Anschauung

Last updated

Anschauung is a German concept that is usually translated as "intuition". It, however, connotes a more nuanced definition especially when the concept is applied to philosophical discourse, including quantum theory. [1] Some of the translations include actual, sense impressions, contemplation, view, opinion, and notion. [1] Anschauung is also an important component of Johann Gottlieb Fichte's doctrine of knowledge.

Contents

Concept

Origin

Plato's Allegory of the Cave including the analogy of the sun. Allegory of the Cave blank.png
Plato's Allegory of the Cave including the analogy of the sun.

Anschauen or Anschauung, as a philosophical concept (intuition), has been identified in Plato's Allegory of the Cave where it was associated with the terms light, sun, and eye. [2] It was also mentioned in the works of Johann Wolfgang von Goethe and was referred to as "Phantasie", “Einbildungskraft”, “exakte sinnliche Phantasie” and “anschauende Urteilskraft”. [2] Used in different contexts, the concept was employed as a tool in Goethe's creative, scientific, and philosophical works. [2]

The term Anschauung is derived from the Middle High German term aneschouwunge, which means "contemplation" or "to look at". [3] The term emerged into a philosophical concept as it became a component in theoretical discourse. It became a part of Friedrich Nietzsche's Theory of Language. [4] It is also cited in Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel and Immanuel Kant's works. There are scholars who maintain that the concept is part of the Kantian terminology, which was developed in Latin and translated to German. [5] This observation holds that Kant often associated the word intuitus with Anschauung to make his meaning clear. [5] The conceptualization was also used in the Kantian investigation on the immediate cognition of the existence of God. [5]

Definition

An application of Anschauung as experience is the perception of fire and immediately recognizing it as fire. Waldbrand-Bodenfeuer.jpg
An application of Anschauung as experience is the perception of fire and immediately recognizing it as fire.

According to Hegel, Anschauung is the immediate perception of something, mental or physical, one that is organized according to its inner nature or according to universal reason. [6] In this definition, he distinguished Anschauung from Vorstellung , which pertains to the philosophical concepts (metaphorical or analogical senses) and their dependence on sensory contents. [7]

Arthur Schopenhauer's definition described the term as what transpires once the eye senses an external object, recognizing it as the cause of the vision. [8] Nietzsche defined Anschauung as the projected image of a completely enraptured being. [8] He also associated it with the word "contemplation". [9] In this definition, there is a rejection of Schopenhauer's version of the concept, as it denies the abstract idealism of the will as well as "its objectifications of the world of representations". [8]

Interpretations

In the Kantian phenomenology, Anschauung is identified as "apprehension". Together with Empfindung (sensation), Anschauung constitutes sense (Sinnlichkeit), which represents subjective states. These two concepts, either independently or together in Wahrnehmung, represent the knowledge of external objects. [10] For Kant, Anschauung is the same as sense-data of knowledge. [11] Another analysis cited it as one of the two characteristics that Kant said represented sensibility. [12] Theseconstitute the sense-impressions identified as facts and are inherent in nature, existing prior to ideas, which are constructs of such impressions. [12] As a doctrine, Anschauung and the corresponding critique of pure understanding are said to reveal the limits of sensible cognition. [13]

In Fichte's doctrine of knowledge, Anschauung plays a role in the perception of the external objects and is united with the notion of Denken. [14] He used Anschauung in a various ways when he outlined his doctrine of knowledge. In some instances, he described it as "non-thought" as sense qualifies as such. [15] In other works, however, he cited that all thoughts are confined within Anschauung. Particularly, Fichte identified "ordinary" and technical conceptualizations. The former pertains to perception or the objective universe for man, citing that what is visually perceived is ego-stuff in thought-forms. [15] The latter denotes the "this and that of the qualitative". [15]

According to Arthur Schopenhauer, everyday empirical Anschauung is intellectual in character since it mainly entails the work of the intellect. [16] This definition is notable because it was against the Kantian notion of a totally direct perception (Wahrnehmung). [16] However, some scholars maintain that for both philosophers, Anschauung is some form of perception. [17] For Schopenhauer, Anschauung is not the common conception of idea since it should be understood as intuition and requires a higher degree of intellect. [18] It is also associated with the thinker's notion pessimism, which was used as part of the principle of sufficient reason. He maintained that truth is compatible with Anschauung and that it can achieve the same result as from that of pessimism. [19]

Related Research Articles

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Arthur Schopenhauer</span> German pessimist philosopher (1788–1860)

Arthur Schopenhauer was a German philosopher. He is best known for his 1818 work The World as Will and Representation, which characterizes the phenomenal world as the product of a blind noumenal will. Building on the transcendental idealism of Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), Schopenhauer developed an atheistic metaphysical and ethical system that rejected the contemporaneous ideas of German idealism. He was among the first thinkers in Western philosophy to share and affirm significant tenets of Indian philosophy, such as asceticism, denial of the self, and the notion of the world-as-appearance. His work has been described as an exemplary manifestation of philosophical pessimism.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Immanuel Kant</span> German philosopher (1724–1804)

Immanuel Kant was a German philosopher and one of the central Enlightenment thinkers. Born in Königsberg, Kant's comprehensive and systematic works in epistemology, metaphysics, ethics, and aesthetics have made him one of the most influential figures in modern Western philosophy.

In philosophy, a noumenon is knowledge posited as an object that exists independently of human sense. The term noumenon is generally used in contrast with, or in relation to, the term phenomenon, which refers to any object of the senses. Immanuel Kant first developed the notion of the noumenon as part of his transcendental idealism, suggesting that while we know the noumenal world to exist because human sensibility is merely receptive, it is not itself sensible and must therefore remain otherwise unknowable to us. In Kantian philosophy, the noumenon is often associated with the unknowable "thing-in-itself". However, the nature of the relationship between the two is not made explicit in Kant's work, and remains a subject of debate among Kant scholars as a result.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">German philosophy</span> Specialty in philosophy, focussed to German language origin

German philosophy, meaning philosophy in the German language or philosophy by German people, in its diversity, is fundamental for both the analytic and continental traditions. It covers figures such as Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, Immanuel Kant, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Karl Marx, Friedrich Nietzsche, Martin Heidegger, Ludwig Wittgenstein, the Vienna Circle, and the Frankfurt School, who now count among the most famous and studied philosophers of all time. They are central to major philosophical movements such as rationalism, German idealism, Romanticism, dialectical materialism, existentialism, phenomenology, hermeneutics, logical positivism, and critical theory. The Danish philosopher Søren Kierkegaard is often also included in surveys of German philosophy due to his extensive engagement with German thinkers.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">19th-century philosophy</span>

In the 19th century, the philosophers of the 18th-century Enlightenment began to have a dramatic effect on subsequent developments in philosophy. In particular, the works of Immanuel Kant gave rise to a new generation of German philosophers and began to see wider recognition internationally. Also, in a reaction to the Enlightenment, a movement called Romanticism began to develop towards the end of the 18th century. Key ideas that sparked changes in philosophy were the fast progress of science, including evolution, most notably postulated by Charles Darwin and Jean-Baptiste Lamarck, and theories regarding what is today called emergent order, such as the free market of Adam Smith within nation states, or the Marxist approach concerning class warfare between the ruling class and the working class developed by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels. Pressures for egalitarianism, and more rapid change culminated in a period of revolution and turbulence that would see philosophy change as well.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">German idealism</span> Philosophical movement

German idealism was a philosophical movement that emerged in Germany in the late 18th and early 19th centuries. It developed out of the work of Immanuel Kant in the 1780s and 1790s, and was closely linked both with Romanticism and the revolutionary politics of the Enlightenment. The best-known thinkers in the movement, besides Kant, were Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, and the proponents of Jena Romanticism. August Ludwig Hülsen, Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi, Gottlob Ernst Schulze, Karl Leonhard Reinhold, Salomon Maimon and Friedrich Schleiermacher also made major contributions.

<i>Critique of Pure Reason</i> 1781 book by Immanuel Kant

The Critique of Pure Reason is a book by the German philosopher Immanuel Kant, in which the author seeks to determine the limits and scope of metaphysics. Also referred to as Kant's "First Critique", it was followed by his Critique of Practical Reason (1788) and Critique of Judgment (1790). In the preface to the first edition, Kant explains that by a "critique of pure reason" he means a critique "of the faculty of reason in general, in respect of all knowledge after which it may strive independently of all experience" and that he aims to reach a decision about "the possibility or impossibility of metaphysics." The term "critique" is understood to mean a systematic analysis in this context, rather than the colloquial sense of the term.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Transcendental idealism</span> Philosophical system founded by Immanuel Kant

Transcendental idealism is a philosophical system founded by German philosopher Immanuel Kant in the 18th century. Kant's epistemological program is found throughout his Critique of Pure Reason (1781). By transcendental Kant means that his philosophical approach to knowledge transcends mere consideration of sensory evidence and requires an understanding of the mind's innate modes of processing that sensory evidence.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Arthur Schopenhauer's aesthetics</span>

Arthur Schopenhauer's aesthetics result from his philosophical doctrine of the primacy of the metaphysical Will as the Kantian thing-in-itself, the ground of life and all being. In his chief work, The World as Will and Representation, Schopenhauer thought that if consciousness or attention is fully engrossed, absorbed, or occupied with the world as painless representations or images, then there is no consciousness of the world as painful willing. Aesthetic contemplation of a work of art provides just such a state—a temporary liberation from the suffering that results from enslavement to the will [need, craving, urge, striving] by becoming a will-less spectator of "the world as representation" [mental image or idea]. Art, according to Schopenhauer, also provides essential knowledge of the world's objects in a way that is more profound than science or everyday experience.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Thing-in-itself</span> In philosophy, the status of objects as they are, independent of observation

In Kantian philosophy, the thing-in-itself is the status of objects as they are, independent of representation and observation. The concept of the thing-in-itself was introduced by the German philosopher Immanuel Kant, and over the following centuries was met with controversy among later philosophers. It is closely related to Kant's concept of noumena or the object of inquiry, as opposed to phenomenon, its manifestations.

<i>The World as Will and Representation</i> Book by Arthur Schopenhauer

The World as Will and Representation, sometimes translated as The World as Will and Idea, is the central work of the German philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer. The first edition was published in late 1818, with the date 1819 on the title-page. A second, two-volume edition appeared in 1844: volume one was an edited version of the 1818 edition, while volume two consisted of commentary on the ideas expounded in volume one. A third expanded edition was published in 1859, the year prior to Schopenhauer's death. In 1948, an abridged version was edited by Thomas Mann.

"Critique of the Kantian philosophy" is a criticism Arthur Schopenhauer appended to the first volume of his The World as Will and Representation (1818). He wanted to show Immanuel Kant's errors so that Kant's merits would be appreciated and his achievements furthered.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Schema (Kant)</span> Rule by which a concept is associated with a sensory input in Kantianism

In Kantian philosophy, a transcendental schema is the procedural rule by which a category or pure, non-empirical concept is associated with a sense impression. A private, subjective intuition is thereby discursively thought to be a representation of an external object. Transcendental schemata are supposedly produced by the imagination in relation to time.

<i>On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason</i> 1813 German-language doctoral dissertation by Schopenhauer

On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason is an elaboration on the classical Principle of Sufficient Reason, written by German philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer as his doctoral dissertation in 1813. The principle of sufficient reason is a powerful and controversial philosophical principle stipulating that everything must have a reason or cause. Schopenhauer revised and re-published it in 1847. The work articulated the centerpiece of many of Schopenhauer's arguments, and throughout his later works he consistently refers his readers to it as the necessary beginning point for a full understanding of his further writings.

A priori and a posteriori are Latin phrases used in philosophy to distinguish types of knowledge, justification, or argument by their reliance on empirical evidence or experience. A priori knowledge is independent from current experience. Examples include mathematics, tautologies, and deduction from pure reason. A posteriori knowledge depends on empirical evidence. Examples include most fields of science and aspects of personal knowledge.

Higher consciousness is the consciousness of God or, in the words of Dawn DeVries, "the part of the human mind that is capable of transcending animal instincts". While the concept has ancient roots, it was significantly developed in German idealism, and is a central notion in contemporary popular spirituality, including the New Age movement.

Schopenhauer's criticism of Kant's schemata is part of Schopenhauer's criticism of the Kantian philosophy which was published in 1819. In the appendix to the first volume of his main work, The World as Will and Representation, Arthur Schopenhauer attempted to assign the psychological cause of Kant's doctrines of the categories and their schemata. Schopenhauer's analysis holds that Kant misused argument by analogy to connect abstract reasoning to empirical perception; Schopenhauer argues that this comparison is baseless, and that its conclusions are thus invalid.

The following is a list of the major events in the history of German idealism, along with related historical events.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Critique of the Schopenhauerian philosophy</span> Critical essay by Philipp Mainländer

Critique of the Schopenhaurian philosophy is a literary work by Philipp Mainländer appended to Die Philosophie der Erlösung, offering a criticism of the philosophy of Arthur Schopenhauer. Mainländer saw the purification of Schopenhauer's philosophy as the primary task of his life. The criticism had an important impact on Nietzsche's philosophical development.

The philosophical ideas and thoughts of Edmund Burke, Thomas Carlyle, Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling, Søren Kierkegaard, Arthur Schopenhauer and Richard Wagner have been frequently described as Romantic.

References

  1. 1 2 Burwell, Jennifer (2018). Quantum Language and the Migration of Scientific Concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. pp. 91–92. ISBN   978-0-262-34512-5.
  2. 1 2 3 Hennigfeld, Iris (2021-11-05). "Anschauung, Anschauen (Intuition)". Goethe-Lexicon of Philosophical Concepts. 1 (2). doi: 10.5195/glpc.2021.49 . ISSN   2694-2321. S2CID   243809168.
  3. "Definition of ANSCHAUUNG". www.merriam-webster.com. Retrieved 2022-02-08.
  4. Crawford, Claudia (2011). The Beginnings of Nietzsche's Theory of Language. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. pp. 158–159. ISBN   978-3-11-011336-5.
  5. 1 2 3 Whitney, William (1911). The Century Dictionary and Cyclopedia: The Century dictionary ... prepared under the superintendence of William Dwight Whitney ... rev. & enl. under the superintendence of Benjamin E. Smith. New York: Century Company. p. 3167.
  6. Luft, Eric v. d. (2019). Ruminations: Selected Philosophical, Historical, and Ideological Papers: Volume 1, Part 1, The Infinite. North Syracuse, NY: Gegensatz Press. p. 100. ISBN   978-1-62130-700-6.
  7. Perkins, Robert L. (2009). Kierkegaard's Fear and Trembling: Critical Appraisals. Eugene, OR: Wipf and Stock Publishers. pp. 63, 68. ISBN   978-1-60608-886-9.
  8. 1 2 3 (2011). Chapter Eleven. Nietzsche’s Worldview in Anschauung. In The Beginnings of Nietzsche's Theory of Language pp. 158-178. Berlin, Boston: De Gruyter.
  9. Nietzsche, Friedrich (2006). On the Genealogy of Morality. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. p. 87. ISBN   0-521-87123-9.
  10. Hyslop, James Hervey (1905). Problems of Philosophy: Or, Principles of Epistemology and Metaphysics. London: The Macmillan Company. p. 304.
  11. Carus, Paul (1892). "What does Anschauung mean?". The Monist. 2 (4): 527–532. doi:10.5840/monist18922411.
  12. 1 2 "Kantian Conceptualism/Nonconceptualism". Stanford University. May 27, 2020. Retrieved February 20, 2022.
  13. Lo, Suet-kwan (2018), "Kant's Revolutionary Doctrine of Anschauung 1 and the Philosophical Significance of Mencius' "Original Mind"", Kant on Intuition, Routledge, pp. 262–274, doi:10.4324/9780429491771-20, ISBN   978-0-429-49177-1, S2CID   197915642 , retrieved 2022-02-20
  14. Thompson, Anna (1894). Radcliffe College Monographs. Boston: Ginn and Company. pp. 190–191.
  15. 1 2 3 Thompson, Anna Boynton (1895). The Unity of Fichte's Doctrine of Knowledge. Boston, MA: Ginn. p. 192.
  16. 1 2 Verwey, G. (2012-12-06). Psychiatry in an Anthropological and Biomedical Context: Philosophical Presuppositions and Implications of German Psychiatry, 1820–1870. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN   978-94-009-5213-3.
  17. Schopenhauer, Arthur (2016). Arthur Schopenhauer: The World as Will and Presentation: Volume I. New York: Routledge. p. 497. ISBN   978-0-321-35578-2.
  18. Pattberg, Thorsten J. (2011). Shengren: Above Philosophy and Beyond Religion. New York: LoD Press, New York. p. 59.
  19. Farrelly, Dan (2015). Arthur Schopenhauer: New Material by Him and about Him by Dr. David Asher. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing. p. 62. ISBN   978-1-4438-7667-4.