Uncertainty effect

Last updated

The uncertainty effect, also known as direct risk aversion, is a phenomenon from economics and psychology which suggests that individuals may be prone to expressing such an extreme distaste for risk that they ascribe a lower value to a risky prospect (e.g., a lottery for which outcomes and their corresponding probabilities are known) than its worst possible realization. [1] [2]

Contents

For example, in the original work on the uncertainty effect by Uri Gneezy, John A. List, and George Wu (2006), individuals were willing to pay $38 for a $50 gift card, but were only willing to pay $28 for a lottery ticket that would yield a $50 or $100 gift card with equal probability. [1]

This effect is considered to be a violation of "internality" (i.e., the proposition that the value of a risky prospect must lie somewhere between the value of that prospect’s best and worst possible realizations) which is central to prospect theory, expected utility theory, and other models of risky choice. [1] Additionally, it has been proposed as an explanation for a host of naturalistic behaviors which cannot be explained by dominant models of risky choice, such as the popularity of insurance/extended warranties for consumer products. [2]

Origins

Research on the uncertainty effect was first formally conducted by Uri Gneezy, John A. List, and George Wu in the early 2000s, though it follows in the footsteps of a large body of work devoted to understanding decision making under risk. As their starting point, Gneezy, List, and Wu noted that most models of risky choice assume that when presented with a risky prospect individuals engage in a balancing exercise of sorts in which they compare the best possible outcomes they might realize to the worst possible outcomes they might realize (e.g., in a gamble that gives a 50-50 chance to win $500 or $1,000, individuals might compare these two outcomes to one another). Within this type of schema, individuals are also expected to weight the value (or utility) of each of these discrete outcomes in accordance with the probability that each will occur. [1]

While expected utility theory and prospect theory differ in terms of how outcomes are evaluated and weighted, they both nonetheless rely upon what Gonzalez, List, and Wu term as the "internality axiom." This axiom specifically posits that the value of some risky prospect must lie between the value of that prospect's best and worst possible outcomes. Formally, for some risky prospect which offers probability of earning and probability of earning (where is strictly greater than ), individuals' elicited values for , , and should satisfy the following inequality: . [1]

In a series of studies conducted by Gneezy, List, and Wu, and in follow-up work conducted by Uri Simonsohn (among others), individuals were repeatedly shown to violate this assumption. For example:

Within this body of work, the uncertainty effect was also shown to extend to choice and to consideration of delayed outcomes; it was also shown not to be a consequence of poorly comprehending the lottery. [1] [2]

Among other explanations, it has been proposed that the uncertainty effect might arise as a consequence of individuals experiencing some form of disutility from risk. [2]

Implications

In his follow-up work on the uncertainty effect (or, as he termed it, direct risk aversion), Simonsohn suggested that it might provide an explanation for certain types of responses to risk that cannot be explained by prospect theory and expected utility theory. One notable example is the widespread popularity of insurance for small-stakes and/or low-probability risks – e.g., warranties for consumer electronics, low-deductible insurance policies, and so on; dominant theories of risky choice do not predict that such products should be popular, and Simonsohn asserted that the uncertainty effect might help to explain why. [2]

Critiques and alternative explanations

In the years after Gneezy, List, and Wu published their findings, several other scholars asserted that the uncertainty effect was simply a consequence of individuals misunderstanding the lottery utilized in initial tests of the uncertainty effect. [3] [4] Such claims were partially refuted by Simonsohn, whose 2009 paper utilized revised lottery instructions, as well as several other successful replications of the uncertainty effect which were published in subsequent years. [2] [5] [6] [7]

Notably, however, in later work with Robert Mislavsky, Simonsohn suggested that the uncertainty effect might be a consequence of aversion to "weird" transaction features as opposed to some form of disutility from risk. [8] These and other alternative explanations are briefly summarized below.

Aversion to lotteries

In work published in 2013, Yang Yang, Joachim Vosgerau, and George Loewenstein suggested that the uncertainty effect might in fact be understood as a framing effect. Specifically, they posited that the anomalies associated with the uncertainty effect might not arise as a consequence of distaste for/disutility from risk, but rather, as a consequence of the fact that in most experiments which successfully replicated the uncertainty effect certain outcomes were contrasted to risky prospects described as lotteries, gambles, and the like. As such, they posited that the effect might instead be described as an aversion to lotteries, or – as they term it – an aversion to "bad deals." [9]

Aversion to "weird transactions"

Although Simonsohn initially proposed that the uncertainty effect might reflect a distaste for uncertainty, in later work he and colleague Robert Mislavsky instead explored the idea that adding "weird" features to a transaction might give rise to patterns which appeared consistent with the uncertainty effect. For example, they noted that internality violations may arise as a consequence of being averse to the notion of purchasing a coin flip or other gamble in order to obtain a gift card, rather than the uncertainty represented by the coin flip itself. In their work, Mislavsky and Simonsohn systematically explored this notion, and suggest that the aversion to weird transactions may help to provide a more parsimonious explanation for certain failures to replicate the uncertainty effect. [8]

See also

Related Research Articles

In economics, utility is a measure of the satisfaction that a certain person has from a certain state of the world. Over time, the term has been used in two different meanings.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Risk aversion</span> Economics theory

In economics and finance, risk aversion is the tendency of people to prefer outcomes with low uncertainty to those outcomes with high uncertainty, even if the average outcome of the latter is equal to or higher in monetary value than the more certain outcome.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Prospect theory</span> Theory of behavioral economics and behavioral finance

Prospect theory is a theory of behavioral economics, judgment and decision making that was developed by Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky in 1979. The theory was cited in the decision to award Kahneman the 2002 Nobel Memorial Prize in Economics.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Loss aversion</span> Overall description of loss aversion theory

Loss aversion is a psychological and economic concept which refers to how outcomes are interpreted as gains and losses where losses are subject to more sensitivity in people's responses compared to equivalent gains acquired. Kahneman and Tversky (1992) have suggested that losses can be twice as powerful, psychologically, as gains. When defined in terms of the utility function shape as in the Cumulative Prospect Theory (CPT), losses have a steeper utility than gains, thus being more "painful" than the satisfaction from a comparable gain as shown in Figure 1. Loss aversion was first proposed by Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman as an important framework for Prospect Theory - an analysis of decision under risk.

The expected utility hypothesis is a foundational assumption in mathematical economics concerning decision making under uncertainty. It postulates that rational agents maximize utility, meaning the subjective desirability of their actions. Rational choice theory, a cornerstone of microeconomics, builds this postulate to model aggregate social behaviour.

In psychology and behavioral economics, the endowment effect is the finding that people are more likely to retain an object they own than acquire that same object when they do not own it. The endowment theory can be defined as "an application of prospect theory positing that loss aversion associated with ownership explains observed exchange asymmetries."

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Mental accounting</span>

Mental accounting is a model of consumer behaviour developed by Richard Thaler that attempts to describe the process whereby people code, categorize and evaluate economic outcomes. Mental accounting incorporates the economic concepts of prospect theory and transactional utility theory to evaluate how people create distinctions between their financial resources in the form of mental accounts, which in turn impacts the buyer decision process and reaction to economic outcomes. People are presumed to make mental accounts as a self control strategy to manage and keep track of their spending and resources. People budget money into mental accounts for savings or expense categories. People also are assumed to make mental accounts to facilitate savings for larger purposes. Mental accounting can result in people demonstrating greater loss aversion for certain mental accounts, resulting in cognitive bias that incentivizes systematic departures from consumer rationality. Through increased understanding of mental accounting differences in decision making based on different resources, and different reactions based on similar outcomes can be greater understood.

Inequity aversion (IA) is the preference for fairness and resistance to incidental inequalities. The social sciences that study inequity aversion include sociology, economics, psychology, anthropology, and ethology. Researches on inequity aversion aim to explain behaviors that are not purely driven by self-interests but fairness considerations.

In decision theory, the Ellsberg paradox is a paradox in which people's decisions are inconsistent with subjective expected utility theory. Daniel Ellsberg popularized the paradox in his 1961 paper, "Risk, Ambiguity, and the Savage Axioms". John Maynard Keynes published a version of the paradox in 1921. It is generally taken to be evidence of ambiguity aversion, in which a person tends to prefer choices with quantifiable risks over those with unknown, incalculable risks.

The Allais paradox is a choice problem designed by Maurice Allais (1953) to show an inconsistency of actual observed choices with the predictions of expected utility theory. Rather than adhering to rationality, the Allais paradox proves that individuals rarely make rational decisions consistently when required to do so immediately. The independence axiom of expected utility theory, which requires that the preferences of an individual should not change when altering two lotteries by equal proportions, was proven to be violated by the paradox.

In accounting, finance, and economics, a risk-seeker or risk-lover is a person who has a preference for risk.

The ambiguity effect is a cognitive bias where decision making is affected by a lack of information, or "ambiguity". The effect implies that people tend to select options for which the probability of a favorable outcome is known, over an option for which the probability of a favorable outcome is unknown. The effect was first described by Daniel Ellsberg in 1961.

In decision theory and economics, ambiguity aversion is a preference for known risks over unknown risks. An ambiguity-averse individual would rather choose an alternative where the probability distribution of the outcomes is known over one where the probabilities are unknown. This behavior was first introduced through the Ellsberg paradox.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Cumulative prospect theory</span>

Cumulative prospect theory (CPT) is a model for descriptive decisions under risk and uncertainty which was introduced by Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman in 1992. It is a further development and variant of prospect theory. The difference between this version and the original version of prospect theory is that weighting is applied to the cumulative probability distribution function, as in rank-dependent expected utility theory but not applied to the probabilities of individual outcomes. In 2002, Daniel Kahneman received the Bank of Sweden Prize in Economic Sciences in Memory of Alfred Nobel for his contributions to behavioral economics, in particular the development of Cumulative Prospect Theory (CPT).

The rank-dependent expected utility model is a generalized expected utility model of choice under uncertainty, designed to explain the behaviour observed in the Allais paradox, as well as for the observation that many people both purchase lottery tickets and insure against losses.

In decision theory, on making decisions under uncertainty—should information about the best course of action arrive after taking a fixed decision—the human emotional response of regret is often experienced, and can be measured as the value of difference between a made decision and the optimal decision.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Risk</span> The possibility of something bad happening

In simple terms, risk is the possibility of something bad happening. Risk involves uncertainty about the effects/implications of an activity with respect to something that humans value, often focusing on negative, undesirable consequences. Many different definitions have been proposed. The international standard definition of risk for common understanding in different applications is "effect of uncertainty on objectives".

In decision theory, the von Neumann–Morgenstern (VNM) utility theorem shows that, under certain axioms of rational behavior, a decision-maker faced with risky (probabilistic) outcomes of different choices will behave as if they are maximizing the expected value of some function defined over the potential outcomes at some specified point in the future. This function is known as the von Neumann–Morgenstern utility function. The theorem is the basis for expected utility theory.

Risk aversion is a preference for a sure outcome over a gamble with higher or equal expected value. Conversely, rejection of a sure thing in favor of a gamble of lower or equal expected value is known as risk-seeking behavior.

In decision theory, a multi-attribute utility function is used to represent the preferences of an agent over bundles of goods either under conditions of certainty about the results of any potential choice, or under conditions of uncertainty.

References

  1. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 Gneezy, U.; List, J. A.; Wu, G. (2006-11-01). "The Uncertainty Effect: When a Risky Prospect is Valued Less than its Worst Possible Outcome". The Quarterly Journal of Economics. 121 (4): 1283–1309. doi:10.1093/qje/121.4.1283. ISSN   0033-5533.
  2. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 Simonsohn, Uri (2009-06-01). "Direct Risk Aversion: Evidence From Risky Prospects Valued Below Their Worst Outcome". Psychological Science. 20 (6): 686–692. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.2009.02349.x. ISSN   0956-7976. PMID   19422629. S2CID   12983766.
  3. Rydval, Ondřej; Ortmann, Andreas; Prokosheva, Sasha; Hertwig, Ralph (2009-12-01). "How certain is the uncertainty effect?". Experimental Economics. 12 (4): 473–487. doi: 10.1007/s10683-009-9224-x . ISSN   1386-4157.
  4. Keren, Gideon; Willemsen, Martijn C. (2009-07-01). "Decision anomalies, experimenter assumptions, and participants' comprehension: Revaluating the uncertainty effect". Journal of Behavioral Decision Making. 22 (3): 301–317. doi: 10.1002/bdm.628 .
  5. Newman, George E.; Mochon, Daniel (2012-01-01). "Why are lotteries valued less? Multiple tests of a direct risk-aversion mechanism" (PDF). Judgment and Decision Making. 7 (1): 19–24. doi:10.1017/S1930297500001807. S2CID   3285568.
  6. Sonsino, Doron (2008-03-01). "Disappointment Aversion in internet Bidding-Decisions". Theory and Decision. 64 (2): 363–393. doi:10.1007/s11238-007-9055-1. hdl: 10.1007/s11238-007-9055-1 . ISSN   1573-7187. S2CID   154407767.
  7. Wang, Yitong; Feng, Tianjun; Keller, L. Robin (2013). "A further exploration of the uncertainty effect". Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 47 (3): 291–310. doi:10.1007/s11166-013-9180-x. ISSN   0895-5646. JSTOR   43550208. S2CID   254980901.
  8. 1 2 Mislavsky, Robert; Simonsohn, Uri (2018-11-01). "When Risk Is Weird: Unexplained Transaction Features Lower Valuations". Management Science. 64 (11): 5395–5404. doi:10.1287/mnsc.2017.2868. ISSN   0025-1909. S2CID   53285818.
  9. Yang, Yang; Vosgerau, Joachim; Loewenstein, George (2013-12-01). "Framing Influences Willingness to Pay but Not Willingness to Accept". Journal of Marketing Research. 50 (6): 725–738. doi:10.1509/jmr.12.0430. ISSN   0022-2437. S2CID   145385973.