De nostri temporis studiorum ratione

Last updated

De nostri temporis studiorum ratione is the seventh inaugural oration given by Giambattista Vico at the University of Naples, the former six having been given from 1699 to 1707. [1] [2] After being delivered in 1708, it was revised by Vico and published in 1709. [1] [3] The work's title is usually rendered in English as "On the Study Methods of Our Time." Alternatively, scholars refer to the work as the De ratione or De nostri. Given the fact that it refers back to the Jesuit ratio studiorum,[ citation needed ] Vico's title may be most literally rendered as "The Method of the Studies of our Times."

Contents

De ratione is primarily a pedagogical work. Vico sets out to compare classical/ancient learning (viz. the political-philosophical thought of pre-Christian Ancient Greece and Ancient Rome) and modernists (esp. modern jurisprudence, or modern readings of jus/right), drawing the reader's attention to what the two can learn from each other. In doing so, Vico endorses a pedagogical project focused on developing the rhetorical prowess of the individual in contrast to the Cartesian pedagogy widespread among learned circles of his time. [4] This work is widely viewed as an important philosophical precursor to Vico's later works as well as an important standalone work in Vico's thought.

Main ideas

Relation to Vico's sixth inaugural address

Vico set out to compare the study methods of his period to those of the Ancients, with an eye to developing the importance of rhetoric in enriching the life of the student. De ratione can be viewed as a logical continuation of his sixth inaugural address (given in 1707), which prescribes a particular study method for the student that takes into account the epistemic changes that occur in the student's mind throughout their life. [2] Vico accordingly argued that since individuals' memories and imagination are strongest when they are at their youngest, they are more disposed to the study of languages during childhood. [2] Other fields, such as mathematics, metaphysics, and Christian theology should be studied later in one's life due to their abstract subject-matter as one's mind becomes able to grasp such concepts. [2]

The importance of ars topica

Vico's central argument in De ratione is fixed on the lack of ars topica, or practices of argumentative eloquence and the use of logical forms in rhetorical contexts, in the pedagogical practices of his day. In a footnote of his introduction to the 1990 edition of De ratione, Elio Gianturco mentions ars topica with respect to Aristotle's Topics, where "topics" in this context are concerned with forms of correct argumentation. [1] In the third section of De Ratione Vico explains this notion:

In our days, instead, philosophical criticism alone is honored. The art of "topics," far from being given first place in the curriculum, is utterly disregarded. Again, I say, this is harmful, since the invention of arguments is by nature prior to the judgment of their validity, so that, in teaching, that invention should be given priority over philosophical criticism. In our days, we keep away from the art of inventing arguments, and think that this skill is of no use. [1] (p. 14)

Gianturco makes note of this central anti-Cartesian remark: "Vico felt that Descartes had completely undermined topics with his theory of the clear and distinct perception." [1] (p. xxxii) For Vico, truth was not only that which could be discerned from rational criticism and methodological inquiries. Instead, truth could be accessed through one's own self-evaluation, improvement, and experience. The pedagogical techniques of the ancients, Vico argued, were better suited to bring to light this aspect of human flourishing despite scientific advancements in medicine, chemistry, and physics. [1] [3] Although knowledge in general can be produced in large amounts with an eye to truthful conclusions using scientific methods, Vico believed that without the correct educational techniques, this knowledge would remain inaccessible to the student deficient in the arts of rhetoric and eloquence.

Similarities with Vico's other works

In his preface to De ratione, Donald Philip Verene states that the work is "widely regarded as the first statement of Vico's original philosophical position as well as a treasure-house of educational ideas." [1] (p. xi) De ratione serves as an initial explication of Vico's pedagogy, jurisprudence, and epistemology as seen in his later works. This includes Vico's De antiquissima sapientia Italorum (On the Most Ancient Wisdom of the Italians) and Scienza Nuova (New Science).

La Scienza Nuova

Vico's emphasis on imagination and memory in study is echoed in the Scienza Nuova, where these faculties play an integral role in Vico's theory of the development of the mind. For example, in axioms 35-37:

35. Wonder is the daughter of ignorance, and the greater the effect admired, the more the wonder grows in proportion.

36. The more vigorous the imagination, the weaker reasoning is.

37. The most sublime labor of poetry is to give sense and passions to things without sense; and it is a property of children to take inanimate things in their hands and, playing with them, to talk with them as if they were living persons. [5] (p. 86)

Vico identifies poetry as a linguistic expression of sensory qualities, arising from the immediacy of perceptible qualities to one's mind. He uses this to argue that ancient languages, particularly in the form of poetry, provide the most immediate notions of how life was experienced during those periods; hence his seventeenth axiom: "Common ways of speaking should be thought to offer the weightiest of testimony about the ancient customs of peoples, which had currency at the time when their languages were formed." [5] (p. 79)

De antiquissima sapientia Italorum

In De antiquissima, Vico gives his first formulation of the verum factum principle, or the principle that what is true is convertible with that which is made. It has been argued that De ratione gives an indirect rhetorical basis for this principle, as rhetoric serves as the basis upon which truth can be made and contested in discursive environments. [6] David Marshall in his analysis of Vico's rhetoric notes with regard to the verum factum principle that:

The verum-factum principle appears to be an unlikely case because, for Vico, the clearest example of the convertibility of verum and factum had initially been mathematics, a field in which human beings understood the fundaments precisely because the fundaments were artifacts of human definition. In the De ratione, as is often noted, this thought had precipitated a corollary sentence: if we understand mathematics because we make it, then in order to understand nature we would have to be capable of bringing that into being too. (p. 343) [6]

In this sense, narrative structures serve as bearers of truth-content just as much as the propositions comprising them; being able to narrate something in the first place is an example of having made something to be the case (i.e., the narration itself). Thus, rhetoric and truth are inseparable from each other, in an analogous fashion to the made and the true.

See also

Related Research Articles

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Rhetoric</span> Art of persuasion

Rhetoric is the art of persuasion. It is one of the three ancient arts of discourse (trivium) along with grammar and logic/dialectic. As an academic discipline within the humanities, rhetoric aims to study the techniques that speakers or writers use to inform, persuade, and motivate their audiences. Rhetoric also provides heuristics for understanding, discovering, and developing arguments for particular situations.

A sophist was a teacher in ancient Greece in the fifth and fourth centuries BCE. Sophists specialized in one or more subject areas, such as philosophy, rhetoric, music, athletics and mathematics. They taught arete, "virtue" or "excellence", predominantly to young statesmen and nobility.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Giambattista Vico</span> Italian philosopher (1668–1744)

Giambattista Vico was an Italian philosopher, rhetorician, historian, and jurist during the Italian Enlightenment. He criticized the expansion and development of modern rationalism, finding Cartesian analysis and other types of reductionism impractical to human life, and he was an apologist for classical antiquity and the Renaissance humanities, in addition to being the first expositor of the fundamentals of social science and of semiotics. He is recognised as one of the first Counter-Enlightenment figures in history.

<i>Kairos</i> Right or opportune moment

Kairos is an ancient Greek word meaning 'the right or critical moment'. In modern Greek, kairos also means 'weather' or 'time'.

<i>Inventio</i> Canon of rhetoric

Inventio, one of the five canons of rhetoric, is the method used for the discovery of arguments in Western rhetoric and comes from the Latin word, meaning "invention" or "discovery". Inventio is the central, indispensable canon of rhetoric, and traditionally means a systematic search for arguments.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Chaïm Perelman</span> Belgian philosopher (1912–1984)

Chaïm Perelman was a Belgian philosopher of Polish-Jewish origin. He was among the most important argumentation theorists of the twentieth century. His chief work is the Traité de l'argumentation – la nouvelle rhétorique (1958), with Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca, translated into English as The New Rhetoric: A Treatise on Argumentation, by John Wilkinson and Purcell Weaver (1969).

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Glossary of rhetorical terms</span>

Owing to its origin in ancient Greece and Rome, English rhetorical theory frequently employs Greek and Latin words as terms of art. This page explains commonly used rhetorical terms in alphabetical order. The brief definitions here are intended to serve as a quick reference rather than an in-depth discussion. For more information, click the terms.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Rhetoric of science</span>

Rhetoric of science is a body of scholarly literature exploring the notion that the practice of science is a rhetorical activity. It emerged after a number of similarly oriented topics of research and discussion during the late 20th century, including the sociology of scientific knowledge, history of science, and philosophy of science, but it is practiced most typically by rhetoricians in academic departments of English, speech, and communication.

Epistemology or theory of knowledge is the branch of philosophy concerned with the nature and scope (limitations) of knowledge. It addresses the questions "What is knowledge?", "How is knowledge acquired?", "What do people know?", "How do we know what we know?", and "Why do we know what we know?". Much of the debate in this field has focused on analyzing the nature of knowledge and how it relates to similar notions such as truth, belief, and justification. It also deals with the means of production of knowledge, as well as skepticism about different knowledge claims.

Topical logic is the logic of topical argument, a branch of rhetoric developed in the Late Antique period from earlier works, such as Aristotle's Topics and Cicero's Topica. It consists of heuristics for developing arguments, which are in the first place plausible rather than rigorous, from commonplaces. In other words, therefore, it consists of standardized ways of thinking up debating techniques from existing, thought-through positions. The actual practice of topical argument was much developed by Roman lawyers. Cicero took the theory of Aristotle to be an aspect of rhetoric. As such it belongs to inventio in the classic fivefold division of rhetoric.

Common sense is "knowledge, judgement, and taste which is more or less universal and which is held more or less without reflection or argument". As such, it is often considered to represent the basic level of sound practical judgement or knowledge of basic facts that any adult human being ought to possess. It is "common" in the sense of being shared by nearly all people. The everyday understanding of common sense is ultimately derived from historical philosophical discussions. Relevant terms from other languages used in such discussions include Latin sensus communis, Ancient Greek κοινὴ αἴσθησις, and French bon sens. However, these are not straightforward translations in all contexts, and in English different shades of meaning have developed. In philosophical and scientific contexts, since the Age of Enlightenment the term "common sense" has been used for rhetorical effect both approvingly and disapprovingly. On the one hand it has been a standard for good taste, good sense, and source of scientific and logical axioms. On the other hand it has been equated to conventional wisdom, vulgar prejudice, and superstition.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Italian philosophy</span> Philosophical tradition of Italy

Over the ages, Italian philosophy had a vast influence on Western philosophy, beginning with the Greeks and Romans, and going onto Renaissance humanism, the Age of Enlightenment and modern philosophy. Philosophy was brought to Italy by Pythagoras, founder of the school of philosophy in Crotone, Magna Graecia. Major philosophers of the Greek period include Xenophanes, Parmenides, Zeno, Empedocles and Gorgias. Roman philosophers include Cicero, Lucretius, Seneca the Younger, Musonius Rufus, Plutarch, Epictetus, Marcus Aurelius, Clement of Alexandria, Sextus Empiricus, Alexander of Aphrodisias, Plotinus, Porphyry, Iamblichus, Augustine of Hippo, Philoponus of Alexandria and Boethius.

<i>The New Science</i>

The New Science is the major work of Italian philosopher Giambattista Vico. It was first published in 1725 to little success, but has gone on to be highly regarded and influential in the philosophy of history, sociology, and anthropology. The central concepts were highly original and prefigured the Age of Enlightenment.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Theories of rhetoric and composition pedagogy</span>

Theories of rhetoric and composition pedagogy encompass a wide range of interdisciplinary fields centered on the instruction of writing. Noteworthy to the discipline is the influence of classical Ancient Greece and its treatment of rhetoric as a persuasive tool. Derived from the Greek work for public speaking, rhetoric's original concern dealt primarily with the spoken word. In the treatise Rhetoric, Aristotle identifies five Canons of the field of rhetoric: invention, arrangement, style, memory, and delivery. Since its inception in the spoken word, theories of rhetoric and composition have focused primarily on writing

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Lesbian rule</span> Flexible strip of lead for use in molding

A Lesbian rule was historically a flexible mason's rule made of lead that could be bent to the curves of a molding, and used to measure or reproduce irregular curves. Lesbian rules were originally constructed of a pliable kind of lead found on the island of Lesbos.

<i>Controversia</i> Exercise in rhetoric

A controversia is an exercise in rhetoric; a form of declamation in which the student speaks for one side in a notional legal case such as treason or poisoning. The facts of the matter and relevant law are presented in a persuasive manner, in the style of a legal counsel.

Theologia Poetica was a designation adopted throughout the Renaissance for political philosophy independent of Biblical revelation. In Italy, discussions on "poetic theology" were articulated most notably by Boccaccio and Petrarch, both of whom promoted a philosophical life capable of withstanding the inquisitorial scrutiny of theological orthodoxy.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Ancient Indian rhetoric</span> Traditional forms of an Indian art of discourse

India has a long tradition of rhetoric about politics, philosophy, and religion, starting from ancient times.

<i>Eloquentia perfecta</i> Tradition of the Society of Jesus

Eloquentia perfecta, a tradition of the Society of Jesus, is a value of Jesuit rhetoric that revolves around cultivating a person as a whole, as one learns to speak and write for the common good. Eloquentia perfecta is a Latin term which means "perfect eloquence". The term connotes values of eloquent expression and action for the common good. For Jesuits, the term eloquentia perfecta was understood as the joining of knowledge and wisdom with virtue and morality.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Pedro Juan Pepinyá</span> Spanish Jesuit humanist (b. 1530)

Pedro Juan Pepinyá, S.J. was a Spanish Jesuit humanist who contributed to the development of the Jesuit Cursus Conimbricensis commentaries on Aristotle and who revised Cypriano Soarez' De arte rhetorica.

References

  1. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 Vico, Giambattista (1990). De nostri temporis studiorum ratione[On the Study Methods of Our Time]. Translated by Gianturco, Elio. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press. ISBN   978-0-8014-9778-0.
  2. 1 2 3 4 "Introduction: On Humanistic Education", On Humanistic Education, Cornell University Press, pp. 1–28, 2018-12-31, retrieved 2024-05-15
  3. 1 2 Costelloe, Timothy (2022), Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), "Giambattista Vico", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2022 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2024-05-15
  4. Birns, Deborah Kier (1980). "Vico's De nostri temporis studiorum ratione and Eighteenth-Century English Thought". Carte Italiane. 1 (1): 38–39. doi:10.5070/C911011186. ISSN   2331-0545.
  5. 1 2 Vico, Giambattista; Taylor, Jason; Miner, Robert C. (2020). The New Science. New Haven (Conn.): Yale University Press. ISBN   978-0-300-19113-4.
  6. 1 2 Marshall, David L. (2012), Bod, Rens; Maat, Jaap; Weststeijn, Thijs (eds.), "The Afterlife of Rhetoric in Hobbes, Vico and Nietzsche", The Making of the Humanities, Volume II: From Early Modern to Modern Disciplines, Amsterdam University Press, pp. 337–354, ISBN   978-90-8964-455-8 , retrieved 2024-05-15