Subtle cardinal

Last updated

In mathematics, subtle cardinals and ethereal cardinals are closely related kinds of large cardinal number.

Contents

A cardinal κ is called subtle if for every closed and unbounded C  κ and for every sequence A of length κ for which element number δ (for an arbitrary δ), Aδ  δ, there exist α, β, belonging to C, with α < β, such that Aα = Aβ  α.

A cardinal κ is called ethereal if for every closed and unbounded C  κ and for every sequence A of length κ for which element number δ (for an arbitrary δ), Aδ  δ and Aδ has the same cardinal as δ, there exist α, β, belonging to C, with α < β, such that card(α) = card(Aβ  Aα).

Subtle cardinals were introduced by Jensen & Kunen (1969). Ethereal cardinals were introduced by Ketonen (1974). Any subtle cardinal is ethereal, and any strongly inaccessible ethereal cardinal is subtle.

Relationship to Vopěnka's Principle

Subtle cardinals are equivalent to a weak form of Vopěnka cardinals. Namely, an inaccessible cardinal is subtle if and only if in , any logic has stationarily many weak compactness cardinals. [1]

Vopenka's principle itself may be stated as the existence of a strong compactness cardinal for each logic.

Theorem

There is a subtle cardinal ≤ κ if and only if every transitive set S of cardinality κ contains x and y such that x is a proper subset of y and x  Ø and x  {Ø}. An infinite ordinal κ is subtle if and only if for every λ < κ, every transitive set S of cardinality κ includes a chain (under inclusion) of order type λ.

Extensions

A hypersubtle cardinal is a subtle cardinal which has a stationary set of subtle cardinals below it. [2] p.1014

See also

Related Research Articles

In set theory, an uncountable cardinal is inaccessible if it cannot be obtained from smaller cardinals by the usual operations of cardinal arithmetic. More precisely, a cardinal κ is strongly inaccessible if it satisfies the following three conditions: it is uncountable, it is not a sum of fewer than κ cardinals smaller than κ, and implies .

In mathematics, a Mahlo cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number. Mahlo cardinals were first described by Paul Mahlo. As with all large cardinals, none of these varieties of Mahlo cardinals can be proven to exist by ZFC.

In set theory, a branch of mathematics, a Q-indescribable cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number that is hard to axiomatize in some language Q. There are many different types of indescribable cardinals corresponding to different choices of languages Q. They were introduced by Hanf & Scott (1961).

In mathematics, a measurable cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number. In order to define the concept, one introduces a two-valued measure on a cardinal κ, or more generally on any set. For a cardinal κ, it can be described as a subdivision of all of its subsets into large and small sets such that κ itself is large, and all singletons {α}, ακ are small, complements of small sets are large and vice versa. The intersection of fewer than κ large sets is again large.

In set theory, a Woodin cardinal is a cardinal number such that for all functions

In set theory, a supercompact cardinal is a type of large cardinal independently introduced by Solovay and Reinhardt. They display a variety of reflection properties.

In mathematics, a cardinal number is called huge if there exists an elementary embedding from into a transitive inner model with critical point and

In the mathematics of transfinite numbers, an ineffable cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number, introduced by Jensen & Kunen (1969). In the following definitions, will always be a regular uncountable cardinal number.

In mathematics, a weakly compact cardinal is a certain kind of cardinal number introduced by Erdős & Tarski (1961); weakly compact cardinals are large cardinals, meaning that their existence cannot be proven from the standard axioms of set theory.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Aleph number</span> Infinite cardinal number

In mathematics, particularly in set theory, the aleph numbers are a sequence of numbers used to represent the cardinality of infinite sets that can be well-ordered. They were introduced by the mathematician Georg Cantor and are named after the symbol he used to denote them, the Hebrew letter aleph.

In set theory, a branch of mathematics, a rank-into-rank embedding is a large cardinal property defined by one of the following four axioms given in order of increasing consistency strength.

In mathematics, a Ramsey cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number introduced by Erdős & Hajnal (1962) and named after Frank P. Ramsey, whose theorem establishes that ω enjoys a certain property that Ramsey cardinals generalize to the uncountable case.

In mathematics, limit cardinals are certain cardinal numbers. A cardinal number λ is a weak limit cardinal if λ is neither a successor cardinal nor zero. This means that one cannot "reach" λ from another cardinal by repeated successor operations. These cardinals are sometimes called simply "limit cardinals" when the context is clear.

In mathematics, and particularly in axiomatic set theory, S (clubsuit) is a family of combinatorial principles that are a weaker version of the corresponding S; it was introduced in 1975 by Adam Ostaszewski.

In mathematics, and particularly in axiomatic set theory, the diamond principle is a combinatorial principle introduced by Ronald Jensen in Jensen (1972) that holds in the constructible universe and that implies the continuum hypothesis. Jensen extracted the diamond principle from his proof that the axiom of constructibility implies the existence of a Suslin tree.

In mathematics, particularly in mathematical logic and set theory, a club set is a subset of a limit ordinal that is closed under the order topology, and is unbounded relative to the limit ordinal. The name club is a contraction of "closed and unbounded".

In mathematics, particularly in set theory, if is a regular uncountable cardinal then the filter of all sets containing a club subset of is a -complete filter closed under diagonal intersection called the club filter.

This is a glossary of set theory.

References

Citations

  1. https://victoriagitman.github.io/files/largeCardinalLogics.pdf
  2. C. Henrion, "Properties of Subtle Cardinals. Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 52, no. 4 (1987), pp.1005--1019."