Mark Johnston (philosopher)

Last updated
Photo of Mark Johnston MarkJohnston.jpg
Photo of Mark Johnston

Mark Johnston is an Australian-born philosopher working at Princeton University. [1]

Contents

Biography and career

In 1980, after his undergraduate degree at the University of Melbourne, Johnston came to Princeton University to work with Saul Kripke and David Lewis, arguably the two most influential anglophone philosophers in the late 20th century. Under their supervision he completed his dissertation Particulars and Persistence in 1984. [2] He became an assistant professor at Princeton in 1984, received tenure there in 1987, and became a full professor in 1991. From 2005-2015 he was the Walter Cerf Professor of Philosophy. [3] He is presently Henry Putnam University Professor at Princeton University. [4]

Johnston has been a visiting professor at the Australian National University, Monash University, Melbourne University, New York University and U.C. Berkeley. His distinguished invited lectureships include the Presidential Lectureship at the University of Southern California (1993), the Kolnai Lectureship at The Central European University (1997), the Presidential Lectureship at Reed College, (2002) and the Brackenridge Lectureship, University of Texas (2017).  He was the Carl Gustav Hempel Lecturer at Princeton University (2006), [5] the Gareth Evans Memorial Lecturer at Oxford University (2017), [6] the Gifford Lecturer at the University of St Andrews (2019), [7] the Townsend Lecturer at U.C. Berkeley (2019) [8] and the Stanton Lecturer at the University of Cambridge (2023). [9] In January 2024, he will deliver the Romanell lecture at the Eastern Division of the American Philosophical Association in New York City. [10]

Johnston’s awards include the Governors Prize in the Humanities, [11] the Pew Charitable Trust Award, the American Academy of Religion Award for Excellence, [12] the Prose Award for Scholarly Excellence from the American Scholarly Editors, the Marc Sanders Award, the Behrman Award for Distinguished Achievement in the Humanities, [11] and the American Philosophical Association’s Romanell Prize. [10] The literary critic James Wood in New Yorker Magazine named Johnston’s book Saving God as a top non-fiction book of 2009. [13] The Boston Review listed his “Is Life a Ponzi Scheme?” a favorite essay of 2014.

Academic Work

Though he first published in formal logic, working on a general solution to the reflexive paradoxes, [14] over his career Johnston has gone on to make influential contributions in a wide range of fields including ontology, cognitive science, philosophy of mind, epistemology, religion, value theory and the ethics of investing. [15]

Johnston is known for (i) deflating the significance of the method of cases for philosophy, pointing to just how the empirical psychological theory of concepts undermines conceptual analysis as an interesting way for philosophy to proceed, [16] [17] (ii) emphasizing the authority of affect, [18] (iii) explaining the straightforward coherence of wishful thinking and self-deception, [19] (iv) offering the idea of response-independence as a measure of the objectivity of a discourse, [20] [21] (v) proposing an account of object perception as the presentation of external objects in a sensory-motor field, prior to the entertaining of truth evaluable perceptual contents, [22] [23] [24] [25] [26] [27] (vi) introducing the original, pre-Lewisian distinction between perduring and enduring, [2] developing a distinctive partial endurance account of identity over time for those persisting material things that are not "ontological trash," [28] (viii) examining the prospects of relativism about the self, [29] [30] (ix) providing a straightforward account of constitution as the relation between a thing and its dependent parts, [31] [32] (x) developing a general account of hylomorphism in terms of Nelson Goodman’s idea of relations that generate, [33] arguing that Nelson Goodman and Harry S. Leonard’s widely accepted mereology [34] does not provide the general theory of the part-whole relation, but only characterizes the simplest and most trivial wholes, the mereological sums, [35] (xi) developing both the so-called “personite” and other fellow-traveler worries problems [36] [37] for reductive accounts of personal survival, and the remnant person problem for the view that we are essentially animals. [38]

In a recent work—On the Basis of Morality: Will in a World of Species-Relative Value—Johnston has addressed the question of the ground of moral status, claiming that to be able to be morally wronged one need not be a full moral agent, but merely a conscious valuer of value, i.e., a will capable of acting to secure species-relative values presented by way of valenced modes of conscious presentation. In that sense he takes us to be on a par with many of the other animals. Herein, he suggests, also lies the hint to the solution of the personite problem and its troubling “animalite” variant. Johnston maintains that we, and the other animals that are moral subjects capable of being wronged, are embodied wills. Wills endure, while their embodiments are ontologically trashy perdurers. Reductionists about personal identity over time, such as Derek Parfit in Reasons and Persons miss the very enduring thing, an individual will, that makes ethical life workable, Johnston argues.

Johnston’s books Saving God (Princeton University Press 2009) and Surviving Death (Princeton University Press 2010) surprised his fellow philosophers, since until they appeared Johnston had been known as the “philosopher’s philosopher” someone pursuing intricate philosophical issues without regard for their public impact—as his then colleague Anthony Appiah put it, when introducing the second of Johnston’s Hempel Lectures (2006). Of Saving God, Jeffrey Stout wrote "This book is a brilliantly conceived contribution to natural theology. Taken together with Johnston's forthcoming Surviving Death, it constitutes the most interesting and provocative elaboration of religious naturalism since Santayana". [39] Writing in The Australian Review of Books C.A.J. Coady remarked “Saving God: Religion after Idolatry is an astonishing book. Its surprise consists in its topic, style, passion, range of religious and philosophical scholarship, and its daring blend of human depth and philosophical originality.” [40] Of Surviving Death, Jacques Berlinerblau, writing in the Chronicle of Higher Education remarked “Johnston reveals himself to be an engaging wit, a swaggering polymath…and, above all, a major talent.” [41] Michael Forster observed "This outstanding book presents original and indeed brave views on a broad range of issues that are of compelling significance not only to philosophers but also to thinking people more generally. The argument proceeds with great subtlety and sophistication and shows a masterful grasp of philosophy, religion, and the arts. The book is also superbly written—pellucid, stylish, engaging, and at points richly humorous. A tour de force." [30]

In his 2023 Stanton Lectures, [9] Johnston offered a novel solution to the old problem of why an omniscient, omnipotent, and omnibenevolent God does not prevent horrendous evil. Johnston’s answer is that when we closely examine the ground of God’s creative act, we can see that although God remains omnipotent after creation, i.e., able to do anything metaphysically possible, the range of what is metaphysically possible narrows because of the internal requirements imposed on creation by God’s distinctive reason for creating. Johnston explains how metaphysical possibility narrows in such a way that God, though still omnipotent, can’t intervene in the wind and the waves of matter.

Professional Activities

In 1991, Johnston was—along with Amy Gutman, Jeffrey Stout, George Kateb and John Cooper— a founding member of the Laurance S. Rockefeller University Center for Human Values. He chaired the Princeton Philosophy Department from 1999-2005, a period during which it continued to be regarded as the leading department of philosophy in the United States and elsewhere. [42] In 2001 Johnston received Princeton University’s Medal of Service [11] for his work on the Presidential Search Committee that lead to the appointment of the first woman President of Princeton, Shirley Tilman. While chair of philosophy he helped Princeton hire into senior positions the distinguished American philosophers Delia Graff Fara, Anthony Appiah, Daniel Garber and three renowned Australia-based philosophers—Peter Singer, Michael Smith and Philip Pettit. In 2012, as Senior Academic Advisor of the Marc Sanders Foundation, he personally established almost all of the Foundation’s projects, which were designed to favor the disadvantaged and the young in the profession, and which continue to this day. In 2013, with Yena Lee, he worked on the early formation and financial support of the now internationally known Minorities in Philosophy (MAP).

From 2018-2020 Johnston served as the Director of Princeton University’s Program in Cognitive Science. [43]

Johnston has supervised many Ph.D. dissertations, including those of Jessica Boyd, Alex Byrne, Michael Graff Fara, Cody Gilmore, Sherif Girgis (pending), Caspar Hare, Benjamin Hellie, Jennifer Hawkins, Adam Lerner, Kirsten Larsen, Carla Marino-Rajme, Christopher O’Callaghan, Joshua O’ Rourke, Christian Perring, Christian Piller, James Pryor, Christopher Register, Scott Sehon, Kieran Setiya, David Sosa, Natalie Stoljar, Hwan Sunwoo, Nathaniel Tabris and Michael Thau.

Selected articles

Related Research Articles

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Existence</span> State of being real

Existence is the state of being real or participating in reality. The terms "being", "reality", and "actuality" are often used as close synonyms. Existence contrasts with nonexistence, nothingness, and nonbeing. A common distinction is between the existence of an entity and its essence, which refers to the entity's nature or essential qualities.

Metaphysics is the branch of philosophy that studies the fundamental nature of reality. This includes studies of the first principles of: being or existence, identity, change, consciousness, space and time, necessity, actuality, and possibility. It can also include questions about the existence of God, as well as relationships between foundational philosophical ideas such as between mind and matter, cause and effect, substance and attribute, or potentiality and actuality.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Ontology</span> Philosophical study of being and existence

In metaphysics, ontology is the philosophical study of being. It investigates what types of entities exist, how they are grouped into categories, and how they are related to one another on the most fundamental level. Ontologists often try to determine what the categories or highest kinds are and how they form a system of categories that encompasses the classification of all entities. Commonly proposed categories include substances, properties, relations, states of affairs, and events. These categories are characterized by fundamental ontological concepts, including particularity and universality, abstractness and concreteness, or possibility and necessity. Of special interest is the concept of ontological dependence, which determines whether the entities of a category exist on the most fundamental level. Disagreements within ontology are often about whether entities belonging to a certain category exist and, if so, how they are related to other entities.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Ian Hacking</span> Canadian philosopher (1936–2023)

Ian MacDougall Hacking was a Canadian philosopher specializing in the philosophy of science. Throughout his career, he won numerous awards, such as the Killam Prize for the Humanities and the Balzan Prize, and was a member of many prestigious groups, including the Order of Canada, the Royal Society of Canada and the British Academy.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">A. C. Ewing</span> English philosopher (1899-1973)

Alfred Cyril EwingFBA, was an English philosopher who spent most of his career at the University of Cambridge. He was a prolific writer who made contributions to Kant scholarship, metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, and the philosophy of religion.

Gregory Vlastos was a preeminent scholar of ancient philosophy, and author of many works on Plato and Socrates. He transformed the analysis of classical philosophy by applying techniques of modern analytic philosophy to restate and evaluate the views of Socrates and Plato.

Peter van Inwagen is an American analytic philosopher and the John Cardinal O'Hara Professor of Philosophy at the University of Notre Dame. He is also a research professor of philosophy at Duke University each spring. He previously taught at Syracuse University, earning his PhD from the University of Rochester in 1969 under the direction of Richard Taylor. Van Inwagen is one of the leading figures in contemporary metaphysics, philosophy of religion, and philosophy of action. He was the president of the Society of Christian Philosophers from 2010 to 2013.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Frank Cameron Jackson</span> Australian philosopher

Frank Cameron JacksonFBA is an Australian analytic philosopher and Emeritus Professor in the School of Philosophy at Australian National University (ANU) where he had spent most of the latter part of his career. His primary research interests include epistemology, metaphysics, meta-ethics and the philosophy of mind. In the latter field he is best known for the "Mary's room" knowledge argument, a thought experiment that is one of the most discussed challenges to physicalism.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Robert Merrihew Adams</span> American philosopher

Robert Merrihew Adams is an American analytic philosopher, specializing in metaphysics, philosophy of religion, ethics, and the history of early modern philosophy.

Robert Culp Stalnaker is an American philosopher who is Laurance S. Rockefeller Professor Emeritus of Philosophy at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. He is a Fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences and a Corresponding Fellow of the British Academy.

Metaphysical naturalism is a philosophical worldview which holds that there is nothing but natural elements, principles, and relations of the kind studied by the natural sciences. Methodological naturalism is a philosophical basis for science, for which metaphysical naturalism provides only one possible ontological foundation. Broadly, the corresponding theological perspective is religious naturalism or spiritual naturalism. More specifically, metaphysical naturalism rejects the supernatural concepts and explanations that are part of many religions.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">J. N. Findlay</span> American philosopher

John Niemeyer Findlay, usually cited as J. N. Findlay, was a South African philosopher.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Alfred Edward Taylor</span> British philosopher

Alfred Edward Taylor, usually cited as A. E. Taylor, was a British idealist philosopher most famous for his contributions to the philosophy of idealism in his writings on metaphysics, the philosophy of religion, moral philosophy, and the scholarship of Plato. He was a fellow of the British Academy (1911) and president of the Aristotelian Society from 1928 to 1929. At Oxford he was made an honorary fellow of New College in 1931. In an age of universal upheaval and strife, he was a notable defender of Idealism in the Anglophone world.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Myles Burnyeat</span> British scholar of ancient philosophy (1939–2019)

Myles Fredric Burnyeat was an English scholar of ancient philosophy.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Barry Stroud</span> Canadian philosopher (1935–2019)

Barry Stroud was a Canadian philosopher and professor at the University of California, Berkeley. Known especially for his work on philosophical skepticism, he wrote about David Hume, Ludwig Wittgenstein, the metaphysics of color, and many other topics.

The following outline is provided as an overview of and topical guide to metaphysics:

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Scott Sehon</span> American philosopher

Scott Robert Sehon is an American philosopher and the Joseph E. Merrill Professor of philosophy at Bowdoin College. His primary work is in the fields of philosophy of mind, metaphysics, epistemology, philosophy of action, and the free will debate. He is the author of Teleological Realism: Mind, Agency and Explanation in which he takes a controversial, non-causalist view of action explanation and Free Will and Action Explanation: a Non-Causal, Compatibilist Account.

Michael Cannon Rea is an American analytic philosopher and, since 2017, John A. O'Brien Professor of Philosophy at the University of Notre Dame. He delivered the 2017 Gifford Lecture on divine hiddenness.

Eleonore Stump is an American philosopher and the Robert J. Henle Professor of Philosophy at Saint Louis University, where she has taught since 1992.

Dutch philosophy is a broad branch of philosophy that discusses the contributions of Dutch philosophers to the discourse of Western philosophy and Renaissance philosophy. The philosophy, as its own entity, arose in the 16th and 17th centuries through the philosophical studies of Desiderius Erasmus and Baruch Spinoza. The adoption of the humanistic perspective by Erasmus, despite his Christian background, and rational but theocentric perspective expounded by Spinoza, supported each of these philosopher's works. In general, the philosophy revolved around acknowledging the reality of human self-determination and rational thought rather than focusing on traditional ideals of fatalism and virtue raised in Christianity. The roots of philosophical frameworks like the mind-body dualism and monism debate can also be traced to Dutch philosophy, which is attributed to 17th century philosopher René Descartes. Descartes was both a mathematician and philosopher during the Dutch Golden Age, despite being from the Kingdom of France. Modern Dutch philosophers like D.H. Th. Vollenhoven provided critical analyses on the dichotomy between dualism and monism.

References

  1. "Mark Johnston | Department of Philosophy". philosophy.princeton.edu. Retrieved 15 June 2020.
  2. 1 2 Johnston, Mark (1984). Particulars and persistence.
  3. "Mark Johnston - CV" (PDF).
  4. "Current Faculty". Philosophy. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  5. "Carl G. Hempel Lecture Series". press.princeton.edu. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  6. "The Gareth Evans Memorial Lectures". www.philosophy.ox.ac.uk. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  7. "Ontotheology as Antidote for Idolatry". The Gifford Lectures. 10 June 2019. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  8. "UC Berkeley - Department of Philosophy". philosophy.berkeley.edu. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  9. 1 2 Goode, D. J. (7 August 2013). "Special lectures overview". www.divinity.cam.ac.uk. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  10. 1 2 "Patrick Romanell Lecture - The American Philosophical Association". www.apaonline.org. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  11. 1 2 3 "Harriet Flower and Mark Johnston receive Behrman Award for the humanities". Princeton University. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  12. "Winners Book Awards". aarweb.org. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  13. Wood, James (9 December 2009). "James Wood on the Books of 2009". The New Yorker. ISSN   0028-792X . Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  14. Johnston, Goddard, Mark, Leonard (1983). "The Nature of Reflexive Paradoxes". Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic. 24.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  15. Johnston, Mark (2000). "Rules for the Misdirection of Funds: Portfolio Screening and the Ethics of Trading". Unexpected Consequences: Essays in Honor of George Soros (Central University Press).
  16. Johnston, Mark (1987). "Human Beings". philpapers.org. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  17. Johnston, Mark; Leslie, Sarah-Jane (2012). "Concepts, analysis, generics and the canberra plan". philpapers.org. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  18. Johnston, Mark (July 2001). "The Authority of Affect". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 63 (1): 181–214. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2001.tb00097.x. ISSN   0031-8205.
  19. Johnston, Mark (1995). "Self-deception and the nature of mind". philpapers.org. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  20. "Response-Dependence Theories | Encyclopedia.com". www.encyclopedia.com. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  21. Johnston, Mark (1993). "Objectivity refigured: Pragmatism without verificationism". philpapers.org. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  22. Johnston, Mark (1992). "How to Speak of the Colors". Philosophical Studies. 68 (3): 221–263. doi:10.1007/BF00694847. ISSN   0031-8116. JSTOR   4320356. S2CID   170372515.
  23. Johnston, Mark (2004). "The Obscure Object of Hallucination". Philosophical Studies. 120 (1/3): 113–183. doi:10.1023/B:PHIL.0000033753.64202.21. ISSN   0031-8116. JSTOR   4321510. S2CID   171074190.
  24. Johnston, Mark (2006). "Better than mere knowledge? The function of sensory awareness". philpapers.org. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  25. Johnston, Mark (2007). "Objective Mind and the Objectivity of Our Minds". philpapers.org. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  26. Johnston, Mark (2011). "There are no visual fields (and no minds either)". philpapers.org. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  27. Johnston, Mark (2011). "On a Neglected Epistemic Virtue". Philosophical Issues. 21: 165–218. doi:10.1111/j.1533-6077.2011.00201.x. ISSN   1533-6077. JSTOR   41329421.
  28. Johnston, Mark; Forbes, Graeme (1987). "Is There a Problem about Persistence?". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes. 61: 107–155. doi:10.1093/aristoteliansupp/61.1.107. ISSN   0309-7013. JSTOR   4106835.
  29. Johnston, Mark (1989). "Relativism and the Self". philpapers.org. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  30. 1 2 Johnston, Mark (30 October 2011). Surviving Death. Princeton University Press. ISBN   978-0-691-13013-2.
  31. Johnston, Mark (1992). "Constitution Is Not Identity". Mind. 101 (401): 89–105. doi:10.1093/mind/101.401.89. ISSN   0026-4423. JSTOR   2254121.
  32. Wasserman, Ryan (2021), "Material Constitution", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2021 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 5 August 2023
  33. Johnston, Mark (2006). "Hylomorphism". philpapers.org. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  34. Leonard, Henry S.; Goodman, Nelson (1940). "The Calculus of Individuals and Its Uses". The Journal of Symbolic Logic. 5 (2): 45–55. doi:10.2307/2266169. ISSN   0022-4812. JSTOR   2266169. S2CID   34482983.
  35. Johnston, Mark (2002). "Parts and Principles". philpapers.org. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  36. Johnston, Mark (September 2017). "The Personite Problem: Should Practical Reason Be Tabled? 1". Noûs. 51 (3): 617–644. doi:10.1111/nous.12159. ISSN   0029-4624.
  37. Johnston, Mark (December 2016). "Personites, Maximality And Ontological Trash: Personites, Maximality, and Ontological Trash". Philosophical Perspectives. 30 (1): 198–228. doi: 10.1111/phpe.12085 .
  38. Johnston, Mark (2016). "Remnant Persons". Animalism. pp. 89–127. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199608751.003.0005. ISBN   978-0-19-960875-1.
  39. Johnston, Mark (31 July 2011). Saving God. Princeton University Press. ISBN   978-0-691-15261-5.
  40. Coady, Tony. Australian Review of Books.{{cite journal}}: Missing or empty |title= (help)
  41. "YOU'RE DEAD, NOPW WHAT?". Tampa Bay Times. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  42. "Chairs and Faculty since 1949". Philosophy. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  43. "From Lindrum's to Princeton, and Surfaces to the Hereafter: A Written Interview with Mark Johnston". ORB. 26 November 2019. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  44. "Profile for Mark Johnston - PhilPapers". philpapers.org. Archived from the original on 17 June 2015.