Median voting rule

Last updated

The median voting rule or median mechanism is a rule for group decision-making along a one-dimensional domain. Each person votes by writing down his/her ideal value, and the rule selects a single value which is (in the basic mechanism) the median of all votes.

Contents

Motivation

Many scenarions of group decision making involve a one-dimensional domain. Some examples are:

Each member has in mind an ideal decision, called his "peak". Each agent prefers the actual amount to be as close as possible to his peak.

A simple way to decide is the average voting rule : ask each member what is his peak, and take the average of all peaks. But this rule easily manipulable. For example, suppose Alice's peak is 30, George's peak is 40, and Chana's peak is 50. If all voters report their true peaks, the actual amount will be 40. But Alice may manipulate and say that her peak is actually 0; then the average will be 30, which is Alice's actual peak. Thus, Alice has gained from the manipulation. Similarly, any agent whose peak is different than the outcome has an incentive to manipulate and report a false peak.

In contrast, the median rule determines the actual budget at the median of all votes. This simple change makes the rule strategyproof: no voter can gain by reporting a false peak. In the above example, the median is 40, and it remains 40 even if Alice reports 0. In fact, as Alice's true peak is below the median, no false report by Alice can potentially decrease the median; Alice can only increase the median, but this will make her worse-off.

Preconditions

The median voting rule holds in any setting in which the agents have single peaked preferences. This means that there exists some linear ordering > of the alternatives, such that for each agent i with peak pi:

Once such a linear order exists, the median of any set of peaks can be computed by ordering the peaks along this linear order.

Note that single-peakedness does not imply any particular distance-measure between the alternatives, and does not imply anything on alternatives at different sides of the peak. In particular, if a > pi > b, then the agent may prefer either a to b or b to a.

Procedure

Each agent i in 1,...,n is asked to report the value of pi. The values are sorted in ascending order p1 ≤ ... ≤ pn. In the basic mechanism, the chosen value when n is odd is p(n+1)/2, which equals the median of values (when n is even, the chosen value is pn/2):

choice = median(p1, ..., pn).

Proof of strategyproofness

Here is a proof that the median rule is strategyproof:

Using similar reasoning, one can prove that the median rule is also group-strategyproof, that is: no coalition has a coordinated manipulation that improves the utility of one of them without harming the others.

Generalized median rules

Median with phantoms

The median rule is not the only strategyproof rule. One can construct alternative rules by adding fixed votes, that do not depend on the citizen votes. These fixed votes are called "phantoms". For every set of phantoms, the rule that chooses the median of the set of real votes + phantoms is group-strategyproof.

For example, suppose the votes are 30, 40, and 50. Without phantoms, the median rule selects 40. If we add two phantoms at 0, then the median rule selects 30; if we add two phantoms at 100, the median rule selects 50; if we add medians at 20 and 35, the median rule selects 35.

Here are some special cases of phantom-median rules, assuming all the votes are between 0 and 100:

Moulin [1] proved the following characterizations:

Additional characterizations

Moulin's characterizations consider only rules that are "peak only", that is, the rule depends only on the n peaks. Ching [2] proved that all rules that are strategyproof and continuous, even if they are not "peak only", are augmented median rules, that is, can be described by a variant of the median rule with some 2n parameters.

Moulin's characterizations require the rules to handle all single-peaked preferences. Several other works allow rules that handle only a subset of single-peaked preferences:

Border and Jordan [5] :Sec.6,7 generalize the notions of single-peaked preferences and median voting rules to multidimensional settings. They consider three classes of preferences: separable (, where each vi,j is a single-peaked utility function); quadratic ( where A is a symmetric positive definite matrix); and their intersection separable quadratic (, where ai,j are positive constants). In quadratic non-separable domains, the only strategyproof mecanisms are dictatorial. But in separable domains, there are multidimensional strategyproof mechanisms that are composed of one-dimensional strategyproof mechanisms, one for each coordinate.

Berga and Serizawa [3] :Sec.4 seek rules that are both strategyproof and satisfy a condition they call "no vetoer": no individual should be able to avoid any alternative to be the outcome by declaring some preference. They characterize generalized median rules as the only strategyproof rules on "minimally-rich domains". They proved that the unique maximal domain that includes a minimally-rich domain, which allows for the existence of strategyproof rules satisfying the "no vetoer" condition, is the domain of convex preferences.

Barbera, Gul and Stacchetti [6] also generalize the notions of single-peaked preferences and median voting rules to multidimensional settings.

Barbera and Jackson [7] characterized strategyproof rules for weakly-single-peaked preferences, in which the maximal set may contain two alternatives.

Moulin characterized strategyproof rules on single-plateau preferences - a generalization of single-peaked in which each agent is allowed to have an entire interval of ideal points. [8]

Application in the oil industry

In 1954, the Iranian Oil Consortium has adopted a median-like rule to determine Iran's total annual oil output. Annually, each member company's role was weighted by its fixed share of the total output. The chosen output, x, was the highest level such that the sum of the shares of members voting for levels as high as x was at least 70%. [9] :103-108

The median voter theorem relates to ranked voting mechanisms, in which each agent reports his/her full ranking over alternatives. The theorem says that, if the agents' preferences are single-peaked, then every Condorcet method always selects the candidate preferred by the median voter (the candidate closest to the voter whose peak is the median of all peaks).

Highest median voting rules are an attempt at applying the same voting rule to elections by asking voters to submit judgments (scores) for each candidate. However, the strategyproof nature of the median voting rule does not extend to choosing candidates unless the voters have single-peaked preferences over each candidate's final score. This may be a reasonable model of expressive voting, but the rule will not be strategyproof in situations where voters have single-peaked preferences over the outcome (winner) of the election.

The Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem says that every strategyproof rule on three or more alternatives must be a dictatorship. The median rule apparently contradicts this theorem, because it is strategyproof and it is not a dictatorship. In fact there is no contradiction: the Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem applies only to rules that operate on the entire preference domain (that is, only to voting rules that can handle any set of preference rankings). In contrast, the median rule applies only to a restricted preference domain—the domain of single-peaked preferences.

Dummet and Farquharson present a sufficient condition for stability in voting games. [10] [ further explanation needed ]

Related Research Articles

The Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem is a theorem in voting theory. It was first conjectured by the philosopher Michael Dummett and the mathematician Robin Farquharson in 1961 and then proved independently by the philosopher Allan Gibbard in 1973 and economist Mark Satterthwaite in 1975. It deals with deterministic ordinal electoral systems that choose a single winner, and shows that for every voting rule of this form, at least one of the following three things must hold:

  1. The rule is dictatorial, i.e. there exists a distinguished voter who can choose the winner; or
  2. The rule limits the possible outcomes to two alternatives only; or
  3. The rule is not straightforward, i.e. there is no single always-best strategy.

In mechanism design, a strategyproof (SP) mechanism is a game form in which each player has a weakly-dominant strategy, so that no player can gain by "spying" over the other players to know what they are going to play. When the players have private information, and the strategy space of each player consists of the possible information values, a truthful mechanism is a game in which revealing the true information is a weakly-dominant strategy for each player. An SP mechanism is also called dominant-strategy-incentive-compatible (DSIC), to distinguish it from other kinds of incentive compatibility.

In political science and social choice theory, the median voter theorem states that if voters and candidates are distributed along a one-dimensional spectrum and voters have single peaked preferences, any voting method satisfying the Condorcet criterion will elect the candidate preferred by the median voter.

Social choice theory or social choice is a branch of welfare economics that studies the processes of collective decision-making. Social choice incorporates insights from economics, mathematics, and game theory to find the best ways to combine individual opinions, preferences, or beliefs into a single coherent measure of the quality of different outcomes, called a social welfare function. Social choice theory includes the closely-related field of voting theory, and is strongly tied to the field of mechanism design, which can be thought of as the combination of social choice with game theory.

In social choice theory, a dictatorship mechanism is a rule by which, among all possible alternatives, the results of voting mirror a single predetermined person's preferences, without consideration of the other voters. Dictatorship by itself is not considered a good mechanism in practice, but it is theoretically important: by Arrow's impossibility theorem, when there are at least three alternatives, dictatorship is the only ranked voting electoral system that satisfies unrestricted domain, Pareto efficiency, and independence of irrelevant alternatives. Similarly, by Gibbard's theorem, when there are at least three alternatives, dictatorship is the only strategyproof rule.

Single-peaked preferences are a class of preference relations. A group has single-peaked preferences over a set of outcomes if the outcomes can be ordered along a line such that:

  1. Each agent has a "best outcome" in the set, and
  2. For each agent, outcomes that are further from his or her best outcome are preferred less.
<span class="mw-page-title-main">Arunava Sen</span> Indian researcher and teacher

Arunava Sen is a professor of economics at the Indian Statistical Institute. He works on Game Theory, Social Choice Theory, Mechanism Design, Voting and Auctions.

In mechanism design, monotonicity is a property of a social choice function. It is a necessary condition for being able to implement such a function using a strategyproof mechanism. Its verbal description is:

If changing one agent's type changes the outcome under the social choice function, then the resulting difference in utilities of the new and original outcomes evaluated at the new type of this agent must be at least as much as this difference in utilities evaluated at the original type of this agent.

In economics, dichotomous preferences (DP) are preference relations that divide the set of alternatives to two subsets: "Good" versus "Bad".

Random priority (RP), also called Random serial dictatorship (RSD), is a procedure for fair random assignment - dividing indivisible items fairly among people.

A simultaneous eating algorithm(SE) is an algorithm for allocating divisible objects among agents with ordinal preferences. "Ordinal preferences" means that each agent can rank the items from best to worst, but cannot (or does not want to) specify a numeric value for each item. The SE allocation satisfies SD-efficiency - a weak ordinal variant of Pareto-efficiency (it means that the allocation is Pareto-efficient for at least one vector of additive utility functions consistent with the agents' item rankings).

In the fields of mechanism design and social choice theory, Gibbard's theorem is a result proven by philosopher Allan Gibbard in 1973. It states that for any deterministic process of collective decision, at least one of the following three properties must hold:

  1. The process is dictatorial, i.e. there is a single voter whose vote chooses the outcome.
  2. The process limits the possible outcomes to two options only.
  3. The process is not straightforward; the optimal ballot for a voter depends on their beliefs about other voters' ballots.

Combinatorial participatory budgeting,also called indivisible participatory budgeting or budgeted social choice, is a problem in social choice. There are several candidate projects, each of which has a fixed costs. There is a fixed budget, that cannot cover all these projects. Each voter has different preferences regarding these projects. The goal is to find a budget-allocation - a subset of the projects, with total cost at most the budget, that will be funded. Combinatorial participatory budgeting is the most common form of participatory budgeting.

Multiwinner approval voting, also called approval-based committee (ABC) voting, is a multi-winner electoral system that uses approval ballots. Each voter may select ("approve") any number of candidates, and multiple candidates are elected. The number of elected candidates is usually fixed in advance. For example, it can be the number of seats in a country's parliament, or the required number of members in a committee.

Fractional social choice is a branch of social choice theory in which the collective decision is not a single alternative, but rather a weighted sum of two or more alternatives. For example, if society has to choose between three candidates: A B or C, then in standard social choice, exactly one of these candidates is chosen, while in fractional social choice, it is possible to choose "2/3 of A and 1/3 of B".

In fractional social choice, fractional approval voting refers to a class of electoral systems using approval ballots, in which the outcome is fractional: for each alternative j there is a fraction pj between 0 and 1, such that the sum of pj is 1. It can be seen as a generalization of approval voting: in the latter, one candidate wins and the other candidates lose. The fractions pj can be interpreted in various ways, depending on the setting. Examples are:

Budget-proposal aggregation (BPA) is a problem in social choice theory. A group has to decide on how to distribute its budget among several issues. Each group-member has a different idea about what the ideal budget-distribution should be. The problem is how to aggregate the different opinions into a single budget-distribution program.

Donor coordination is a problem in social choice. There are several donors, each of whom wants to donate some money. Each donor supports a different set of targets. The goal is to distribute the total donated amount among the various targets in a way that respects the donors' preferences.

Belief aggregation, also called risk aggregation,opinion aggregation or probabilistic opinion pooling, is a process in which different probability distributions, produced by different experts, are combined to yield a single probability distribution.

In mechanism design, a regret-free truth-telling mechanism is a mechanism in which each player who reveals his true private information does not feel regret after seeing the mechanism outcome. A regret-free mechanism incentivizes agents who want to avoid regret to report their preferences truthfully.

References

  1. Moulin, H. (1980). "On strategy-proofness and single peakedness". Public Choice. 35 (4): 437–455. doi:10.1007/BF00128122. S2CID   154508892.
  2. Ching, Stephen (December 1997). "Strategy-proofness and 'median voters'". International Journal of Game Theory. 26 (4): 473–490. doi:10.1007/BF01813886. hdl: 10722/177668 . S2CID   42830689.
  3. 1 2 Berga, Dolors; Serizawa, Shigehiro (January 2000). "Maximal Domain for Strategy-Proof Rules with One Public Good". Journal of Economic Theory. 90 (1): 39–61. doi:10.1006/jeth.1999.2579.
  4. Massó, Jordi; Moreno de Barreda, Inés (June 2011). "On strategy-proofness and symmetric single-peakedness". Games and Economic Behavior. 72 (2): 467–484. doi:10.1016/j.geb.2010.12.001. hdl: 2072/53376 .
  5. 1 2 Border, Kim C.; Jordan, J. S. (January 1983). "Straightforward Elections, Unanimity and Phantom Voters". The Review of Economic Studies. 50 (1): 153. doi:10.2307/2296962. JSTOR   2296962.
  6. Barberà, Salvador; Gul, Faruk; Stacchetti, Ennio (December 1993). "Generalized Median Voter Schemes and Committees". Journal of Economic Theory. 61 (2): 262–289. doi:10.1006/jeth.1993.1069.
  7. Barberà, Salvador; Jackson, Matthew (July 1994). "A characterization of strategy-proof social choice functions for economies with pure public goods" (PDF). Social Choice and Welfare. 11 (3). doi:10.1007/BF00193809.
  8. Moulin, H. (August 1984). "Generalized condorcet-winners for single peaked and single-plateau preferences". Social Choice and Welfare. 1 (2): 127–147. doi:10.1007/BF00452885.
  9. Blair, John M. (1976). The Control of Oil. doi:10.1007/978-1-349-81487-9. ISBN   978-1-349-81489-3.
  10. Dummett, Michael; Farquharson, Robin (1961). "Stability in Voting". Econometrica. 29 (1): 33–43. doi:10.2307/1907685. JSTOR   1907685.