A joint Politics and Economics series |
Social choice and electoral systems |
---|
Mathematicsportal |
The highest median voting rules are a class of graded voting rules where the candidate with the highest median rating is elected.
The various highest median rules differ in their treatment of ties, i.e., the method of ranking the candidates with the same median rating.
Proponents of highest median rules argue that they provide the most faithful reflection of the voters' opinion. They note that as with other cardinal voting rules, highest medians are not subject to Arrow's impossibility theorem.
However, critics note that highest median rules violate participation and the Archimedean property; highest median rules can fail to elect a candidate almost-unanimously preferred over all other candidates.
As in score voting, voters rate candidates along a common scale, e.g.:
Excellent | Very Good | Good | Fair | Passable | Inadequate | Bad | |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Candidate A | X | ||||||
Candidate B | X | ||||||
Candidate C | X | ||||||
Candidate D | X |
An elector can give the same appreciation to several different candidates. A candidate not evaluated automatically receives the mention "Bad". [1]
Then, for each candidate, we calculate what percentage of voters assigned them each grade, e.g.:
Candidate | Excellent | Very Good | Good | Fair | Passable | Inadequate | Bad | TOTAL |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
A | 5% | 13% | 21% | 20% | 9% | 17% | 15% | 100% |
B | 5% | 14% | 19% | 13% | 13% | 12% | 24% | 100% |
C | 4% | 6% | 10% | 15% | 16% | 24% | 25% | 100% |
This is presented graphically in the form of a cumulative histogram whose total corresponds to 100% of the votes cast:
For each candidate, we then determine the majority (or median) grade (shown here in bold). This rule means that an absolute majority (more than 50%) of voters judge that a candidate deserves at least its majority grade, and that half or more (50% or more) of the electors judges that he deserves at the most its majority grade. Thus, the majority grade looks like a median.
If only one candidate has the highest median score, they are elected. Otherwise, highest median rules must invoke a tiebreaking procedure to choose between the candidates with the highest median grade.
When different candidates share the same median rating, a tie-breaking rule is required, analogous to interpolation. For discrete grading scales, the median is insensitive to changes in the data and highly sensitive to the choice of scale (as there are large "gaps" between ratings).
Most tie-breaking rules choose between tied candidates by comparing their relative shares of proponents (above-median grades) and opponents (below-median grades). [2] The share of proponents and opponents are represented by and respectively, while their share of median grades is written as .
The example in the following table shows a six-way tied rating, where each alternative wins under one of the rules mentioned above. (All scores apart from Bucklin/anti-Bucklin are scaled to fall in to allow for interpreting them as interpolations between the next-highest and next-lowest scores.)
Candidate | Against | For | Diff | Central | Nearest | GMJ |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
A | 15% | 30% | 15% | 17% | 30% | 14% |
B | 4% | 11% | 7% | 23% | 11% | 4% |
C | 27% | 40% | 13% | 10% | 40% | 20% |
D | 43% | 45% | 2% | 1% | 45% | 8% |
E | 3% | 0% | -3% | -50% | -3% | -2% |
F | 49% | 46% | -3% | -2% | -49% | -30% |
Formula |
Cardinal voting systems allow voters to provide much more information than ranked-choice ballots (so long as there are enough categories); in addition to allowing voters to specify which of two candidates they prefer, cardinal ballots allow them to express how strongly they prefer such candidates. [4] Voters can choose between a wide variety of options for rating candidates, allowing for nuanced judgments of quality. [4] [5]
Because highest median methods ask voters to evaluate candidates rather than rank them, they escape Arrow's impossibility theorem, and satisfy both unanimity and independence of irrelevant alternatives. [6] However, highest medians fail the slightly stronger near-unanimity criterion (see #Disadvantages).
Several candidates belonging to a similar political faction can participate in the election without helping or hurting each other, as highest median methods satisfy independence from irrelevant alternatives: [6] Adding candidates does not change the ranking of previous candidates. In other words, if a group ranks A higher than B when choosing between A and B, they should not rank that B higher than A when choosing between A, B, and C.
The most commonly-cited advantage of highest median rules over their mean-based counterparts is they minimize the number of voters who have an incentive to be dishonest. [4] Voters with weak preferences in particular will not have much incentive to give candidates very high or very low scores. On the other hand, all voters in a score voting system have an incentive to exaggerate, which in theory would lead to de facto approval voting for a large share of the electorate most voters will only give the highest or lowest score to every candidate).
Highest median rules violate the participation criterion; in other words, a candidate may lose because they have "too many supporters."
In the example below, notice how adding the two ballots labeled "+" causes A (the initial winner) to lose to B:
+ | + | New Median | Old Median | ||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
A | 9 | 9 | 9 | 6 | 5 | 3 | 0 |
B | 9 | 7 | 7 | 7 | 4 | 2 | 0 |
C | 9 | 0 | 0 | 4 | 3 | 2 | 0 |
It can be proven that score voting (i.e. choosing highest mean instead of highest median) is the unique voting system satisfying the participation criterion, Archimedean property, and independence of irrelevant alternatives, as a corollary of the VNM utility theorem. [7]
Highest median rules violate the Archimedean property; informally, the Archimedean property says that if "99.999...%" of voters prefer Alice to Bob, Alice should defeat Bob. As shown below, it is possible for Alice to defeat Bob in an election, even if only one voter thinks Bob is better than Alice, and a very large number of voters (up to 100%) give Alice a higher rating:
# ballots | Alice | Bob | Charlie |
---|---|---|---|
Many | 100/100 | 52/100 | 0/100 |
1 | 50/100 | 51/100 | 1/100 |
Many | 49/100 | 0/100 | 100/100 |
In this election, Bob has the highest median score (51) and defeats Alice, even though every voter except one (perhaps Bob himself) thinks Alice is a better candidate. This is true no matter how many voters there are. As a result, even a single voter's weak preferences can override the strong preferences of the rest of the electorate.
The above example restricted to candidates Alice and Bob also serves as an example of highest median rules failing the majority criterion, although highest medians can pass the majority criterion with normalized ballots (i.e. ballots scaled to use the whole 0-100 range). However, normalization cannot recover the Archimedean criterion.
A poll of French voters found a majority would be opposed to implementing majority judgment, but a majority would support conducting elections by score voting. [8] [9] [ better source needed ]
Score voting, sometimes called range voting, is an electoral system for single-seat elections. Voters give each candidate a numerical score, and the candidate with the highest average score is elected. Score voting includes the well-known approval voting, but also lets voters give partial (in-between) approval ratings to candidates.
Strategic or tactical voting is voting in consideration of possible ballots cast by other voters in order to maximize one's satisfaction with the election's results.
A Condorcet method is an election method that elects the candidate who wins a majority of the vote in every head-to-head election against each of the other candidates, whenever there is such a candidate. A candidate with this property, the pairwise champion or beats-all winner, is formally called the Condorcet winner or Pairwise Majority Rule Winner (PMRW). The head-to-head elections need not be done separately; a voter's choice within any given pair can be determined from the ranking.
Arrow's impossibility theorem is a key result in social choice theory, showing that no ranking-based decision rule can satisfy the requirements of rational choice theory. Most notably, Arrow showed that no such rule can satisfy independence of irrelevant alternatives, the principle that a choice between two alternatives A and B should not depend on the quality of some third, unrelated option C.
The Copeland or Llull method is a ranked-choice voting system based on counting each candidate's pairwise wins and losses.
Bucklin voting is a class of voting methods that can be used for single-member and multi-member districts. As in highest median rules like the majority judgment, the Bucklin winner will be one of the candidates with the highest median ranking or rating. It is named after its original promoter, the Georgist politician James W. Bucklin of Grand Junction, Colorado, and is also known as the Grand Junction system.
A Condorcet winner is a candidate who would receive the support of more than half of the electorate in a one-on-one race against any one of their opponents. Voting systems where a majority winner will always win are said to satisfy the Condorcet winner criterion. The Condorcet winner criterion extends the principle of majority rule to elections with multiple candidates.
In social choice, a no-show paradox is a surprising behavior in some voting rules, where a candidate loses an election as a result of having too many supporters. More formally, a no-show paradox occurs when adding voters who prefer Alice to Bob causes Alice to lose the election to Bob. Voting systems without the no-show paradox are said to satisfy the participation criterion.
The majority criterion is a voting system criterion applicable to voting rules over ordinal preferences required that if only one candidate is ranked first by over 50% of voters, that candidate must win.
A voting system satisfies join-consistency if combining two sets of votes, both electing A over B, always results in a combined electorate that ranks A over B. It is a stronger form of the participation criterion. Systems that fail the consistency criterion are susceptible to the multiple-district paradox, which allows for a particularly egregious kind of gerrymander: it is possible to draw boundaries in such a way that a candidate who wins the overall election fails to carry even a single electoral district.
In single-winner voting system theory, the Condorcet loser criterion (CLC) is a measure for differentiating voting systems. It implies the majority loser criterion but does not imply the Condorcet winner criterion.
Later-no-harm is a property of some ranked-choice voting systems, first described by Douglas Woodall. In later-no-harm systems, increasing the rating or rank of a candidate ranked below the winner of an election cannot cause a higher-ranked candidate to lose. It is a common property in the plurality-rule family of voting systems.
Majority judgment (MJ) is a single-winner voting system proposed in 2010 by Michel Balinski and Rida Laraki. It is a kind of highest median rule, a cardinal voting system that elects the candidate with the highest median rating.
Rated, evaluative, graded, or cardinalvotingrules are a class of voting methods that allow voters to state how strongly they support a candidate, by giving each one a grade on a separate scale.
Ranked voting is any voting system that uses voters' rankings of candidates to choose a single winner or multiple winners. More formally, a ranked system is one that depends only on which of two candidates is preferred by a voter, and as such does not incorporate any information about intensity of preferences. Ranked voting systems vary dramatically in how preferences are tabulated and counted, which gives them very different properties.
There are a number of different criteria which can be used for voting systems in an election, including the following
This article discusses the methods and results of comparing different electoral systems. There are two broad ways to compare voting systems:
Combined approval voting (CAV) is an electoral system where each voter may express approval, disapproval, or indifference toward each candidate. The winner is the candidate with the highest score, which is determined by subtracting the number of approval votes by the number of disapproval votes.
STAR voting is an electoral system for single-seat elections. The name stands for "Score Then Automatic Runoff", referring to the fact that this system is a combination of score voting, to pick two finalists with the highest total scores, followed by an "automatic runoff" in which the finalist who is preferred on more ballots wins. It is a type of cardinal voting electoral system.
Graduated majority judgment (GMJ), sometimes called the usual judgment or continuous Bucklin voting, is a single-winner rated voting rule that selects the candidate with the highest median score. It was first suggested as an improvement on majority judgment by Andrew Jennings in 2010.