Math on Trial

Last updated

Math on Trial: How Numbers Get Used and Abused in the Courtroom is a book on mathematical and statistical reasoning in legal argumentation, for a popular audience. It was written by American mathematician Leila Schneps and her daughter, French mathematics educator Coralie Colmez, and published in 2013 by Basic Books.

Contents

Topics

Math on Trial consists of ten chapters, each outlining a particular mathematical fallacy, presenting a case study of a trial in which it arose, and then detailing the effects of the fallacy on the case outcome [1] [2] The cases range over a wide range of years and locations, and are roughly ordered by the sophistication of the reasoning needed to resolve them. [3] Their descriptions are based on case records, contemporary newspaper accounts, later scholarship, and in some cases interviews with the principals. [2] In particular:

A final conclusion section sums up the cases and brings their histories up to date. [1] Beyond legal practice, the authors argue that the fallacies present in the cases they describe are representative of those appearing more broadly in the public sphere. [10]

Audience and reception

Although some familiarity with basic probability would be helpful to readers, [2] the book is intended for a broad audience, and reviewer Ray Hill writes that its authors "have struck the right balance of providing enough mathematics for the specialist to check out the details, but not so much as to overwhelm the general reader". Hill recommends the book, writing that it "is packed with interest and drama". [1] Similarly, Daniel Ullman writes that it is "beautifully written", with powerful storytelling and careful research. [4] Ludwig Paditz write that it "vividly shows how the desire for scientific certainty can lead even well-meaning courts to commit grave injustice". [8] Paul H. Edelman singles out the wide range of times and places of the cases presented as a particular strength of the book. [10]

Several reviewers suggest that, beyond a general audience, the book may also be useful as supplementary material for students of probability and statistics, [5] [7] [11] although reviewer Chris Stapel warns that it often overemphasizes the significance of mathematics in the legal cases presented. [11] As reviewer Iwan Praton writes, in many of these cases, the correct reasoning was also presented, but "it is not enough to be correct—one has to be persuasive, too". [7]

However, as well as these positive reviews, the book attracted a significant amount of criticism from its reviewers. Noah Giansiracusa complains that the authors sometimes perpetrate the same fallacies or mistaken calculations that they warn of, that their treatment of legal reasoning can be superficial, and that their accounts of some cases appear to exhibit bias by the authors instead of presenting the cases neutrally. [3] Daniel Ullman also outlines several miscalculations by the authors, while pointing out that they do not affect the overall story told by the book. [4] Michael Finkelstein, a lawyer and scholar of legal statistics, points out an error of fact in Chapter 9 (the book discusses the jury's opinion in a case that had no jury), citing it as evidence of its tendency to aggrandize the role of mathematics in these cases. He suggests instead that in practice, convincing courts of cases through statistical arguments is very difficult and that the fallacies described in these cases are unrepresentative of modern jurisprudence. [6] Edelman criticizes the book for multiple instances of jumps in reasoning, from the mathematical evidence presented in cases and the outcome in cases to dubious conclusions about the significance of the mathematics to the outcome. [10]

Both Edelman and Ullman strongly disagree with the authors' conclusion that mathematics has been a disastrous force in the law. [4] [10] Edelman argues that the problems of fallacious mathematical arguments in legal cases are not different in nature from those of any other expert testimony, and would better be addressed by improving the training of judges in the general use of expert evidence than in the quixotic goal of increasing the mathematical literacy of prospective jurors. [10] Ullman, instead, sees danger in the book's warning against the use of statistical arguments in legal cases, writing that "it is critically important to permit sound mathematics and science to inform legal proceedings". [4]

Related Research Articles

The gambler's fallacy, also known as the Monte Carlo fallacy or the fallacy of the maturity of chances, is the incorrect belief that, if a particular event occurs more frequently than normal during the past, it is less likely to happen in the future, when it has otherwise been established that the probability of such events does not depend on what has happened in the past. Such events, having the quality of historical independence, are referred to as statistically independent. The fallacy is commonly associated with gambling, where it may be believed, for example, that the next dice roll is more than usually likely to be six because there have recently been fewer than the expected number of sixes.

The word probability has been used in a variety of ways since it was first applied to the mathematical study of games of chance. Does probability measure the real, physical, tendency of something to occur, or is it a measure of how strongly one believes it will occur, or does it draw on both these elements? In answering such questions, mathematicians interpret the probability values of probability theory.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Simpson's paradox</span> Probability and statistics phenomenon

Simpson's paradox is a phenomenon in probability and statistics in which a trend appears in several groups of data but disappears or reverses when the groups are combined. This result is often encountered in social-science and medical-science statistics, and is particularly problematic when frequency data are unduly given causal interpretations. The paradox can be resolved when confounding variables and causal relations are appropriately addressed in the statistical modeling.

A fallacy, also known as paralogia in modern psychology, is the use of invalid or otherwise faulty reasoning in the construction of an argument which may appear to be a well-reasoned argument if unnoticed. The term was introduced in the Western intellectual tradition by the Aristotelian De Sophisticis Elenchis.

Inductive reasoning is a method of reasoning in which a general principle is derived from a body of observations. It consists of making broad generalizations based on specific observations. Inductive reasoning is distinct from deductive reasoning, where the conclusion of a deductive argument is certain given the premises are correct; in contrast, the truth of the conclusion of an inductive argument is probable, based upon the evidence given.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Base rate fallacy</span> Error in thinking which involves under-valuing base rate information

The base rate fallacy, also called base rate neglect or base rate bias, is a type of fallacy in which people tend to ignore the base rate in favor of the individuating information . Base rate neglect is a specific form of the more general extension neglect.

The Howland will forgery trial was a U.S. court case in 1868 where businesswoman Henrietta "Hetty" Howland Robinson, who would later become the richest woman in America, contested the validity of the will of her grandaunt, Sylvia Ann Howland.

People v. Collins was a 1968 American robbery trial in California noted for its misuse of probability and as an example of the prosecutor's fallacy.

Logic is the formal science of using reason and is considered a branch of both philosophy and mathematics and to a lesser extent computer science. Logic investigates and classifies the structure of statements and arguments, both through the study of formal systems of inference and the study of arguments in natural language. The scope of logic can therefore be very large, ranging from core topics such as the study of fallacies and paradoxes, to specialized analyses of reasoning such as probability, correct reasoning, and arguments involving causality. One of the aims of logic is to identify the correct and incorrect inferences. Logicians study the criteria for the evaluation of arguments.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Lucia de Berk</span> Dutch paediatric nurse

Lucia de Berk, often called Lucia de B., is a Dutch licensed paediatric nurse who was the subject of a miscarriage of justice. In 2003, she was sentenced to life imprisonment, for which no parole is possible under Dutch law, for four murders and three attempted murders of patients under her care. In 2004, after an appeal, she was convicted of seven murders and three attempted murders.

In logic and mathematics, proof by example is a logical fallacy whereby the validity of a statement is illustrated through one or more examples or cases—rather than a full-fledged proof.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Leila Schneps</span> American mathematician and novelist

Leila Schneps is an American mathematician and fiction writer at the Centre national de la recherche scientifique working in number theory. Schneps has written general audience math books and, under the pen name Catherine Shaw, has written mathematically themed murder mysteries.

<i>How Not to Be Wrong</i> Book by Jordan Ellenberg

How Not to Be Wrong: The Power of Mathematical Thinking, written by Jordan Ellenberg, is a New York Times Best Selling book that connects various economic and societal philosophies with basic mathematics and statistical principles.

<i>Taking Sudoku Seriously</i> 2011 book about sudoku

Taking Sudoku Seriously: The math behind the world's most popular pencil puzzle is a book on the mathematics of Sudoku. It was written by Jason Rosenhouse and Laura Taalman, and published in 2011 by the Oxford University Press. The Basic Library List Committee of the Mathematical Association of America has suggested its inclusion in undergraduate mathematics libraries. It was the 2012 winner of the PROSE Awards in the popular science and popular mathematics category.

<i>Markov Chains and Mixing Times</i>

Markov Chains and Mixing Times is a book on Markov chain mixing times. The second edition was written by David A. Levin, and Yuval Peres. Elizabeth Wilmer was a co-author on the first edition and is credited as a contributor to the second edition. The first edition was published in 2009 by the American Mathematical Society, with an expanded second edition in 2017.

<i>Fat Chance: Probability from 0 to 1</i> Textbook on probability theory

Fat Chance: Probability from 0 to 1 is an introductory undergraduate-level textbook on probability theory, centered on the metaphor of games of chance. It was written by Benedict Gross, Joe Harris, and Emily Riehl, based on a course for non-mathematicians taught to Harvard University undergraduates, and published by the Cambridge University Press in 2019. An associated online course has been offered to the public by Harvard.

<i>The Secrets of Triangles</i>

The Secrets of Triangles: A Mathematical Journey is a popular mathematics book on the geometry of triangles. It was written by Alfred S. Posamentier and Ingmar Lehmann, and published in 2012 by Prometheus Books.

Point Processes is a book on the mathematics of point processes, randomly located sets of points on the real line or in other geometric spaces. It was written by David Cox and Valerie Isham, and published in 1980 by Chapman & Hall in their Monographs on Applied Probability and Statistics book series. The Basic Library List Committee of the Mathematical Association of America has suggested its inclusion in undergraduate mathematics libraries.

References

  1. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 Hill, Ray (September 2013), "Review of Math on Trial" (PDF), Newsletter of London Mathematical Society, London Mathematical Society, 428
  2. 1 2 3 Long, Mary, "Review of Math on Trial", MathSciNet , MR   3025050
  3. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 Giansiracusa, Noah (July 2016), "Teaching the quandary of statistical jurisprudence: a review-essay on Math on Trial by Schneps and Colmez", Journal of Humanistic Mathematics, Claremont Colleges Library, 6 (2): 207–224, doi: 10.5642/jhummath.201602.15
  4. 1 2 3 4 5 6 Ullman, Daniel (May 2014), The American Mathematical Monthly , 121 (5): 463–466, doi:10.4169/amer.math.monthly.121.05.463, JSTOR   10.4169/amer.math.monthly.121.05.463, MR   3186224, S2CID   218544853, Zbl   1305.00079 {{citation}}: CS1 maint: untitled periodical (link)
  5. 1 2 3 4 5 Gorkin, Pamela (November 2013), "Review of Math on Trial", The Mathematical Intelligencer , 36 (1): 78–79, doi:10.1007/s00283-013-9421-5, MR   3167003, S2CID   253815485, Zbl   1302.00023
  6. 1 2 3 Finkelstein, Michael (July–August 2013), "Quantitative evidence often a tough sell in court (review of Math on Trial)" (PDF), SIAM News , 46 (6), archived from the original (PDF) on 2016-04-16
  7. 1 2 3 Praton, Iwan (August 2013), The American Statistician , 67 (3): 188–189, JSTOR   24591472 {{citation}}: CS1 maint: untitled periodical (link)
  8. 1 2 Paditz, Ludwig, "Review of Math on Trial", zbMATH , Zbl   1285.00006
  9. Raloff, Janet (29 June 2013), "Bookshelf (review of Math on Trial)", Science News , 183 (13): 30, JSTOR   23599236
  10. 1 2 3 4 5 Edelman, Paul H. (2013), "Burden of proof: a review of Math on Trial" (PDF), Notices of the American Mathematical Society , 60 (7): 910–914, doi:10.1090/noti1024, MR   3086639, Zbl   1322.00010
  11. 1 2 Stapel, Chris (December 2013 – January 2014), "Publications (review of Math on Trial)", The Mathematics Teacher , 107 (5): 396, doi:10.5951/mathteacher.107.5.0394, JSTOR   10.5951/mathteacher.107.5.0394