoplatonism.

Apollodorus of Seleucia, or Apollodorus Ephillus, was a Stoic philosopher, and a pupil of Diogenes of Babylon.

Cynicism (philosophy) ancient school of philosophy

Cynicism is a school of thought of ancient Greek philosophy as practiced by the Cynics. For the Cynics, the purpose of life is to live in virtue, in agreement with nature. As reasoning creatures, people can gain happiness by rigorous training and by living in a way which is natural for themselves, rejecting all conventional desires for wealth, power, and fame. Instead, they were to lead a simple life free from all possessions.

Socrates Classical Greek Athenian philosopher

Socrates was a classical Greek (Athenian) philosopher credited as one of the founders of Western philosophy, and as being the first moral philosopher of the Western ethical tradition of thought. An enigmatic figure, he made no writings, and is known chiefly through the accounts of classical writers writing after his lifetime, particularly his students Plato and Xenophon. Other sources include the contemporaneous Antisthenes, Aristippus, and Aeschines of Sphettos. Aristophanes, a playwright, is the main contemporary author to have written plays mentioning Socrates during Socrates' lifetime, though a fragment of Ion of Chios' Travel Journal provides important information about Socrates' youth.

References

Further reading