Nim

Last updated
Nim
NimGame.svg
Matches set up in rows for a game of Nim. Players take turns to choose a row and remove any number of matches from it.
Genres Mathematical game
Abstract strategy game
Players2
ChanceNone

Nim is a mathematical game of strategy in which two players take turns removing (or "nimming") objects from distinct heaps or piles. On each turn, a player must remove at least one object, and may remove any number of objects provided they all come from the same heap or pile. Depending on the version being played, the goal of the game is either to avoid taking the last object or to take the last object.

Contents

Variants of nim have been played since ancient times. [1] The game is said to have originated in China—it closely resembles the Chinese game of 捡石子 jiǎn-shízi, or "picking stones" [2] —but the origin is uncertain; the earliest European references to nim are from the beginning of the 16th century. Its current name was coined by Charles L. Bouton of Harvard University, who also developed the complete theory of the game in 1901, [3] but the origins of the name were never fully explained. The Oxford English Dictionary derives the name from the German verb nimm , meaning "take".

Nim is typically played as a misère game , in which the player to take the last object loses. Nim can also be played as a "normal play" game whereby the player taking the last object wins. In either normal play or a misère game, when there is exactly one heap with at least two objects, the player who takes next can easily win. If this removes either all or all but one objects from the heap that has two or more, then no heaps will have more than one object, so the players are forced to alternate removing exactly one object until the game ends. If the player leaves an even number of non-zero heaps (as the player would do in normal play), the player takes last; if the player leaves an odd number of heaps (as the player would do in misère play), then the other player takes last.

Normal-play nim (or more precisely the system of nimbers) is fundamental to the Sprague–Grundy theorem, which essentially says that in normal play every impartial game is equivalent to a nim heap that yields the same outcome when played in parallel with other normal play impartial games (see disjunctive sum).

While all normal-play impartial games can be assigned a nim value, that is not the case under the misère convention. Only tame games can be played using the same strategy as misère nim.

Nim is a special case of a poset game where the poset consists of disjoint chains (the heaps).

The evolution graph of the game of nim with three heaps is the same as three branches of the evolution graph of the Ulam-Warburton automaton. [4]

At the 1939 New York World's Fair Westinghouse displayed a machine, the Nimatron, that played nim. [5] From May 11, 1940, to October 27, 1940, only a few people were able to beat the machine in that six-month period; if they did, they were presented with a coin that said "Nim Champ". [6] [7] [ failed verification ] [8] [ failed verification ][ unreliable source? ] It was also one of the first-ever electronic computerized games. Ferranti built a nim-playing computer which was displayed at the Festival of Britain in 1951. In 1952 Herbert Koppel, Eugene Grant and Howard Bailer, engineers from the W. L. Maxon Corporation, developed a machine weighing 23 kilograms (50 lb) which played nim against a human opponent and regularly won. [9] A nim playing machine has been described made from tinkertoys. [10]

The game of nim was the subject of Martin Gardner's February 1958 Mathematical Games column in Scientific American. A version of nim is played—and has symbolic importance—in the French New Wave film Last Year at Marienbad (1961). [11]

Game play and illustration

The normal game is between two players and is played with three heaps of any number of objects. The two players alternate taking any number of objects from any one of the heaps. The goal is to be the last to take an object. In misère play, the goal is instead to ensure that the opponent is forced to take the last remaining object.

The following example of a normal game is played between fictional players Bob and Alice, who start with heaps of three, four and five objects.

Heap AHeap BHeap CMove
345Game begins
145Bob takes 2 from A
142Alice takes 3 from C
132Bob takes 1 from B
122Alice takes 1 from B
022Bob takes entire A heap, leaving two 2s
012Alice takes 1 from B
011Bob takes 1 from C leaving two 1s. (In misère play he would take 2 from C leaving (0, 1, 0).)
001Alice takes 1 from B
000Bob takes entire C heap and wins

Winning positions

The practical strategy to win at the game of nim is for a player to get the other into one of the following positions, and every successive turn afterwards they should be able to make one of the smaller positions. Only the last move changes between misère and normal play.

2 heaps3 heaps4 heaps
1 1 *1 1 1 **1 1 1 1 *
2 21 2 31 1 n n
3 31 4 51 2 4 7
4 41 6 71 2 5 6
5 51 8 91 3 4 6
6 62 4 61 3 5 7
7 72 5 72 3 4 5
8 83 4 72 3 6 7
9 93 5 62 3 8 9
n n4 8 124 5 6 7
4 9 134 5 8 9
5 8 13nnmm
5 9 12nnnn
* Only valid for normal play.
** Only valid for misère.

For the generalisations, n and m can be any value > 0, and they may be the same.

Mathematical theory

Nim has been mathematically solved for any number of initial heaps and objects, and there is an easily calculated way to determine which player will win and which winning moves are open to that player.

The key to the theory of the game is the binary digital sum of the heap sizes, i.e., the sum (in binary), neglecting all carries from one digit to another. This operation is also known as "bitwise xor" or "vector addition over GF(2)" (bitwise addition modulo 2). Within combinatorial game theory it is usually called the nim-sum, as it will be called here. The nim-sum of x and y is written xy to distinguish it from the ordinary sum, x + y. An example of the calculation with heaps of size 3, 4, and 5 is as follows:

 Binary Decimal     0112    310    Heap A   1002    410    Heap B   1012    510    Heap C   ---   0102    210    The nim-sum of heaps A, B, and C, 3 ⊕ 4 ⊕ 5 = 2

An equivalent procedure, which is often easier to perform mentally, is to express the heap sizes as sums of distinct powers of 2, cancel pairs of equal powers, and then add what is left:

3 = 0 + 2 + 1 =     2   1      Heap A 4 = 4 + 0 + 0 = 4              Heap B 5 = 4 + 0 + 1 = 4       1      Heap C -------------------------------------------------------------------- 2 =                 2          What is left after canceling 1s and 4s

In normal play, the winning strategy is to finish every move with a nim-sum of 0. This is always possible if the nim-sum is not zero before the move. If the nim-sum is zero, then the next player will lose if the other player does not make a mistake. To find out which move to make, let X be the nim-sum of all the heap sizes. Find a heap where the nim-sum of X and heap-size is less than the heap-size; the winning strategy is to play in such a heap, reducing that heap to the nim-sum of its original size with X. In the example above, taking the nim-sum of the sizes is X = 3 ⊕ 4 ⊕ 5 = 2. The nim-sums of the heap sizes A=3, B=4, and C=5 with X=2 are

AX = 3 ⊕ 2 = 1 [Since (011) ⊕ (010) = 001 ]
BX = 4 ⊕ 2 = 6
CX = 5 ⊕ 2 = 7

The only heap that is reduced is heap A, so the winning move is to reduce the size of heap A to 1 (by removing two objects).

As a particular simple case, if there are only two heaps left, the strategy is to reduce the number of objects in the bigger heap to make the heaps equal. After that, no matter what move your opponent makes, you can make the same move on the other heap, guaranteeing that you take the last object.

When played as a misère game, Nim strategy is different only when the normal play move would leave only heaps of size one. In that case, the correct move is to leave an odd number of heaps of size one (in normal play, the correct move would be to leave an even number of such heaps).

These strategies for normal play and a misère game are the same until the number of heaps with at least two objects is exactly equal to one. At that point, the next player removes either all objects (or all but one) from the heap that has two or more, so no heaps will have more than one object (in other words, so all remaining heaps have exactly one object each), so the players are forced to alternate removing exactly one object until the game ends. In normal play, the player leaves an even number of non-zero heaps, so the same player takes last; in misère play, the player leaves an odd number of non-zero heaps, so the other player takes last.

In a misère game with heaps of sizes three, four and five, the strategy would be applied like this:

A B C nim-sum    3 4 5 0102=210   I take 2 from A, leaving a sum of 000, so I will win. 1 4 5 0002=010   You take 2 from C 1 4 3 1102=610   I take 2 from B 1 2 3 0002=010   You take 1 from C 1 2 2 0012=110   I take 1 from A 0 2 2 0002=010   You take 1 from C 0 2 1 0112=310   The normal play strategy would be to take 1 from B, leaving an even number (2)                  heaps of size 1.  For misère play, I take the entire B heap, to leave an odd                  number (1) of heaps of size 1. 0 0 1 0012=110   You take 1 from C, and lose.

Proof of the winning formula

The soundness of the optimal strategy described above was demonstrated by C. Bouton.

Theorem. In a normal nim game, the player making the first move has a winning strategy if and only if the nim-sum of the sizes of the heaps is not zero. Otherwise, the second player has a winning strategy.

Proof: Notice that the nim-sum (⊕) obeys the usual associative and commutative laws of addition (+) and also satisfies an additional property, x  x = 0.

Let x1, ..., xn be the sizes of the heaps before a move, and y1, ..., yn the corresponding sizes after a move. Let s = x1  ...  xn and t = y1  ...  yn. If the move was in heap k, we have xi = yi for all ik, and xk > yk. By the properties of ⊕ mentioned above, we have

t = 0 ⊕ t       = sst       = s ⊕ (x1 ⊕ ... ⊕ xn) ⊕ (y1 ⊕ ... ⊕ yn)       = s ⊕ (x1y1) ⊕ ... ⊕ (xnyn)       = s ⊕ 0 ⊕ ... ⊕ 0 ⊕ (xkyk) ⊕ 0 ⊕ ... ⊕ 0       = sxkyk  (*) t = sxkyk.

The theorem follows by induction on the length of the game from these two lemmas.

Lemma 1. If s = 0, then t ≠ 0 no matter what move is made.

Proof: If there is no possible move, then the lemma is vacuously true (and the first player loses the normal play game by definition). Otherwise, any move in heap k will produce t = xk  yk from (*). This number is nonzero, since xk  yk.

Lemma 2. If s ≠ 0, it is possible to make a move so that t = 0.

Proof: Let d be the position of the leftmost (most significant) nonzero bit in the binary representation of s, and choose k such that the dth bit of xk is also nonzero. (Such a k must exist, since otherwise the dth bit of s would be 0.) Then letting yk = s  xk, we claim that yk < xk: all bits to the left of d are the same in xk and yk, bit d decreases from 1 to 0 (decreasing the value by 2d), and any change in the remaining bits will amount to at most 2d−1. The first player can thus make a move by taking xk  yk objects from heap k, then

t = sxkyk           (by (*))   = sxk ⊕ (sxk)   = 0.

The modification for misère play is demonstrated by noting that the modification first arises in a position that has only one heap of size 2 or more. Notice that in such a position s ≠ 0, and therefore this situation has to arise when it is the turn of the player following the winning strategy. The normal play strategy is for the player to reduce this to size 0 or 1, leaving an even number of heaps with size 1, and the misère strategy is to do the opposite. From that point on, all moves are forced.

Variations

The subtraction game

Interactive subtraction game: Players take turns removing 1, 2 or 3 objects from an initial pool of 21 objects. The player taking the last object wins. Subtraction game SMIL.svg
Interactive subtraction game: Players take turns removing 1, 2 or 3 objects from an initial pool of 21 objects. The player taking the last object wins.

In another game which is commonly known as nim (but is better called the subtraction game), an upper bound is imposed on the number of objects that can be removed in a turn. Instead of removing arbitrarily many objects, a player can only remove 1 or 2 or ... or k at a time. This game is commonly played in practice with only one heap.

Bouton's analysis carries over easily to the general multiple-heap version of this game. The only difference is that as a first step, before computing the nim-sums we must reduce the sizes of the heaps modulo k + 1. If this makes all the heaps of size zero (in misère play), the winning move is to take k objects from one of the heaps. In particular, in ideal play from a single heap of n objects, the second player can win if and only if

0 = n (mod k + 1) (in normal play), or
1 = n (mod k + 1) (in misère play).

This follows from calculating the nim-sequence of S(1, 2, ..., k),

from which the strategy above follows by the Sprague–Grundy theorem.

The 21 game

The game "21" is played as a misère game with any number of players who take turns saying a number. The first player says "1" and each player in turn increases the number by 1, 2, or 3, but may not exceed 21; the player forced to say "21" loses. This can be modeled as a subtraction game with a heap of 21–n objects. The winning strategy for the two-player version of this game is to always say a multiple of 4; it is then guaranteed that the other player will ultimately have to say 21; so in the standard version, wherein the first player opens with "1", they start with a losing move.

The 21 game can also be played with different numbers, e.g., "Add at most 5; lose on 34".

A sample game of 21 in which the second player follows the winning strategy:

Player     Number   1           1   2           4   1        5, 6 or 7   2           8   1       9, 10 or 11   2          12   1      13, 14 or 15   2          16   1      17, 18 or 19   2          20   1          21

The 100 game

A similar version is the "100 game": Two players start from 0 and alternately add a number from 1 to 10 to the sum. The player who reaches 100 wins. The winning strategy is to reach a number in which the digits are subsequent (e.g., 01, 12, 23, 34,...) and control the game by jumping through all the numbers of this sequence. Once a player reaches 89, the opponent can only choose numbers from 90 to 99, and the next answer can in any case be 100.

A multiple-heap rule

In another variation of nim, besides removing any number of objects from a single heap, one is permitted to remove the same number of objects from each heap.

Circular nim

Yet another variation of nim is 'circular nim', wherein any number of objects are placed in a circle and two players alternately remove one, two or three adjacent objects. For example, starting with a circle of ten objects,

. . . . . . . . . .

three objects are taken in the first move

_ . . . . . . . _ _

then another three

_ . _ _ _ . . . _ _

then one

_ . _ _ _ . . _ _ _

but then three objects cannot be taken out in one move.

Grundy's game

In Grundy's game, another variation of nim, a number of objects are placed in an initial heap and two players alternately divide a heap into two nonempty heaps of different sizes. Thus, six objects may be divided into piles of 5+1 or 4+2, but not 3+3. Grundy's game can be played as either misère or normal play.

Greedy nim

Greedy nim is a variation wherein the players are restricted to choosing stones from only the largest pile. [12] It is a finite impartial game. Greedy nim misère has the same rules as greedy nim, but the last player able to make a move loses.

Let the largest number of stones in a pile be m and the second largest number of stones in a pile be n. Let pm be the number of piles having m stones and pn be the number of piles having n stones. Then there is a theorem that game positions with pm even are P positions. [13] This theorem can be shown by considering the positions where pm is odd. If pm is larger than 1, all stones may be removed from this pile to reduce pm by 1 and the new pm will be even. If pm = 1 (i.e. the largest heap is unique), there are two cases:

Thus, there exists a move to a state where pm is even. Conversely, if pm is even, if any move is possible (pm ≠ 0), then it must take the game to a state where pm is odd. The final position of the game is even (pm = 0). Hence, each position of the game with pm even must be a P position.

Index-k nim

A generalization of multi-heap nim was called "nim" or "index-k" nim by E. H. Moore, [14] who analyzed it in 1910. In index-k nim, instead of removing objects from only one heap, players can remove objects from at least one but up to k different heaps. The number of elements that may be removed from each heap may be either arbitrary or limited to at most r elements, like in the "subtraction game" above.

The winning strategy is as follows: Like in ordinary multi-heap nim, one considers the binary representation of the heap sizes (or heap sizes modulo r + 1). In ordinary nim one forms the XOR-sum (or sum modulo 2) of each binary digit, and the winning strategy is to make each XOR sum zero. In the generalization to index-k nim, one forms the sum of each binary digit modulo k + 1.

Again the winning strategy is to move such that this sum is zero for every digit. Indeed, the value thus computed is zero for the final position, and given a configuration of heaps for which this value is zero, any change of at most k heaps will make the value non-zero. Conversely, given a configuration with non-zero value, one can always take from at most k heaps, carefully chosen, so that the value will become zero.

Building nim

Building nim is a variant of nim wherein the two players first construct the game of nim. Given n stones and s empty piles, the players, alternating turns, place exactly one stone into a pile of their choice. [15] Once all the stones are placed, a game of Nim begins, starting with the next player that would move. This game is denoted BN(n,s).

Higher-dimensional nim

n-d nim is played on a board, whereon any number of continuous pieces can be removed from any hyper-row. The starting position is usually the full board, but other options are allowed. [16]

Graph nim

The starting board is a disconnected graph, and players take turns to remove adjacent vertices. [17]

Candy nim

Candy nim is a version of normal-play nim in which players try to achieve two goals at the same time: taking the last object (in this case, candy) and taking the maximum number of candies by the end of the game. [18]

See also

Related Research Articles

Sprouts is an impartial paper-and-pencil game which can be analyzed for its mathematical properties. It was invented by mathematicians John Horton Conway and Michael S. Paterson at Cambridge University in the early 1960s. The setup is even simpler than the popular Dots and Boxes game, but gameplay develops much more artistically and organically.

In combinatorial game theory, the Sprague–Grundy theorem states that every impartial game under the normal play convention is equivalent to a one-heap game of nim, or to an infinite generalization of nim. It can therefore be represented as a natural number, the size of the heap in its equivalent game of nim, as an ordinal number in the infinite generalization, or alternatively as a nimber, the value of that one-heap game in an algebraic system whose addition operation combines multiple heaps to form a single equivalent heap in nim.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">TacTix</span> Two-player strategy game invented by Danish polymath Piet Hein

TacTix is a two-player strategy game invented by Piet Hein, a poet well known for dabbling in math and science, best known for his game Hex.

In combinatorial game theory, an impartial game is a game in which the allowable moves depend only on the position and not on which of the two players is currently moving, and where the payoffs are symmetric. In other words, the only difference between player 1 and player 2 is that player 1 goes first. The game is played until a terminal position is reached. A terminal position is one from which no moves are possible. Then one of the players is declared the winner and the other the loser. Furthermore, impartial games are played with perfect information and no chance moves, meaning all information about the game and operations for both players are visible to both players.

In mathematics, the nimbers, also called Grundy numbers, are introduced in combinatorial game theory, where they are defined as the values of heaps in the game Nim. The nimbers are the ordinal numbers endowed with nimber addition and nimber multiplication, which are distinct from ordinal addition and ordinal multiplication.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Combinatorial game theory</span> Branch of game theory about two-player sequential games with perfect information

Combinatorial game theory is a branch of mathematics and theoretical computer science that typically studies sequential games with perfect information. Study has been largely confined to two-player games that have a position that the players take turns changing in defined ways or moves to achieve a defined winning condition. Combinatorial game theory has not traditionally studied games of chance or those that use imperfect or incomplete information, favoring games that offer perfect information in which the state of the game and the set of available moves is always known by both players. However, as mathematical techniques advance, the types of game that can be mathematically analyzed expands, thus the boundaries of the field are ever changing. Scholars will generally define what they mean by a "game" at the beginning of a paper, and these definitions often vary as they are specific to the game being analyzed and are not meant to represent the entire scope of the field.

Hexapawn is a deterministic two-player game invented by Martin Gardner. It is played on a rectangular board of variable size, for example on a 3×3 board or on a regular chessboard. On a board of size n×m, each player begins with m pawns, one for each square in the row closest to them. The goal of each player is to either advance a pawn to the opposite end of the board or leave the other player with no legal moves, either by stalemate or by having all of their pieces captured.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Chomp</span> Abstract strategy game

Chomp is a two-player strategy game played on a rectangular grid made up of smaller square cells, which can be thought of as the blocks of a chocolate bar. The players take it in turns to choose one block and "eat it", together with those that are below it and to its right. The top left block is "poisoned" and the player who eats this loses.

In the mathematics of combinatorial games, the sum or disjunctive sum of two games is a game in which the two games are played in parallel, with each player being allowed to move in just one of the games per turn. The sum game finishes when there are no moves left in either of the two parallel games, at which point the last player to move wins. This operation may be extended to disjunctive sums of any number of games, again by playing the games in parallel and moving in exactly one of the games per turn. It is the fundamental operation that is used in the Sprague–Grundy theorem for impartial games and which led to the field of combinatorial game theory for partisan games.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Wythoff's game</span> Two-player mathematical subtraction game

Wythoff's game is a two-player mathematical subtraction game, played with two piles of counters. Players take turns removing counters from one or both piles; when removing counters from both piles, the numbers of counters removed from each pile must be equal. The game ends when one player removes the last counter or counters, thus winning.

Subtract-a-square is a two-player mathematical subtraction game. It is played by two people with a pile of coins between them. The players take turns removing coins from the pile, always removing a non-zero square number of coins. The game is usually played as a normal play game, which means that the player who removes the last coin wins. It is an impartial game, meaning that the set of moves available from any position does not depend on whose turn it is. Solomon W. Golomb credits the invention of this game to Richard A. Epstein.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Grundy's game</span> Mathematical game

Grundy's game is a two-player mathematical game of strategy. The starting configuration is a single heap of objects, and the two players take turn splitting a single heap into two heaps of different sizes. The game ends when only heaps of size two and smaller remain, none of which can be split unequally. The game is usually played as a normal play game, which means that the last person who can make an allowed move wins.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Kayles</span> Mathematical game

Kayles is a simple impartial game in combinatorial game theory, invented by Henry Dudeney in 1908. Given a row of imagined bowling pins, players take turns to knock out either one pin, or two adjacent pins, until all the pins are gone. Using the notation of octal games, Kayles is denoted 0.77.

The octal games are a class of two-player games that involve removing tokens from heaps of tokens. They have been studied in combinatorial game theory as a generalization of Nim, Kayles, and similar games.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Cram (game)</span>

Cram is a mathematical game played on a sheet of graph paper. It is the impartial version of Domineering and the only difference in the rules is that players may place their dominoes in either orientation, but it results in a very different game. It has been called by many names, including "plugg" by Geoffrey Mott-Smith, and "dots-and-pairs". Cram was popularized by Martin Gardner in Scientific American.

In the mathematical theory of games, genus theory in impartial games is a theory by which some games played under the misère play convention can be analysed, to predict the outcome class of games.

In combinatorial game theory, and particularly in the theory of impartial games in misère play, an indistinguishability quotient is a commutative monoid that generalizes and localizes the Sprague–Grundy theorem for a specific game's rule set.

In combinatorial game theory, poset games are mathematical games of strategy, generalizing many well-known games such as Nim and Chomp. In such games, two players start with a poset, and take turns choosing one point in the poset, removing it and all points that are greater. The player who is left with no point to choose, loses.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Fibonacci nim</span> Game of taking coins from a pile

Fibonacci nim is a mathematical subtraction game, a variant of the game of nim. Players alternate removing coins from a pile, on each move taking at most twice as many coins as the previous move, and winning by taking the last coin. The Fibonacci numbers feature heavily in its analysis; in particular, the first player can win if and only if the starting number of coins is not a Fibonacci number. A complete strategy is known for best play in games with a single pile of counters, but not for variants of the game with multiple piles.

In combinatorial game theory, a subtraction game is an abstract strategy game whose state can be represented by a natural number or vector of numbers and in which the allowed moves reduce these numbers. Often, the moves of the game allow any number to be reduced by subtracting a value from a specified subtraction set, and different subtraction games vary in their subtraction sets. These games also vary in whether the last player to move wins or loses. Another winning convention that has also been used is that a player who moves to a position with all numbers zero wins, but that any other position with no moves possible is a draw.

References

  1. Jorgensen, Anker Helms (2009), "Context and driving forces in the development of the early computer game Nimbi", IEEE Annals of the History of Computing, 31 (3): 44–53, doi:10.1109/MAHC.2009.41, MR   2767447, S2CID   2833693, The two-person mathematical game nim, which many believe originated in China, is probably one of the oldest games in the world.
  2. Yaglom, I. M. (2001), "Two games with matchsticks", in Tabachnikov, Serge (ed.), Kvant Selecta: Combinatorics, I, Volume 1, Mathematical world, vol. 17, American Mathematical Society, pp. 1–8, ISBN   9780821821718
  3. Bouton, C. L. (1901–1902), "Nim, a game with a complete mathematical theory", Annals of Mathematics , 3 (14): 35–39, doi:10.2307/1967631, JSTOR   1967631
  4. Khovanova, Tanya; Xiong, Joshua (2014). "Nim Fractals". arXiv: 1405.5942 [math.CO].
  5. Flesch, Rudolf (1951). The Art of Clear Thinking. New York: Harper and Brothers Publishers. p. 3.
  6. Kellem, Betsy (2022-03-01). "The Nimatron". JSTOR Daily. Archived from the original on 2023-06-28. Retrieved 2023-06-28.
  7. "ExpoMuseum / New York World's Fair, 1939-'40". www.expomuseum.com. Archived from the original on 24 February 2021. Retrieved 20 April 2018.
  8. "1940: Nimatron". platinumpiotr.blogspot.com. Retrieved 20 April 2018.
  9. Grant, Eugene F.; Lardner, Rex (August 2, 1952). "The Talk of the Town – It". The New Yorker .
  10. Cohen, Harvey A. "How to Construct NIM Playing Machine" (PDF).
  11. Morrissette, Bruce (1968), "Games and game structures in Robbe-Grillet", Yale French Studies (41): 159–167, doi:10.2307/2929672, JSTOR   2929672 . Morrissette writes that Alain Robbe-Grillet, one of the screenwriters for the film, "thought he had invented" the game.
  12. Winning Ways for your Mathematical Plays. Vol. 4 vols. (2nd ed.). A K Peters Ltd. 2001.; Berlekamp, Elwyn R.; Conway, John Horton; Guy, Richard K. (2003-06-15). vol. 1. ISBN   978-1-56881-130-7.; Berlekamp, Elwyn R.; Conway, John Horton; Guy, Richard K. (2003-06-15). vol. 2. ISBN   978-1-56881-142-0.; Berlekamp, Elwyn R.; Conway, John Horton; Guy, Richard K. (2003-06-15). vol. 3. ISBN   978-1-56881-143-7.; Berlekamp, Elwyn R.; Conway, John Horton; Guy, Richard K. (2004-06-15). vol. 4. ISBN   978-1-56881-144-4.
  13. M H Albert, R. J. Nowakowski (2004). "Nim Restrictions" (PDF). Integers: 2.
  14. Moore, E. H. A Generalization of the Game Called Nim. Annals of Mathematics 11 (3), 1910, pp. 93–94
  15. Larsson, Urban; Heubach, Silvia; Dufour, Matthieu; Duchêne, Eric (2015). "Building Nim". arXiv: 1502.04068 [cs.DM].
  16. "1021 - 2D-Nim". Poj.org. Retrieved 2019-01-09.
  17. Erickson, Lindsay Anne (2011). "The Game of Nim on Graphs". North Dakota State University.
  18. Rubinstein-Salzedo, Simon (18 May 2018). "P Play in Candy Nim". arXiv: 1805.07019 [math.CO].

Further reading