Junction and nexus are two kinds of syntactic relationship, according to the Danish linguist Otto Jespersen, who was keen to demonstrate the parallels as well as the contrast between them. An example of either junction or nexus is described in terms of the rank of each word, or "word group", that makes it up.
Jespersen first wrote of junction and nexus in the book Sprogets Logik (1913), [1] after which his theory of ranks and of nexus versus junction "remained substantially unchanged" but was described more fully in De to Hovedarter av grammattiske Forbindelser (1921), [2] The Philosophy of Grammar (1924), [3] and Analytic Syntax (1937). [4] [5]
Both nexus and junction involve what Jespersen calls rank. The rank of a word used in a particular context depends on the word's "mutual relations" with other words. As a simple example: [6] [a]
In the combination extremely hot weather the last word weather, which is evidently the chief idea, may be called primary; hot, which defines weather, secondary, and extremely, which defines hot, tertiary.
"Extremely hot weather" is a simple example of what Jespersen terms junction.
In a more complex example, adds Jespersen, a tertiary word might be said to be defined by a quaternary and the quaternary by a quinary; however, "it is needless to distinguish more than three ranks, as there are no formal or other traits that distinguish words of these lower orders from tertiary words". [6]
With examples such as burning hot soup, Jespersen shows that the distinction between secondary (burning taken as coordinated with hot, and related to soup as hot is) and tertiary (burning taken as modifying hot) is not always clear. [7]
In Jespersen's analysis, a given part of speech (grammatical category) is more or less likely to be employed as a primary, secondary, or tertiary.
Jespersen uses special to mean what other writers might term specific, and relates the specialization of a word or word group to factors including its part of speech (verb, adjective, etc):
[O]n the whole substantives are more special than adjectives, they are applicable to fewer objects than adjectives. . . . The adjective indicates and singles out one quality, one distinguishing mark, but each substantive suggests, to whoever understands it, many distinguishing features by which he recognizes the person or thing in question. [20]
Other factors are its rank (primary, secondary, etc), and its function within a clause (object, predicative complement, etc):
The subject is always a primary, though not necessarily the only primary in the sentence; this amounts to saying that the subject is comparatively definite and special, while the predicate is less definite, and thus applicable to a greater number of things. [21]
This is a simply demonstrated for sentences such as "My father is old" (old applying to many people or indeed animals, things and more, but my father to a single person); more problematic with the pair "Miss Castlewood was the prettiest girl at the ball" and "The prettiest girl at the ball was Miss Castlewood" (in the specified context, the prettiest girl at the ball and Miss Castlewood being but a single person). [21] As for a clause such as "there were many people present", the generalization about subjects relies on Jespersen's stance that the subject is not there but instead many people. [22] [e]
Specialization is aided by secondaries. The most important class of adjuncts, writes Jespersen, is of "restrictive or qualifying adjuncts", which limit the reference of the primary, and thus "specialize or define it" ("Icelandic peasants" being more specific than "peasants"). [24] An adjunct is less specific than the primary (and a subjunct less specific than the adjunct), but no matter:
[I]t is really most natural that a less special term is used in order further to specialize what is already to some extent special: the method of attaining a high degree of specialization is analogous to that of reaching the roof of a building by means of ladders: if one ladder will not do, you first take the tallest ladder you have and tie the second tallest to the top of it, and if that is not enough, you tie on the next in length, etc. [24]
A genitive (John's, my) too can be used as a restrictive adjunct. [25]
Jespersen's treatment of articles and the like is not entirely clear. He regards them as pronouns; [26] and says that "the so-called definite article the . . . would be better called the defining or determining article", used as "the least special of adjuncts and yet [one that] specializes more than most other words". [27] He illustrates this: "In the rose, rose is restricted to that one definite rose which is at this very moment in my thought and must be in yours, too, because we have just mentioned it, or because everything in the situation points towards that particular rose." [27] He writes that "the dog is a primary not only when it is the subject, as in the dog barks, but also when it is the object of a verb, as in I see the dog, or of a preposition, as in he runs after the dog" (in which the article belongs to the word group that is a primary); [28] but continues "we may, of course, have two or more coordinate adjuncts to the same primary: thus, in a nice young lady the words a, nice, and young equally define lady", seemingly implying that the article is the entirety of an adjunct. [7]
Proper names too can have adjuncts, and Jespersen distinguishes between the restrictive adjunct in "young Burns" (as distinguished from an older person with that surname) [29] and the non-restrictive adjuncts in "my dear little Ann", which do not specify and "may be termed ornamental . . . or . . . parenthetical adjuncts". [30] The two kinds can be mixed: "In 'this extremely sagacious little man', this alone defines, the other adjuncts merely describe parenthetically" [31] but Jespersen notes that there can be ambiguity: "The industrious Japanese will conquer in the long run: does this mean that the [Japanese] as a nation will conquer, because they are industrious, or that the industrious among the Japanese nation will conquer?" [31]
Jespersen compares a furiously barking dog and the dog barks furiously: [32]
The tertiary element furiously is the same in both combinations, and may therefore here be left out of account. The relation between the dog barks and a barking dog is evidently the same as that between the rose is red and a red rose. In the dog barks and the rose is red we have complete meanings, complete sentences, in which it is usual to speak of the dog and the rose as the subject, and of barks and is red as the predicate, while the combination is spoken of as predication. But what is the difference between these and the other combinations?
For Jespersen, the two expressions do differ: whereas the dog barks furiously "is rounded off as a complete piece of communication", the furiously barking dog "lacks that peculiar finish and makes us ask: What about that dog?". [33] Jespersen concedes that the difference is often attributed to the presence or absence of what is called a verb (after participles and infinitives are excluded as mere verbids), but he rejects this as the criterion. [33] Instead, for the constructions exemplified by a furiously barking dog and the dog barks furiously, Jespersen uses junction and nexus respectively. [7]
It will be "useful", Jespersen says, to use adjunct and adnex for a secondary word in a junction and a nexus respectively; and to use subjunct for a tertiary word in either. [f] [7]
Jespersen confessed to difficulty in describing the fundamental difference(s) between junction and nexus, and employed imagery for the purpose. The version in The Philosophy of Grammar (1924) is: [34]
A nexus . . . always contains two ideas which must necessarily remain separate: the secondary term adds something new to what has already been named. Whereas the junction is more stiff or rigid, the nexus is more pliable; it is, as it were, animate or articulated. Comparisons, of course, are always to some extent inadequate, still as these things are very hard to express in a completely logical or scientific way, we may be allowed to say that the way in which the adjunct is joined to its primary is like the way in which the nose and the ears are fixed on the head, while an adnex rests on its primary as the head on the trunk or a door on a wall. A junction is like a picture, a nexus like a process or a drama. The distinction between a composite name for one idea and the connexion of one concept with another concept is most easily seen if we contrast two such sentences as the blue dress is the oldest and the oldest dress is blue; the fresh information imparted about the dress is, in the first sentence that it is the oldest, and in the second that it is blue; cf. also a dancing woman charms and a charming woman dances.
In Analytic Syntax (1937), Jespersen revises his comparisons, and concludes: [35]
we get nearer the simple truth by saying that a junction serves to make what we are talking about more definite or precise, while a nexus tells us something by placing two (or more) definite ideas in relation to one another.
Jespersen describes various kinds of nexus.
Jespersen provides three kinds of nexus containing a finite verb: [36] First, there is the "ordinary complete sentence": the dog barks. Secondly, nexuses can also be found "in subordinate clauses, that is, as parts of a sentence": "She is afraid when the dog barks". And thirdly, there is "the very interesting phenomenon" exemplified in "Arthur whom they say is kill'd to-night". [g]
As for alternatives:
I . . . [ask] the reader to bear in mind that on the one hand the presence of a finite verb is not required in a nexus, and that on the other hand a nexus may, but does not always, form a complete sentence. [38]
First, Jespersen provides examples of "accusative with infinitive": "I heard/made her sing"; "I caused her to sing"; "she can hardly prevail upon him to eat"; "you may count on him to come"; "nothing could be better than for you to call" (in which for you is "nothing but the primary (subject) of the nexus, whose secondary part is the infinitive" [39] But the nexus may be discontinuous: "he is said/expected/supposed to come at five"; [40] and there are "rare cases" of nexuses serving as subjuncts: "we divided it: he to speak to the Spaniards and I to the English". [h] [40]
Although he does not here include gerunds (another verbid, or non-finite verb form), Jespersen does include "verbal substantives" (substantives derived from verbs) such as "I heard of the Doctor's arrival". [40]
This places "the predicative first, to which the subject is added as a kind of afterthought, but without the verb is". As examples: "Quite serious all this, though it reads like a joke"; "Amazing the things that Russians will gather together and keep". The order may be reversed: "Now I am in Arden, the more fool I!" [i] [41]
Jespersen denies that "we have here ellipsis of is" ("quite serious all this is", "the more fool am I", etc), as "it would only weaken the idiomatic force of such sentences if we were to add the verb, though it would be required if the subject were placed first". [42]
In "I doubt the Doctor's cleverness", [43] [j] cleverness is derived not from a verb but from an adjective. [43] (Examples such as scholarship and chaplaincy are derived from what Jespersen terms substantives. [b] [44] ) Jespersen does concede that "There is evidently great similarity between the substantives here considered, which [such as whiteness] are formed from adjectives, and verbal substantives . . . like coming, arrival, movement, . . . etc." [43]
Jespersen regards the cage empty within "I found the cage empty" as a single object: a nexus-object. Other examples: "does that prove me wrong?"; "he gets things done" [42] [k]
Jespersen comments: "The most interesting thing here is that a verb may take a nexus-object which is quite different from its usual objects, as in 'he drank himself drunk' ... and that verbs otherwise intransitive may have a nexus-object of result: 'he slept himself sober' ". [46]
The object is not necessarily of a verb; a preposition too may have a nexus-object: "I sat at work in the school-room with the window open". [47] Jespersen points out that with is frequent in this construction, and that examples such as with both of us absent show that with has been bleached of its normal meaning. [48]
He adds: "I am inclined to include here some combinations with 'quantifiers', which are not to be taken in the usual way". As examples, too many cooks spoil the broth and no news is good news (which are "evidently quite different from the adjuncts in too many people are poor or no news arrived on that day"). [49]
The construction is one in which "there are two members standing to another in the peculiar relation here termed nexus", and "this combination plays the part of a subjunct in the sentence". Examples include "we shall go, weather permitting"; "this done, he shut the window"; "dinner over, we left the hotel" [50]
"In this notwithstanding (notwithstanding this) and notwithstanding all our efforts we have properly a nexus-subjunct with this and all our efforts as primaries and the negative participle as adnex, but the construction is now practically to be considered as containing a preposition and its object". [51] [l]
"[W]hat might be termed the nexus of deprecation", writes Jespersen, is one "in which the connexion is as it were brushed aside at once as impossible; the meaning is thus negative, and this is expressed in speech by the intonation, which is the same as in questions, often in an exaggerated form and not infrequently given to the two members separately". [53]
This may use an infinitive: "What? I loue! I sue! I seeke a wife!"; "I say anything disrespectful of Dr. Kenn? Heaven forbid!" [m] [54]
Or "a subject and a predicative may be placed together with the same interrogative tone and the same effect of brushing aside the idea of their combination as real or possible": "Why, his grandfather was a tradesman! he a gentleman!" [h] [54]
As a nexus must have "two notions" (whereas the members of a junction form one notion), Jespersen supposes that his reader will be surprised to hear of a single-member nexus. However:
We do find cases in which we have either a primary alone or a secondary alone, and which nevertheless offer so close an analogy to an ordinary nexus that it is impossible to separate them from undoubted instances of nexus. But an accurate analysis will show that the usual two members are everywhere present to the mind, and that it is only in the linguistic expression that one of them may now and then be absent. [55]
A primary alone (a nexus without an adnex) appears in "Yes, I made them" (as a response to "Did they run?"), and "I told them to". "Psychologically" writes Jespersen, "these are cases of aposiopesis ('stop-short sentences' or 'pull-up sentences', as I have called them. . . .)" [56]
The reverse (a nexus without a primary) "is extremely frequent in exclamations, where it is not necessary to tell the hearer what one is speaking about; they form complete pieces of communication and should unhesitatingly be termed 'sentences'." Examples include "How nice!"; "What an extraordinary piece of good luck!"; "Practice makes perfect". [57]
"An accusative-with-infinitive without the accusative is not at all rare": "live and let live"; "make believe"; "I have heard say" [58]
The primary of the nexus is unexpressed but understood to be I in "I like to travel", or "I like travelling"; it is understood to be "the indefinite 'generic person' " in "to travel (travelling) is not easy nowadays", or "activity leads to happiness". [58]
The concepts of rank, junction and nexus were essential to Jespersen's syntactic analyses, particularly as described in The Philosophy of Grammar [3] and Analytic Syntax; [4] but also as employed in Essentials of English Grammar [59] and the fourth syntax volume [60] of Modern English Grammar . [61]
Jespersen ends two chapters of The Philosophy of Grammar dedicated to nexus with: [62]
I venture to hope that the reader will find that the numerous phenomena brought together in this and the preceding chapter throw so much light on one another that it warrants my grouping of these constructions in a separate class, for which the term "nexus" may not be found inappropriate.
In his obituary of Jespersen, Louis Helmslev describes the theory of junction and nexus as a well-known part of Jespersen's grammatical doctrine. but one that
in reality is of lesser importance. Theoretically, the distinction between junction and nexus is not clearly defined; the fundamental notions are left undefined, and the consequence of this is an ever-increasing generalization of the notion of nexus. . . . [I]t seems clear that the theory cannot be maintained in this form. [n]
Pointing out that "[w]e can never assume much correlation between form and meaning", Eugene Nida criticizes Jespersen's "rather serious distortion and complication of the formal and functional values": [64]
For example, the setting up of "nexus" substantives, and dividing expression such as the doctor's arrival from the man's house, because the first is equivalent in meaning to a "nexus" construction, the doctor arrives, is largely unwarranted since there are no paralleling formal or functional differences.
Lorenzo Cigana states that it is difficult to view such straightforward examples of nexus as having secondaries analogous to painted in the painted rose. In the rose is red, the relationship between the secondaries is and red is asymmetrical (red cannot specify is), and "the insertion of a new semantic element that characterizes a verbal construction, ultimately breaks the uniformity of a headed rank-structure". In an old man drank too much wine, it is hard to interpret drank as a secondary of two primaries (man and wine) other than just semantically. [65]
Paul Christophersen remarks that Jespersen's theories of ranks, junction and nexus "have not stood up to later criticism very well". [66] Within a highly laudatory review of Jespersen's Analytic Syntax, [o] James D. McCawley expresses reservations about the three (which he describes as "peculiarly Jespersenian concepts which appear throughout the book"): "Jespersen's explanations of [these] . . . are far from satisfactory. In [Analytic Syntax], his characterizations of nexus and junction rest heavily on analogies which I find unenlightening. . . ." [68]
Paul Diderichsen's "theory of fields" and Louis Hjelmslev's functional approach both drew from Jespersen's model of syntax. [69]
Impressed by the "simplicity, manageability and versatility" of Jespersen's theoretical approach (according prime importance to rank, junction and nexus) and notation (specifically, those used in Analytic Syntax) , Sigfrido Di Giorgi adopted both for a pedagogic grammar, published in 1994, for intermediate/advanced EFL learners. [70]
In Systemic functional grammar, rank has a meaning very different from Jespersen's. [71]
Jespersen's junction and nexus should not be confused with the juncture and nexus of Role and reference grammar. [72]
Both adjunct and (to a lesser extent) subjunct are terms still used in syntactic theory, with meanings related to but very different from those that Jespersen gives them. [73] [74]