Communication Theory as a Field

Last updated

"Communication Theory as a Field" is a 1999 article by Robert T. Craig, attempting to unify the academic field of communication theory. [1] [2]

Contents

Craig argues that communication theorists can become unified in dialogue by charting what he calls the "dialogical dialectical tension", or the similarities and differences in their understanding of "communication" and demonstrating how those elements create tension within the field. [3] Craig mapped these similarities and differences into seven suggested traditions of communication theory and showed how each of these traditions understand communication, as well as how each tradition's understanding creates tension with the other traditions. [4]

The article has received multiple awards, [5] [6] has become the foundation for many communication theory textbooks, [7] [8] [9] [10] [11] and has been translated into several different languages. [12] [13]

"Communication theory as a field" has created two main dialogues between Craig and other theorists. Myers argued that Craig misrepresented the theoretical assumptions of his theory, and that the theory itself does not distinguish between good and bad theories. [14] Craig responded that Myers misunderstood not only the basic argument of the article, but also misrepresented his own case study. [15] Russill proposed pragmatism as an eighth tradition of communication theory, [16] [17] Craig responded by expanding this idea and placing Russill's proposition in conversation with the other seven traditions. [18]

Recognition and awards

"Communication Theory as a Field" has been recognized by multiple associations for its influence upon the field of communication. These awards include the Best Article Award from the International Communication Association [5] as well as the Golden Anniversary Monograph Award from the National Communication Association. [6] That work has since been translated into French [12] and Russian. [13] The theory presented in "Communication Theory as a Field" has become the basis of the book "Theorizing Communication" which Craig co-edited with Heidi Muller, [8] as well as being adopted by several other communication theory textbooks as a new framework for understanding the field of communication theory. [7] [9] [10] [11]

Metamodel

Sparked by the "Third Debate" within the field of International Relations Theory in the 1980s, "Communication Theory as a Field" expanded the conversation regarding disciplinary identity in the field of communication. [19] [2] [20] [21] [22] [23] [24] At that time, communication theory textbooks had little to no agreement on how to present the field or which theories to include in their textbooks. [25] [26] This article has since become the foundational framework for four different textbooks to introduce the field of communication. [7] [8] [9] [10] [11] In this article Craig "proposes a vision for communication theory that takes a huge step toward unifying this rather disparate field and addressing its complexities." [9] To move toward this unifying vision Craig focused on communication theory as a practical discipline and shows how "various traditions of communication theory can be engaged in dialogue on the practice of communication." [27] [28] In this deliberative process theorists would engage in dialog about the "practical implications of communication theories." [15] In the end Craig proposes seven different traditions of communication theory and outlines how each one of them would engage the others in dialogue. [29]

Craig argues that while the study of communication and communication theory has become a rich and flourishing field "Communication theory as an identifiable field of study does not yet exist" and the field of communication theory has become fragmented into separate domains which simply ignore each other. [30] This inability to engage in dialog with one another causes theorists to view communication from isolated viewpoints, and denies them the richness that is available when engaging different perspectives. [31] Craig argues that communication theorists are all engaging in the study of practical communication. [31] By doing so different traditions are able to have a common ground from which a dialog can form, albeit each taking a different perspective of communication. [31] Through this process of forming a dialog between theorists with different viewpoints on communication "communication theory can fully engage with the ongoing practical discourse (or metadiscourse) about communication in society." [31]

The communication discipline began not as a single discipline, but through many different disciplines independently researching communication. [31] This interdisciplinary beginning has separated theorists through their different conceptions of communication, rather than unifying them in the common topic of communication. [32] Craig argues that the solution to this incoherence in the field of communication is not a unified theory of communication, but to create a dialogue between these theorists which engages these differences with one another to create new understandings of communication. [33] [34]

To achieve this dialog Craig proposes what he calls "Dialogical-Dialectical coherence," or a "common awareness of certain complementaries and tensions among different types of communication theory." [3] Craig believes that the different theories cannot develop in total isolation from one another, therefore this dialogical-dialectical coherence will provide a set of background assumptions from which different theories can engage each other in productive argumentation. [3] Craig argues for a metatheory, or "second level" theory which deals with "first level" theories about communication. [35] This second level metamodel of communication theory would help to understand the differences between first level communication traditions. [36] With this thesis in place, Craig proposes seven suggested traditions of communication that have emerged and each of which have their own way of understanding communication. [37] [38]

  1. Rhetorical: views communication as the practical art of discourse. [39]
  2. Semiotic: views communication as the mediation by signs. [40]
  3. Phenomenological: communication is the experience of dialogue with others. [41]
  4. Cybernetic: communication is the flow of information. [42]
  5. Socio-psychological: communication is the interaction of individuals. [43]
  6. Socio-cultural: communication is the production and reproduction of the social order. [44]
  7. Critical: communication is the process in which all assumptions can be challenged. [45]

These proposed seven traditions of communication theory are then placed on two separate tables [46] first to show how each traditions different interpretation of communication defines the tradition's vocabulary, communication problems, and commonplaces, [47] and next to show what argumentation between the traditions would look like. [48] Craig then outlines the specifics of each tradition. [49]

Conclusion

Craig concluded with an open invitation to explore how the differences in these theories might shed light on key issues, show where new traditions could be created, and engaging communication theory with communication problems through metadiscourse. [50] Craig further proposes several future traditions that could possibly be fit into the metamodel. [51] A feminist tradition where communication is theorized as "connectedness to others", an aesthetic tradition theorizing communication as "embodied performance", an economic tradition theorizing communication as "exchange", and a spiritual tradition theorizing communication on a "nonmaterial or mystical plane of existence." [52]

Response

Myers, constitutive metamodel, and truth

In 2001 Myers, a computer-mediated communication scholar from Loyola University New Orleans, criticizes Craig's ideas in "A Pox on All Compromises: A reply to Craig (1999)." [14] Myers makes two main arguments against Craig's article. Myers argues that Craig misrepresents the metamodel, and that the lack of any critical truth within Craigs construction is problematic for the field of communication theory. [53] [18] The metamodel is misrepresented by unjustly arguing that there is a separation between first and second level constitutive models while hiding the paradox within this statement, and that it privileges the constitutive model rather than another theoretical conception. [54] Next Myers argues that Craig fails to draw any way to discern truth within the theories. [55] Using a case study regarding the rise and fall of technological determinism among computer-mediated communication scholars, [56] Myers argues that a metamodel needs to provide some mechanism that will "reduce misrepresentation and mistake" in evaluating theory. [57] Myers frames Craig's ideas of collective discourse without an evaluative criteria of what is good theory and bad theory as "a Mad Hatter's tea party" which will "allow all to participate in this party of discourse" but will not be able to "inform any of the participants when it is time to leave." [57]

Craig's response to Myers

Craig responded, in "an almost Jamesian reply", [58] that Myers criticisms were not founded in actual inconsistencies within Craigs argument. [59] Rather they were founded in the difference between Myers and Craig's "respective notions of truth and the proper role of empirical truth as a criterion for adjudicating among theories." [59] In regard to Myers first claim that the separation between first level theories and second level metatheory is paradoxical and therefore an inaccurate or misguided distinction, Craig admits that there is a paradox inherent within a separation between first order theories and metatheory but "slippage between logical levels is an inherent feature (or bug) of communication, and we should not forget that theory is, among other things, communication. " [60] Craig cites Gregory Bateson as pointing out that while the theory of logical types forbids the mixing of different "levels" to avoid paradox, "practical communication necessarily does exactly that." [61] Actual communication is fraught with paradox, and while a logicians ideal would have us try and resolve these paradoxes, in actual practice we don't because there is no way to do so. [61] In actually occurring communication people employ different means of dealing with this paradox, but resolving the paradox is not a possible solution. [61] Craig argues that Myers has been unable to prove any inconsistency or misrepresentation when it came to using the constitutive model for his metamodel. [62] Rather than trying to subvert every other theory to a constitutional model, Craig used the constitutive model not for some theory of truth or logical necessity, but because the constitutive model pragmatically will accomplish the goal of the project, that of opening up a space from which competing theories of communication can interact. [60] With this the constitutional model will be able to maintain a theoretical cosmopolitanism. [63]

On the second argument that the metamodel lacks any empirical truth criteria, Craig argues that not only did Myers miss the point of the metamodel by claiming it should evaluate the truth of theories [64] but that Myers own case study fails to back up his point. [65] The metamodel itself does not distinguish the falseness of other models. [66] However, contrary to Myers claim, the metamodel does allow theorists engaged in discussion to judge the validity of theories "on the basis of empirical evidence in ordinary reasonable ways." [66] What the metamodel does deny is a universally established absolute truth in the field of communication theory. [67] Craig points out that Myers was correct in that the metamodel is ill-equipped to judge theories as valid or invalid, it also doesn't do a good job of closing "the Antarctic ozone hole or solve other problems for which it was not designed." [68] The case study that Myers presents is the debate about technological determinism in the realm of Computer Mediated Communication. [56] Craig points out that this debate occurred between social scientific researchers. [68] This type of research has a shared commitment to empirical research methods. [68] So in spite of already possessing a shared truth criteria, these researchers failed to prevent errors Myers hopes would be avoided by holding onto a form of absolute truth. [68] This case study would be a good critique of empirical truth but "how it supports a critique of the constitutive metamodel is less than apparent." [68] By relying upon this case study Myers sabotages his argument for establishing an absolute truth criteria, demonstrating that "we would gain little by holding on to such a criterion." [68]

Russill, pragmatism as an eighth tradition

After this exchange between Myers and Craig, there was no real disciplinary discussion of the metamodel [69] [70] besides textbooks which used the metamodel as a framework for introducing the field. [7] [8] [9] [10] [11] Then in 2004 in an unpublished dissertation, [16] [71] which was mentioned in a footnote in his 2005 "The road not Taken: William James's Radical Empiricism and Communication Theory," [17] [71] Russill proposed the possibly of pragmatism as an eighth tradition of communication studies. [71] [72] [73] [74] This was attempted by using "Craig's rules" for the requirements of a tradition in communication theory [75] [76] [58] which Russill formulates as "a problem formulation..., an initial vocabulary..., and arguments for the plausibility of this viewpoint in relation to prevailing traditions of theory." [77] [78]

Russill did not write his dissertation with the goal of constructing a tradition of communication theory, rather he was attempting to "resuscitate and reconstruct Dewey's theory of the public as a pragmatist theory of democratic communication." [75] [79] To accomplish this goal Russill places Dewey in conversation with a variety of theorists including William James, John Locke, James Carey, Michel Foucault, Jürgen Habermas, and Walter Lippmann among others. [75] [16] Russill makes the argument that the pragmatist tradition "conceptualizes communication in response to the problem of incommensurability." [80] Incommensurability being how a pluralistic society can engage in cooperation when there is an absence "of common, absolute standards for resolving differences." [80] Russill briefly attempted to construct a pragmatist tradition of communication only to establish Dewey's theory of the public within that tradition. [81] [72] To do this he outlines pragmatism as a tradition that identifies the problem formulation as "incommensurability", and the vocabulary as "democracy, publics, power, criticism, response-ability, triple contingency." [77] [80]

Craig's response to Russill

Craig responds to this in "Pragmatism in the Field of Communication Theory" and mentions that while Russill "does not entirely follow 'Craig's Rules'" for a new tradition of communication theory, Russill "does define a pragmatist tradition in terms of a distinct way of framing the problem of communication and articulates premises that make the tradition theoretically and practically plausible." [81] Craig points out that Russill is not the first communication theorists who writes on pragmatism, however he is the first to use the constitutive metamodel to define it as a tradition of communication. [82] This conception of pragmatism as an eighth tradition of communication studies allows a new space for theories, which Craig identified as either ambiguously placed or neglected, to "immediately snap into focus as contributors to a distinct [pragmatic] tradition." [82]

To fully outline a new tradition of communication theory, Russill would have had to fully incorporate that tradition within the dialogical-dialectical matrix. [83] Russill failed to fully consider the full range of criticism which would occur between the Pragmatist tradition and the other traditions of communication. [83] Craig uses the dialogical-dialectical matrix to outline how pragmatism could be incorporated into the metamodel. [84]

See also

Notes

  1. Craig 1999.
  2. 1 2 Littlejohn & Foss 2008, pp. 6.
  3. 1 2 3 Craig 1999, pp. 124.
  4. Craig 1999, pp. 132–149.
  5. 1 2 "International Communication Association Awards" (PDF). International Communication Association. 2003. Archived from the original (PDF) on July 26, 2011. Retrieved January 8, 2011.
  6. 1 2 "National Communication Association Awards" (PDF). National Communication Association. 2001. Retrieved January 8, 2011.
  7. 1 2 3 4 Craig 2007, pp. 125.
  8. 1 2 3 4 Craig & Muller 2007.
  9. 1 2 3 4 5 Littlejohn & Foss 2008.
  10. 1 2 3 4 Griffin 2006.
  11. 1 2 3 4 Miller 2005.
  12. 1 2 Craig 2009b.
  13. 1 2 Craig, Robert (February 3, 2011). "Robert Craig Vita" (PDF). University of Colorado. Archived from the original (PDF) on June 12, 2010. Retrieved February 21, 2011.
  14. 1 2 Myers 2001.
  15. 1 2 Craig 2001.
  16. 1 2 3 Russill 2004.
  17. 1 2 Russill 2005.
  18. 1 2 Craig 2007.
  19. Donsback 2006.
  20. Penman 2000.
  21. Anderson & Baym 2004.
  22. Lindlof & Taylor 2002.
  23. D'Angelo 2002.
  24. Jimenez & Guillem 2009.
  25. Anderson 1996, pp. 200–201.
  26. Craig 1999, pp. 120.
  27. Craig 2006, pp. 13.
  28. Penman 2000, pp. 6.
  29. Craig 1999, pp. 132–146.
  30. Craig 1999, pp. 119–120.
  31. 1 2 3 4 5 Craig 1999, p. 121.
  32. Craig 1999, pp. 120–123.
  33. Craig 1999, pp. 123–125.
  34. Penman 2000, pp. 76.
  35. Craig 1999, pp. 126–127.
  36. Craig 1999, pp. 123–132.
  37. Anderson & Baym 2004, pp. 440.
  38. Craig 1999, pp. 132–134.
  39. Craig 1999, pp. 135–136.
  40. Craig 1999, pp. 136–138.
  41. Craig 1999, pp. 138–140.
  42. Craig 1999, pp. 141–142.
  43. Craig 1999, pp. 142–144.
  44. Craig 1999, pp. 144–146.
  45. Craig 1999, pp. 146–149.
  46. Craig 1999, pp. 133–134.
  47. Craig 1999, pp. 132, 133.
  48. Craig 1999, pp. 132, 134.
  49. Craig 1999, pp. 135–149.
  50. Craig 1999, pp. 149.
  51. Craig 1999, pp. 149, 151.
  52. Craig 1999, pp. 151.
  53. Myers 2001, pp. 219.
  54. Myers 2001, pp. 219–123, 226.
  55. Myers 2001, pp. 222–223.
  56. 1 2 Myers 2001, pp. 223–226.
  57. 1 2 Myers 2001, pp. 226.
  58. 1 2 Russill 2005, pp. 300.
  59. 1 2 Craig 2001, pp. 232.
  60. 1 2 Craig 2001, pp. 234.
  61. 1 2 3 Craig 2001, pp. 233.
  62. Craig 2001, pp. 234–235.
  63. Craig 2001, pp. 236.
  64. Craig 2001, pp. 236–237.
  65. Craig 2001, pp. 236, 238.
  66. 1 2 Craig 2001, pp. 237.
  67. Craig 2001, pp. 230.
  68. 1 2 3 4 5 6 Craig 2001, pp. 238.
  69. Craig 2007, pp. 125–126.
  70. Craig 2009a, pp. 7.
  71. 1 2 3 Craig 2007, pp. 126.
  72. 1 2 Russill 2004, pp. 281–282.
  73. Russill 2005, pp. 296–298.
  74. Craig 2009a.
  75. 1 2 3 Craig 2007, pp. 130.
  76. Russill 2004, pp. 282.
  77. 1 2 Russill 2004, pp. 281.
  78. Craig 2007, pp. 133.
  79. Russill 2004, pp. iii, 5, 68–105, 279–283.
  80. 1 2 3 Craig 2007, pp. 131.
  81. 1 2 Craig 2007, pp. 130–131.
  82. 1 2 Craig 2007, pp. 134.
  83. 1 2 Craig 2007, pp. 135.
  84. Craig 2007, pp. 135–137.

Related Research Articles

In analytic philosophy, anti-realism is a position which encompasses many varieties such as metaphysical, mathematical, semantic, scientific, moral and epistemic. The term was first articulated by British philosopher Michael Dummett in an argument against a form of realism Dummett saw as 'colorless reductionism'.

Epistemology is the branch of philosophy concerned with knowledge. Epistemologists study the nature, origin, and scope of knowledge, epistemic justification, the rationality of belief, and various related issues. Debates in (contemporary) epistemology are generally clustered around four core areas:

  1. The philosophical analysis of the nature of knowledge and the conditions required for a belief to constitute knowledge, such as truth and justification
  2. Potential sources of knowledge and justified belief, such as perception, reason, memory, and testimony
  3. The structure of a body of knowledge or justified belief, including whether all justified beliefs must be derived from justified foundational beliefs or whether justification requires only a coherent set of beliefs
  4. Philosophical skepticism, which questions the possibility of knowledge, and related problems, such as whether skepticism poses a threat to our ordinary knowledge claims and whether it is possible to refute skeptical arguments
<span class="mw-page-title-main">Pragmatism</span> Philosophical tradition

Pragmatism is a philosophical tradition that views language and thought as tools for prediction, problem solving, and action, rather than describing, representing, or mirroring reality. Pragmatists contend that most philosophical topics—such as the nature of knowledge, language, concepts, meaning, belief, and science—are all best viewed in terms of their practical uses and successes.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Richard Rorty</span> American philosopher

Richard McKay Rorty was an American philosopher. Educated at the University of Chicago and Yale University, he had strong interests and training in both the history of philosophy and in contemporary analytic philosophy. Rorty's academic career included appointments as the Stuart Professor of Philosophy at Princeton University, Kenan Professor of Humanities at the University of Virginia, and Professor of Comparative literature at Stanford University. Among his most influential books are Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (1979), Consequences of Pragmatism (1982), and Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (1989).

Within the realm of communication studies, organizational communication is a field of study surrounding all areas of communication and information flow that contribute to the functioning of an organization. Organizational communication is constantly evolving and as a result, the scope of organizations included in this field of research have also shifted over time. Now both traditionally profitable companies, as well as NGO's and non-profit organizations, are points of interest for scholars focused on the field of organizational communication. Organizations are formed and sustained through continuous communication between members of the organization and both internal and external sub-groups who possess shared objectives for the organization. The flow of communication encompasses internal and external stakeholders and can be formal or informal.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Communication theory</span> Proposed description of communication phenomena

Communication theory is a proposed description of communication phenomena, the relationships among them, a storyline describing these relationships, and an argument for these three elements. Communication theory provides a way of talking about and analyzing key events, processes, and commitments that together form communication. Theory can be seen as a way to map the world and make it navigable; communication theory gives us tools to answer empirical, conceptual, or practical communication questions.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Pragmaticism</span>

"Pragmaticism" is a term used by Charles Sanders Peirce for his pragmatic philosophy starting in 1905, in order to distance himself and it from pragmatism, the original name, which had been used in a manner he did not approve of in the "literary journals". Peirce in 1905 announced his coinage "pragmaticism", saying that it was "ugly enough to be safe from kidnappers". Today, outside of philosophy, "pragmatism" is often taken to refer to a compromise of aims or principles, even a ruthless search for mercenary advantage. Peirce gave other or more specific reasons for the distinction in a surviving draft letter that year and in later writings. Peirce's pragmatism, that is, pragmaticism, differed in Peirce's view from other pragmatisms by its commitments to the spirit of strict logic, the immutability of truth, the reality of infinity, and the difference between (1) actively willing to control thought, to doubt, to weigh reasons, and (2) willing not to exert the will, willing to believe. In his view his pragmatism is, strictly speaking, not itself a whole philosophy, but instead a general method for the clarification of ideas. He first publicly formulated his pragmatism as an aspect of scientific logic along with principles of statistics and modes of inference in his "Illustrations of the Logic of Science" series of articles in 1877-8.

A pragmatic theory of truth is a theory of truth within the philosophies of pragmatism and pragmaticism. Pragmatic theories of truth were first posited by Charles Sanders Peirce, William James, and John Dewey. The common features of these theories are a reliance on the pragmatic maxim as a means of clarifying the meanings of difficult concepts such as truth; and an emphasis on the fact that belief, certainty, knowledge, or truth is the result of an inquiry.

Neopragmatism, sometimes called post-Deweyan pragmatism, linguistic pragmatism, or analytic pragmatism, is the philosophical tradition that infers that the meaning of words is a result of how they are used, rather than the objects they represent.

Standpoint theory, or standpoint epistemology, is a theory for analyzing inter-subjective discourses. Standpoint theory proposes that authority is rooted in individuals’ personal knowledge and perspectives and the power that such authority exerts.

Metaepistemology is the branch of epistemology and metaphilosophy that studies the underlying assumptions made in debates in epistemology, including those concerning the existence and authority of epistemic facts and reasons, the nature and aim of epistemology, and the methodology of epistemology.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Stephen Neale</span> British philosopher

Stephen Roy Albert Neale is a British philosopher and specialist in the philosophy of language who has written extensively about meaning, information, interpretation, and communication, and more generally about issues at the intersection of philosophy and linguistics. Neale is a Distinguished Professor of Philosophy and Linguistics and holder of the John H. Kornblith Family Chair in the Philosophy of Science and Values at the Graduate Center, City University of New York (CUNY).

Richard Shusterman is an American pragmatist philosopher. Known for his contributions to philosophical aesthetics and the emerging field of somaesthetics, currently he is the Dorothy F. Schmidt Eminent Scholar in the Humanities and Professor of Philosophy at Florida Atlantic University.

The B-theory of time, also called the "tenseless theory of time", is one of two positions regarding the temporal ordering of events in the philosophy of time. B-theorists argue that the flow of time is only a subjective illusion of human consciousness, that the past, present, and future are equally real, and that time is tenseless: temporal becoming is not an objective feature of reality. Therefore, there is nothing privileged about the present, ontologically speaking.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Richard J. Bernstein</span> American philosopher (1932–2022)

Richard Jacob Bernstein was an American philosopher who taught for many years at Haverford College and then at The New School for Social Research, where he was Vera List Professor of Philosophy. Bernstein wrote extensively about a broad array of issues and philosophical traditions including American pragmatism, neopragmatism, critical theory, deconstruction, social philosophy, political philosophy, and hermeneutics.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Robert B. Talisse</span> American philosopher and political theorist

Robert B. Talisse is an American philosopher and political theorist. He is currently Professor of Philosophy and Chair of the Philosophy Department at Vanderbilt University in Nashville, Tennessee, where he is also a Professor of Political Science. Talisse is a former editor of the academic journal Public Affairs Quarterly, and a regular contributor to the blog 3 Quarks Daily, where he posts a monthly column with his frequent co-author and fellow Vanderbilt philosopher Scott Aikin. He earned his PhD in Philosophy from the Graduate Center of the City University of New York in 2001. His principal area of research is political philosophy, with an emphasis on democratic theory and liberalism.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Robert T. Craig</span> American academic (born 1947)

Robert T. Craig is an American communication theorist from the University of Colorado, Boulder who received his BA in Speech at the University of Wisconsin–Madison, and his MA and PhD in communication from Michigan State University. Craig was on the 1988 founding board of the journal "Research on Language and Social Interaction," a position he continues to hold. From 1991 to 1993 Craig was the founding editor of the International Communication Association journal "Communication Theory" which has been in continuous publication since 1991. He is currently the editor for the ICA Handbook series. In 2009 Craig was elected as a Lifetime Fellow for the International Communication Association, an organization he was president for in 2004–2005.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Pragmatic ethics</span> Theory of normative philosophical ethics and meta-ethics

Pragmatic ethics is a theory of normative philosophical ethics and meta-ethics. Ethical pragmatists such as John Dewey believe that some societies have progressed morally in much the way they have attained progress in science. Scientists can pursue inquiry into the truth of a hypothesis and accept the hypothesis, in the sense that they act as though the hypothesis were true; nonetheless, they think that future generations can advance science, and thus future generations can refine or replace their accepted hypotheses. Similarly, ethical pragmatists think that norms, principles, and moral criteria are likely to be improved as a result of inquiry.

<i>The Self Awakened</i>

The Self Awakened: Pragmatism Unbound is a 2007 book by philosopher and politician Roberto Mangabeira Unger. In the book, Unger sets forth a theory of human nature, a philosophical view of time, nature and reality, and a proposal for changes to social and political institutions so that they best nourish the context-transcending quality that Unger sees at the core of human existence. Written in a prophetic and poetic manner that drew comparison with the work of Whitman and Emerson, and delving into issues of humankind's existential predicament in a manner that one critic found evocative of Sartre, The Self Awakened also serves as a summation of many of the core principles of Unger's work.

Scott F. Aikin is an American philosopher and assistant professor of philosophy at Vanderbilt University in Nashville, Tennessee, where he also holds a joint appointment in Classics. He earned an M.A. in philosophy from the University of Montana in 1999 and a Ph.D. in philosophy from Vanderbilt University in 2006. His principal areas of research are epistemology, argumentation theory, ancient philosophy, and pragmatism.

References