Action (philosophy)

Last updated

In philosophy, an action is an event that an agent performs for a purpose, that is, guided by the person's intention. [1] [2] The first question in the philosophy of action is to determine how actions differ from other forms of behavior, like involuntary reflexes. [3] [4] According to Ludwig Wittgenstein, it involves discovering "[w]hat is left over if I subtract the fact that my arm goes up from the fact that I raise my arm". [5] There is broad agreement that the answer to this question has to do with the agent's intentions. So driving a car is an action since the agent intends to do so, but sneezing is a mere behavior since it happens independent of the agent's intention. The dominant theory of the relation between the intention and the behavior is causalism: [1] driving the car is an action because it is caused by the agent's intention to do so. On this view, actions are distinguished from other events by their causal history. [2] Causalist theories include Donald Davidson's account, which defines actions as bodily movements caused by intentions in the right way, and volitionalist theories, according to which volitions form a core aspect of actions. Non-causalist theories, on the other hand, often see intentions not as the action's cause but as a constituent of it.

Contents

An important distinction among actions is between non-basic actions, which are done by doing something else, and basic actions, for which this is not the case. Most philosophical discussions of actions focus on physical actions in the form of bodily movements. But many philosophers consider mental actions to be a distinct type of action that has characteristics quite different from physical actions. Deliberations and decisions are processes that often precede and lead to actions. Actions can be rational or irrational depending on the reason for which they are performed. The problem of responsibility is closely related to the philosophy of actions since we usually hold people responsible for what they do.

Conceptions

Conceptions of action try to determine what all actions have in common or what their essential features are. Causalist theories, like Donald Davidson's account or standard forms of volitionalism, hold that causal relations between the agent's mental states and the resulting behavior are essential to actions. According to Davidson, actions are bodily movements that are caused by intentions in the right way. Volitionalist theories include the notion of volitions in their account of actions. Volitions are understood as forms of summoning of means within one's power and are different from merely intending to do something later. Non-causalists, on the other hand, deny that intentions or similar states cause actions.

Davidson's account

The most well-known account of action, sometimes simply referred to as the standard account, is due to Davidson, who holds that actions are bodily movements that are caused by intentions. [6] Davidson explains the intentions themselves in terms of beliefs and desires. [1] For example, the action of flipping a light switch rests, on the one hand, on the agent's belief that this bodily movement would turn on the light and, on the other hand, on the desire to have light. [7] Because of its reliance on psychological states and causal relations, this position is considered to be a Humean theory of action. [8] According to Davidson, it is not just the bodily behavior that counts as the action but also the consequences that follow from it. So the movement of the finger flipping the switch is part of the action as well as the electrons moving through the wire and the light bulb turning on. Some consequences are included in the action even though the agent did not intend them to happen. [2] [4] It is sufficient that what the agent does "can be described under an aspect that makes it intentional". [9] [4] So, for example, if flipping the light switch alerts the burglar then alerting the burglar is part of the agent's actions. [1] In an example from Anscombe's manuscript Intention, pumping water can also be an instance of poisoning the inhabitants. [10]

One difficulty with theories of action that try to characterize actions in terms of causal relations between mental states and bodily movements, so-called causalist theories, is what has been referred to as wayward causal chains. [3] A causal chain is wayward if the intention caused its goal to realize but in a very unusual way that was not intended, e.g. because the skills of the agent are not exercised in the way planned. [1] For example, a rock climber forms the intention to kill the climber below him by letting go of the rope. A wayward causal chain would be that, instead of opening the holding hand intentionally, the intention makes the first climber so nervous that the rope slips through his hand and thus leads to the other climber's death. [11] Davidson addresses this issue by excluding cases of wayward causation from his account since they are not examples of intentional behavior in the strict sense. So bodily behavior only constitutes an action if it was caused by intentions in the right way.

One important objection to Davidson's theory of actions is that it does not account for the agent's role in the production of action. This role could include reflecting on what to do, choosing an alternative and then carrying it out. [6] Another objection is that mere intentions seem to be insufficient to cause actions, that other additional elements, namely volitions or tryings, are necessary. For example, as John Searle has pointed out, there seems to be a causal gap between intending to do something and actually doing it, which needs an act of the will to be overcome. [6]

Volitionalism

Volitionalists aim to overcome these shortcomings of Davidson's account by including the notion of volition or trying in their theory of actions. [6] Volitions and tryings are forms of affirming something, like intentions. They can be distinguished from intentions because they are directed at executing a course of action in the here and now, in contrast to intentions, which involve future-directed plans to do something later. [6] Some authors also distinguish volitions, as acts of the will, from tryings, as the summoning of means within one's power. [6] [12] But it has been argued that they can be treated as a unified notion since there is no important difference between the two for the theory of action because they play the same explanatory role. [13] This role includes both the experiential level, [4] involving the trying of something instead of merely intending to do so later, and the metaphysical level, in the form of mental causation bridging the gap between mental intention and bodily movement. [14] [6]

Volitionalism as a theory is characterized by three core theses: (1) that every bodily action is accompanied by a trying, (2) that tryings can occur without producing bodily movements and (3) that in the case of successful tryings, the trying is the cause of the bodily movement. [6] [4] The central idea of the notion of trying is found in the second thesis. It involves the claim that some of our tryings lead to successful actions while others arise without resulting in an action. [15] But even in an unsuccessful case there is still something: it is different from not trying at all. [6] For example, a paralyzed person, after having received a new treatment, may test if the treatment was successful by trying to move her legs. But trying and failing to move the legs is different from intending to do it later or merely wishing to do it: only in the former case does the patient learn that the treatment was unsuccessful. [6] There is a sense in which tryings either take place or not, but cannot fail, unlike actions, whose success is uncertain. [15] [3] This line of thought has led some philosophers to suggest that the trying itself is an action: a special type of action called basic action. [1] But this claim is problematic since it threatens to lead to a vicious regress: if something is an action because it was caused by a volition then we would have to posit one more volition in virtue of which the first trying can be regarded as an action. [3] [16]

An influential criticism of the volitional explanations of actions is due to Gilbert Ryle, who argued that volitions are either active, in which case the aforementioned regress is inevitable, or they are not, in which case there would be no need to posit them as an explanatory inert "ghost in the machine". [4] But it has been suggested that this constitutes a false dilemma: that volitions can play an explanatory role without leading to a vicious regress. John Stuart Mill, for example, avoids this problem by holding that actions are composed of two parts: a volition and the bodily movement corresponding to it. [4]

Volitions can also be used to explain how the agent knows about her own action. This knowledge about what one is doing or trying to do is available directly through introspection: the agent does not need to observe her behavior through sensory perception to arrive at this knowledge, unlike an external observer. [1] [4] The experience of agency involved in volitions can be distinguished from the experience of freedom, which involves the additional aspect of having various alternative routes of action to choose from. [4] But volition is possible even if there are no additional alternatives. [4]

Volitionalists usually hold that there is a causal relation between volitions and bodily movements. [6] Critics have pointed out that this position threatens to alienate us from our bodies since it introduces a strict distinction between our agency and our body, which is not how things appear to us. [6] [17] One way to avoid this objection is to hold that volitions constitute bodily movements, i.e. are an aspect of them, instead of causing them. [17] Another response able to soften this objection is to hold that volitions are not just the initial triggers of the bodily movements but that they are continuous activities guiding the bodily movements while they are occurring. [6] [18]

Non-causalism

Non-causalist or anti-causalist theories deny that intentions or similar states cause actions. [19] [20] [21] They thereby oppose causalist theories like Davidson's account or standard forms of volitionalism. They usually agree that intentions are essential to actions. [22] This brings with it the difficulty of accounting for the relation between intentions and actions in a non-causal way. [19] Some suggestions have been made on this issue but this is still an open problem since none of them have gathered significant support. The teleological approach, for example, holds that this relation is to be understood not in terms of efficient causation but in terms of final "causation". [23] One problem with this approach is that the two forms of causation do not have to be incompatible. Few theorists deny that actions are teleological in the sense of being goal-oriented. But the representation of a goal in the agent's mind may act as an efficient cause at the same time. [19] Because of these problems, most of the arguments for non-causalism are negative: they constitute objections pointing out why causalist theories are unfeasible. [19] [24] Important among them are arguments from wayward causation: that behavior only constitutes an action if it was caused by an intention in the right way, not in any way. This critique focuses on difficulties causalists have faced in explicitly formulating how to distinguish between proper and wayward causation. [25]

An important challenge to non-causalism is due to Davidson. [22] [25] As he points out, we usually have many different reasons for performing the same action. But when we perform it, we often perform it for one reason but not for another. [25] [24] For example, one reason for Abdul to go for cancer treatment is that he has prostate cancer, another is that they have his favorite newspaper in the waiting area. Abdul is aware of both of these reasons, but he performs this action only because of the former reason. Causalist theories can account for this fact through causal relation: the former but not the latter reason causes the action. The challenge to non-causalist theories is to provide a convincing non-causal explanation of this fact. [25] [24]

Individuation

The problem of individuation concerns the question of whether two actions are identical or of how actions should be counted. For example, on April 14, 1865, John Wilkes Booth both pulled the trigger of his gun, fired a shot and killed Abraham Lincoln. On a fine-grained theory of individuation, the pulling, the firing and the killing are three distinct actions. [3] In its most extreme form, there is one distinct action for every action type. [4] So, for example, since "singing" and "singing loudly" are two different action types, someone who sings loudly performs at least these two distinct actions. [3] This kind of view has the unintuitive consequence that even the most simple exercises of agency result in a vast number of actions. Theories of coarse-grained individuation of actions, on the other hand, hold that events that constitute each other or cause each other are to be counted as one action. [3] [2] On this view, the action of pulling the trigger is identical to the action of firing the gun and to the action of killing Lincoln. So in doing all of these things, Booth performed only one action. One intuition in favor of this view is that we often do one thing by doing another thing: [2] we shoot the gun by pulling the trigger or we turn on the light by flipping the switch. One argument against this view is that the different events may happen at different times. [4] For example, Lincoln died of his injuries the following day, so a significant time after the shooting. This raises the question of how to explain that two events happening at different times are identical. [4]

Types

Basic and non-basic

An important distinction among actions is between basic and non-basic actions. This distinction is closely related to the problem of individuation since it also depends on the notion of doing one thing by or in virtue of doing another thing, like turning on a light by flipping a switch. [26] [27] [28] In this example, the flipping of the switch is more basic than the turning-on of the light. But the turning-on of the light can itself constitute another action, like the action of alerting the burglar. It is usually held that the chain or hierarchy of actions composed this way has a fundamental level at which it stops. [26] [4] The action at this fundamental level is called a basic action: it is not done by doing something else. [3] For this reason, basic actions are simple while non-basic actions are complex. [26]

It is often assumed that bodily movements are basic actions, like the pressing of one's finger against the trigger, while the consequences of these movements, like the firing of the gun, are non-basic actions. [3] But it seems that bodily movements are themselves constituted by other events (muscle contractions) [4] which are themselves constituted by other events (chemical processes). However, it appears that these more basic events are not actions since they are not under our direct volitional control. [1] [4] One way to solve these complications is to hold that basic actions correspond to the most simple commands we can follow. [26] This position excludes most forms of muscle contractions and chemical processes from the list of basic actions since we usually cannot follow the corresponding commands directly. What counts as a basic action, according to this view, depends on the agent's skills. [26] So contracting a given muscle is a basic action for an agent who has learned to do so. For something to be a basic action it is not just important what the agent can do but what the agent actually does. So raising one's right hand may only count as a basic action if it is done directly through the right hand. If the agent uses her left hand to lift the right hand then the raising of the right hand is not a basic action anymore. [1] [4]

A contrasting view identifies basic actions not with bodily movements but with mental volitions. [1] One motivation for this position is that volitions are the most direct element in the chain of agency: they cannot fail, unlike bodily actions, whose success is initially uncertain. [3] One argument against this position is that it may lead to a vicious regress if it is paired with the assumption that an earlier volition is needed in order for the first volition to constitute an action. [16] This is why volitionists often hold that volitions cause actions or are parts of actions but are not full actions themselves.

Physical and mental

Philosophers have investigated the concept of actions mostly in regard to physical actions, which are usually understood in terms of bodily movements. [9] [16] It is not uncommon among philosophers to understand bodily movements as the only form of action. [6] Some volitionists, on the other hand, claim that all actions are mental because they consist in volitions. But this position involves various problems, as explained in the corresponding section above. However, there is a middle path possible between these two extreme positions that allows for the existence of both physical and mental actions. [16] Various mental events have been suggested as candidates for non-physical actions, like imagining, judging or remembering. [16]

One influential account of mental action comes from Galen Strawson, who holds that mental actions consist in "triggering the delivery of content to one's field of consciousness". [16] [29] According to this view, the events of imagining, judging or remembering are not mental actions strictly speaking but they can be the products of mental actions. [16] Mental actions, in the strict sense, are prefatory or catalytic: they consist in preparing the mind for these contents to arise. [29] They foster hospitable conditions but cannot ensure that the intended contents will appear. [16] Strawson uses the analogy of jumping off a wall, in which the jumping itself (corresponding to the triggering) is considered an action, but the falling (corresponding to the entertaining of a content) is not an action anymore since it is outside the agent's control. [16] [29] Candace L. Upton and Michael Brent object that this account of mental actions is not complete. [16] Taking their lead from mental activities taking place during meditation, they argue that Strawson's account leaves out various forms of mental actions, like maintaining one's attention on an object or removing a content from consciousness. [16]

One reason for doubting the existence of mental actions is that mental events often appear to be involuntary responses to internal or external stimuli and therefore not under our control. [16] Another objection to the existence of mental actions is that the standard account of actions in terms of intentions seems to fail for mental actions. The problem here is that the intention to think about something already needs to include the content of the thought. So the thought is no longer needed since the intention already "thinks" the content. This leads to a vicious regress since another intention would be necessary to characterize the first intention as an action. [16] An objection not just to mental actions but to the distinction between physical and mental actions arises from the difficulty of finding strict criteria to distinguish the two. [30]

Deliberation and decision

Deliberations and decisions are relevant for actions since they frequently precede the action. It is often the case that several courses of action are open to the agent. [3] In such cases, deliberation performs the function of evaluating the different options by weighing the reasons for and against them. Deciding then is the process of picking one of these alternatives and forming an intention to perform it, thereby leading toward an action. [3] [31]

Explanation and rationality

Explanations can be characterized as answers to why-questions. [32] [33] Explanations of actions are concerned with why the agent performed the action. The most straightforward answer to this question cites the agent's desire. For example, John went to the fridge because he had a desire for ice cream. The agent's beliefs are another relevant feature for action explanation. [3] So the desire to have ice cream does not explain that John went to the fridge unless it is paired with John's belief that there is ice cream in the fridge. The desire together with the belief is often referred to as the reason for the action. [3] [4] Causalist theories of action usually hold that this reason explains the action because it causes the action. [3] [6]

Behavior that does not have a reason is not an action since it is not intentional. Every action has a reason but not every action has a good reason. Only actions with good reasons are considered rational. [34] For example, John's action of going to the fridge would be considered irrational if his reason for this is bad, e.g. because his belief that there is ice cream in the fridge is merely based on wishful thinking. [35]

Responsibility

The problem of responsibility is closely related to the philosophy of actions since we usually hold people responsible for what they do. But in one sense the problem of responsibility is wider since we can be responsible not just for doing something but for failing to do something, so-called omissions. [3] [2] [4] For example, a pedestrian witnessing a terrible car accident may be morally responsible for calling an ambulance and for providing help directly if possible. Additionally to what the agent did, it is also relevant what the agent could have done otherwise, i.e. what powers and capacities the agent had. [36] The agent's intentions are also relevant for responsibility, but we can be responsible for things we did not intend. For example, a chain smoker may have a negative impact on the health of the people around him. This is a side-effect of his smoking that is not part of his intention. The smoker may still be responsible for this damage, either because he was aware of this side-effect and decided to ignore it or because he should have been aware of it, so-called negligence. [37]

Perception

In enactivism theory, perception is understood to be sensorimotor in nature. That is, we carry out actions as an essential part of perceiving the world. Alva Noë states: 'We move our eyes, head and body in taking in what is around us... [we]: crane our necks, peer, squint, reach for our glasses or draw near to get a better look...'...'Perception is a mode of activity on the part of the whole animal...It cannot be represented in terms of merely passive, and internal, processes...' [38]

Problem of mental causation

Some philosophers (e.g. Donald Davidson [39] ) have argued that the mental states the agent invokes as justifying his action are physical states that cause the action.[ citation needed ] Problems have been raised for this view because the mental states seem to be reduced to mere physical causes.[ citation needed ] Their mental properties don't seem to be doing any work.[ citation needed ] If the reasons an agent cites as justifying his action, however, are not the cause of the action, they must explain the action in some other way or be causally impotent.[ citation needed ] Those who hold the belief that mental properties are reducible to physical properties are known as token-identity reductionists. [40] Some have disagreed with the conclusion that this reduction means the mental explanations are causally impotent while still maintaining that the reduction is possible. [41] For example, Dretske has put forward the viewpoint of reasons as structuring causes. [41] This viewpoint maintains that the relation, intentional properties that are created in the process of justifying one's actions are causally potent in that the process is an instance of action. [41] When considering that actions are causally potent, Dretske claims that the process of justifying one's actions is necessarily part of the causal system. [41] Others have objected to the belief that mental states can cause physical action without asserting that mental properties can be reduced to physical properties. [42] Such individuals suggest that mental states are epiphenomenal, in that they have no impact on physical states, but are nonetheless distinct entities (see epiphenomenalism). [43]

See also

Related Research Articles

Causality is an influence by which one event, process, state, or object (acause) contributes to the production of another event, process, state, or object (an effect) where the cause is partly responsible for the effect, and the effect is partly dependent on the cause. In general, a process has many causes, which are also said to be causal factors for it, and all lie in its past. An effect can in turn be a cause of, or causal factor for, many other effects, which all lie in its future. Some writers have held that causality is metaphysically prior to notions of time and space.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Free will</span> Ability to make choices without constraints

Free will is the notional capacity or ability to choose between different possible courses of action unimpeded.

Action theory is an area in philosophy concerned with theories about the processes causing willful human bodily movements of a more or less complex kind. This area of thought involves epistemology, ethics, metaphysics, jurisprudence, and philosophy of mind, and has attracted the strong interest of philosophers ever since Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics. With the advent of psychology and later neuroscience, many theories of action are now subject to empirical testing.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Mind–body dualism</span> Philosophical theory

In the philosophy of mind, mind–body dualism denotes either the view that mental phenomena are non-physical, or that the mind and body are distinct and separable. Thus, it encompasses a set of views about the relationship between mind and matter, as well as between subject and object, and is contrasted with other positions, such as physicalism and enactivism, in the mind–body problem.

Experience refers to conscious events in general, more specifically to perceptions, or to the practical knowledge and familiarity that is produced by these processes. Understood as a conscious event in the widest sense, experience involves a subject to which various items are presented. In this sense, seeing a yellow bird on a branch presents the subject with the objects "bird" and "branch", the relation between them and the property "yellow". Unreal items may be included as well, which happens when experiencing hallucinations or dreams. When understood in a more restricted sense, only sensory consciousness counts as experience. In this sense, experience is usually identified with perception and contrasted with other types of conscious events, like thinking or imagining. In a slightly different sense, experience refers not to the conscious events themselves but to the practical knowledge and familiarity they produce. In this sense, it is important that direct perceptual contact with the external world is the source of knowledge. So an experienced hiker is someone who actually lived through many hikes, not someone who merely read many books about hiking. This is associated both with recurrent past acquaintance and the abilities learned through them.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Libertarianism (metaphysics)</span> Term in metaphysics

Libertarianism is one of the main philosophical positions related to the problems of free will and determinism which are part of the larger domain of metaphysics. In particular, libertarianism is an incompatibilist position which argues that free will is logically incompatible with a deterministic universe. Libertarianism states that since agents have free will, determinism must be false and vice versa.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Hard determinism</span> View that free will does not exist

Hard determinism is a view on free will which holds that determinism is true, that it is incompatible with free will, and therefore that free will does not exist. Although hard determinism generally refers to nomological determinism, it can also be a position taken with respect to other forms of determinism that necessitate the future in its entirety.

The language of thought hypothesis (LOTH), sometimes known as thought ordered mental expression (TOME), is a view in linguistics, philosophy of mind and cognitive science, forwarded by American philosopher Jerry Fodor. It describes the nature of thought as possessing "language-like" or compositional structure. On this view, simple concepts combine in systematic ways to build thoughts. In its most basic form, the theory states that thought, like language, has syntax.

Emergentism is the belief in emergence, particularly as it involves consciousness and the philosophy of mind. A property of a system is said to be emergent if it is a new outcome of some other properties of the system and their interaction, while it is itself different from them. Within the philosophy of science, emergentism is analyzed both as it contrasts with and parallels reductionism.

A mental state, or a mental property, is a state of mind of a person. Mental states comprise a diverse class, including perception, pain/pleasure experience, belief, desire, intention, emotion, and memory. There is controversy concerning the exact definition of the term. According to epistemic approaches, the essential mark of mental states is that their subject has privileged epistemic access while others can only infer their existence from outward signs. Consciousness-based approaches hold that all mental states are either conscious themselves or stand in the right relation to conscious states. Intentionality-based approaches, on the other hand, see the power of minds to refer to objects and represent the world as the mark of the mental. According to functionalist approaches, mental states are defined in terms of their role in the causal network independent of their intrinsic properties. Some philosophers deny all the aforementioned approaches by holding that the term "mental" refers to a cluster of loosely related ideas without an underlying unifying feature shared by all. Various overlapping classifications of mental states have been proposed. Important distinctions group mental phenomena together according to whether they are sensory, propositional, intentional, conscious or occurrent. Sensory states involve sense impressions like visual perceptions or bodily pains. Propositional attitudes, like beliefs and desires, are relations a subject has to a proposition. The characteristic of intentional states is that they refer to or are about objects or states of affairs. Conscious states are part of the phenomenal experience while occurrent states are causally efficacious within the owner's mind, with or without consciousness. An influential classification of mental states is due to Franz Brentano, who argues that there are only three basic kinds: presentations, judgments, and phenomena of love and hate.

In the philosophy of mind, psychophysical parallelism is the theory that mental and bodily events are perfectly coordinated, without any causal interaction between them. As such, it affirms the correlation of mental and bodily events, but denies a direct cause and effect relation between mind and body. This coordination of mental and bodily events has been postulated to occur either in advance by means of God or at the time of the event or, finally, according to Baruch Spinoza's Ethics, mind and matter are two of infinite attributes of the only Substance-God, which go as one without interacting with each other. On this view, mental and bodily phenomena are independent yet inseparable, like two sides of a coin.

Causalism holds behavior and actions to be the result of previous mental states, such as beliefs, desires, or intentions, rather than from a present conscious will guiding one's actions.

Physical causal closure is a metaphysical theory about the nature of causation in the physical realm with significant ramifications in the study of metaphysics and the mind. In a strongly stated version, physical causal closure says that "all physical states have pure physical causes" — Jaegwon Kim, or that "physical effects have only physical causes" — Agustin Vincente, p. 150.

The problem of mental causation is a conceptual issue in the philosophy of mind. That problem, in short, is how to account for the common-sense idea that intentional thoughts or intentional mental states are causes of intentional actions. The problem divides into several distinct sub-problems, including the problem of causal exclusion, the problem of anomalism, and the problem of externalism. However, the sub-problem which has attracted most attention in the philosophical literature is arguably the exclusion problem.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Mind–body problem</span> Open question in philosophy of how abstract minds interact with physical bodies

The mind–body problem is a philosophical problem concerning the relationship between thought and consciousness in the human mind, and the body.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Desire</span> Emotion of longing for a person, object or outcome

Desires are states of mind that are expressed by terms like "wanting", "wishing", "longing" or "craving". A great variety of features is commonly associated with desires. They are seen as propositional attitudes towards conceivable states of affairs. They aim to change the world by representing how the world should be, unlike beliefs, which aim to represent how the world actually is. Desires are closely related to agency: they motivate the agent to realize them. For this to be possible, a desire has to be combined with a belief about which action would realize it. Desires present their objects in a favorable light, as something that appears to be good. Their fulfillment is normally experienced as pleasurable in contrast to the negative experience of failing to do so. Conscious desires are usually accompanied by some form of emotional response. While many researchers roughly agree on these general features, there is significant disagreement about how to define desires, i.e. which of these features are essential and which ones are merely accidental. Action-based theories define desires as structures that incline us toward actions. Pleasure-based theories focus on the tendency of desires to cause pleasure when fulfilled. Value-based theories identify desires with attitudes toward values, like judging or having an appearance that something is good.

Interactionism or interactionist dualism is the theory in the philosophy of mind which holds that matter and mind are two distinct and independent substances that exert causal effects on one another. An example of your mind influencing your body would be if you are depressed, you can observe the effects on your body, such as a slouched posture, a lackluster smile, etc. Another example, this time of your body affecting your mind would be: If you struck your toe very forcefully on a door, you would experience terrible pain. Interactionism is one type of dualism, traditionally a type of substance dualism though more recently also sometimes a form of property dualism. Many philosophers and scientists have responded to this theory with arguments both supporting and opposing its relevance to life and whether the theory corresponds to reality.

An intention is a mental state in which the agent commits themselves to a course of action. Having the plan to visit the zoo tomorrow is an example of an intention. The action plan is the content of the intention while the commitment is the attitude towards this content. Other mental states can have action plans as their content, as when one admires a plan, but differ from intentions since they do not involve a practical commitment to realizing this plan. Successful intentions bring about the intended course of action while unsuccessful intentions fail to do so. Intentions, like many other mental states, have intentionality: they represent possible states of affairs.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Agent causation</span> Idea in philosophy

Agent causation, or Agent causality, is an idea in philosophy which states that a being who is not an event—namely an agent—can cause events. Agent causation contrasts with event causation, which occurs when an event causes another event. Whether agent causation as a concept is logically sound is itself a topic of philosophical debate.

Humeanism refers to the philosophy of David Hume and to the tradition of thought inspired by him. Hume was an influential Scottish philosopher well known for his empirical approach, which he applied to various fields in philosophy. In the philosophy of science, he is notable for developing the regularity theory of causation, which in its strongest form states that causation is nothing but constant conjunction of certain types of events without any underlying forces responsible for this regularity of conjunction. This is closely connected to his metaphysical thesis that there are no necessary connections between distinct entities. The Humean theory of action defines actions as bodily behavior caused by mental states and processes without the need to refer to an agent responsible for this. The slogan of Hume's theory of practical reason is that "reason is...the slave of the passions". It restricts the sphere of practical reason to instrumental rationality concerning which means to employ to achieve a given end. But it denies reason a direct role regarding which ends to follow. Central to Hume's position in metaethics is the is-ought distinction. It states that is-statements, which concern facts about the natural world, do not imply ought-statements, which are moral or evaluative claims about what should be done or what has value. In philosophy of mind, Hume is well known for his development of the bundle theory of the self. It states that the self is to be understood as a bundle of mental states and not as a substance acting as the bearer of these states, as is the traditional conception. Many of these positions were initially motivated by Hume's empirical outlook. It emphasizes the need to ground one's theories in experience and faults opposing theories for failing to do so. But many philosophers within the Humean tradition have gone beyond these methodological restrictions and have drawn various metaphysical conclusions from Hume's ideas.

References

  1. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 Wilson, George; Shpall, Samuel; Piñeros Glasscock, Juan S. (2016). "Action". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  2. 1 2 3 4 5 6 Honderich, Ted (2005). "Action". The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
  3. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 Audi, Robert (1999). "action theory". The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.
  4. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 Craig, Edward (1996). "Action". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge.
  5. "Action theory". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 1 March 2021.
  6. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 Stuchlik, Joshua (2013). "From Volitionalism to the Dual Aspect Theory of Action". Philosophia. 41 (3): 867–886. doi:10.1007/s11406-013-9414-9. S2CID   144779235.
  7. Malpas, Jeff (2019). "Donald Davidson: 2.1 Reasons as Causes". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 1 March 2021.
  8. Railton, Peter (2006). "Humean Theory of Practical Rationality". The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory. Oxford University Press. pp. 265–81.
  9. 1 2 Latham, Noa (2016). "Meditation and Self-Control". Philosophical Studies. 173 (7): 1779–1798. doi:10.1007/s11098-015-0578-y. S2CID   170959501.
  10. Anscombe, Gertrude (2000). Intention. Harvard University Press. pp. 37–45. ISBN   0674003993.
  11. Enç, Berent (2004). "Causal Theories of Intentional Behavior and Wayward Causal Chains". Behavior and Philosophy. 32 (1): 149–166.
  12. Honderich, Ted (2005). "Volution". The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
  13. Adams, Frederick; Mele, Alfred R. (1992). "The Intention/Volition Debate". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 22 (3): 323–337. doi:10.1080/00455091.1992.10717283. S2CID   142465441.
  14. Honderich, Ted (2005). "Trying". The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
  15. 1 2 Kühler, Michael; Rüther, Markus (27 October 2016). "7. Handlungsversuche". Handbuch Handlungstheorie: Grundlagen, Kontexte, Perspektiven (in German). J.B. Metzler. ISBN   978-3-476-02492-3.
  16. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 Brent, Michael; Upton, Candace (2019). "Meditation and the Scope of Mental Action". Philosophical Psychology. 32 (1): 52–71. doi:10.1080/09515089.2018.1514491. S2CID   149891767.
  17. 1 2 Haddock, Adrian (June 2005). "At one with our actions, but at two with our bodies". Philosophical Explorations. 8 (2): 157–172. doi:10.1080/13869790500095939. ISSN   1386-9795. S2CID   142740785.
  18. Ginet, Carl (1990). On Action. Cambridge University Press.
  19. 1 2 3 4 Wilson, George; Shpall, Samuel (2016). "Action: 3. The Explanation of Action". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  20. Hu, Jiajun (2018). "1. Introduction". Actions Are Not Events: An Ontological Objection to the Causal Theory of Action.
  21. Goetz, Stewart C. (1988). "A Noncausal Theory of Agency". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 49 (2): 303–316. doi:10.2307/2107978. JSTOR   2107978.
  22. 1 2 Schlosser, Markus (2019). "Agency". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 14 May 2021.
  23. Hu, Jiajun (2018). "6. Conclusion". Actions Are Not Events: An Ontological Objection to the Causal Theory of Action.
  24. 1 2 3 Queloz, Matthieu (2018). "Davidsonian Causalism and Wittgensteinian Anti-Causalism: A Rapprochement". Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy. 5 (20201214): 153–72. doi: 10.3998/ergo.12405314.0005.006 .
  25. 1 2 3 4 Hu, Jiajun (2018). "5. A Davidsonian Challenge". Actions Are Not Events: An Ontological Objection to the Causal Theory of Action.
  26. 1 2 3 4 5 Kühler, Michael; Rüther, Markus (27 October 2016). "6. Basishandlungen". Handbuch Handlungstheorie: Grundlagen, Kontexte, Perspektiven (in German). J.B. Metzler. ISBN   978-3-476-02492-3.
  27. Honderich, Ted (2005). "Basic action". The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
  28. "Basic action". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 1 March 2021.
  29. 1 2 3 Strawson, Galen (2003). "Mental Ballistics or the Involuntariness of Spontaniety". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. 103 (3): 227–257. doi:10.1111/j.0066-7372.2003.00071.x.
  30. Levy, Yair (2019). "What is 'Mental Action'?". Philosophical Psychology. 32 (6): 971–993. doi:10.1080/09515089.2019.1632427. S2CID   198595347.
  31. Szaniawski, Klemens (1 August 1980). "Philosophy of decision making". Acta Psychologica. 45 (1): 327–341. doi:10.1016/0001-6918(80)90041-4. ISSN   0001-6918.
  32. Mayes, G. Randolph. "Theories of Explanation: 4. Contemporary Developments in the Theory of Explanation". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 1 March 2021.
  33. Skow, Bradford (2016). "2. From Explanations to Why-Questions". Reasons Why. Oxford University Press UK.
  34. Alvarez, Maria (1 August 2018). "Reasons for action, acting for reasons, and rationality". Synthese. 195 (8): 3293–3310. doi: 10.1007/s11229-015-1005-9 . ISSN   1573-0964.
  35. Sturdee, P. G. (1995). "Irrationality and the Dynamic Unconscious: The Case for Wishful Thinking". Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology. 2 (2): 163–174.
  36. Talbert, Matthew (2019). "Moral Responsibility". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 1 March 2021.
  37. King, Matt (2009). "The Problem with Negligence". Social Theory and Practice. 35 (4): 577–595. doi:10.5840/soctheorpract200935433.
  38. Alva Noë Action in Perception: (2004), MIT Press(pp1/2 and 111)
  39. "Davidson, D. Essays on Actions and Events, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2001a.
  40. van Riel, Raphael; Van Gulick, Robert (2019), "Scientific Reduction", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2020-03-10
  41. 1 2 3 4 Robb, David; Heil, John (2019), "Mental Causation", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2020-03-10
  42. Epiphenomenalism. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2019.{{cite book}}: |website= ignored (help)
  43. Huxley, T. H., 1874, "On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata, and its History", The Fortnightly Review 16 (New Series): 555–580. Reprinted in Method and Results: Essays by Thomas H. Huxley, New York: D. Appleton and Company, 1898.

Further reading