This article may need to be rewritten to comply with Wikipedia's quality standards.(March 2020) |
In metaphysics, a causal model (or structural causal model) is a conceptual model that describes the causal mechanisms of a system. Several types of causal notation may be used in the development of a causal model. Causal models can improve study designs by providing clear rules for deciding which independent variables need to be included/controlled for.
They can allow some questions to be answered from existing observational data without the need for an interventional study such as a randomized controlled trial. Some interventional studies are inappropriate for ethical or practical reasons, meaning that without a causal model, some hypotheses cannot be tested.
Causal models can help with the question of external validity (whether results from one study apply to unstudied populations). Causal models can allow data from multiple studies to be merged (in certain circumstances) to answer questions that cannot be answered by any individual data set.
Causal models have found applications in signal processing, epidemiology and machine learning. [2]
Causal models are mathematical models representing causal relationships within an individual system or population. They facilitate inferences about causal relationships from statistical data. They can teach us a good deal about the epistemology of causation, and about the relationship between causation and probability. They have also been applied to topics of interest to philosophers, such as the logic of counterfactuals, decision theory, and the analysis of actual causation. [3]
— Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Judea Pearl defines a causal model as an ordered triple , where U is a set of exogenous variables whose values are determined by factors outside the model; V is a set of endogenous variables whose values are determined by factors within the model; and E is a set of structural equations that express the value of each endogenous variable as a function of the values of the other variables in U and V. [2]
Aristotle defined a taxonomy of causality, including material, formal, efficient and final causes. Hume rejected Aristotle's taxonomy in favor of counterfactuals. At one point, he denied that objects have "powers" that make one a cause and another an effect. Later he adopted "if the first object had not been, the second had never existed" ("but-for" causation). [4]
In the late 19th century, the discipline of statistics began to form. After a years-long effort to identify causal rules for domains such as biological inheritance, Galton introduced the concept of mean regression (epitomized by the sophomore slump in sports) which later led him to the non-causal concept of correlation. [4]
As a positivist, Pearson expunged the notion of causality from much of science as an unprovable special case of association and introduced the correlation coefficient as the metric of association. He wrote, "Force as a cause of motion is exactly the same as a tree god as a cause of growth" and that causation was only a "fetish among the inscrutable arcana of modern science". Pearson founded Biometrika and the Biometrics Lab at University College London, which became the world leader in statistics. [4]
In 1908 Hardy and Weinberg solved the problem of trait stability that had led Galton to abandon causality, by resurrecting Mendelian inheritance. [4]
In 1921 Wright's path analysis became the theoretical ancestor of causal modeling and causal graphs. [5] He developed this approach while attempting to untangle the relative impacts of heredity, development and environment on guinea pig coat patterns. He backed up his then-heretical claims by showing how such analyses could explain the relationship between guinea pig birth weight, in utero time and litter size. Opposition to these ideas by prominent statisticians led them to be ignored for the following 40 years (except among animal breeders). Instead scientists relied on correlations, partly at the behest of Wright's critic (and leading statistician), Fisher. [4] One exception was Burks, a student who in 1926 was the first to apply path diagrams to represent a mediating influence (mediator) and to assert that holding a mediator constant induces errors. She may have invented path diagrams independently. [4] : 304
In 1923, Neyman introduced the concept of a potential outcome, but his paper was not translated from Polish to English until 1990. [4] : 271
In 1958 Cox warned that controlling for a variable Z is valid only if it is highly unlikely to be affected by independent variables. [4] : 154
In the 1960s, Duncan, Blalock, Goldberger and others rediscovered path analysis. While reading Blalock's work on path diagrams, Duncan remembered a lecture by Ogburn twenty years earlier that mentioned a paper by Wright that in turn mentioned Burks. [4] : 308
Sociologists originally called causal models structural equation modeling, but once it became a rote method, it lost its utility, leading some practitioners to reject any relationship to causality. Economists adopted the algebraic part of path analysis, calling it simultaneous equation modeling. However, economists still avoided attributing causal meaning to their equations. [4]
Sixty years after his first paper, Wright published a piece that recapitulated it, following Karlin et al.'s critique, which objected that it handled only linear relationships and that robust, model-free presentations of data were more revealing. [4]
In 1973 Lewis advocated replacing correlation with but-for causality (counterfactuals). He referred to humans' ability to envision alternative worlds in which a cause did or not occur, and in which an effect appeared only following its cause. [4] : 266 In 1974 Rubin introduced the notion of "potential outcomes" as a language for asking causal questions. [4] : 269
In 1983 Cartwright proposed that any factor that is "causally relevant" to an effect be conditioned on, moving beyond simple probability as the only guide. [4] : 48
In 1986 Baron and Kenny introduced principles for detecting and evaluating mediation in a system of linear equations. As of 2014 their paper was the 33rd most-cited of all time. [4] : 324 That year Greenland and Robins introduced the "exchangeability" approach to handling confounding by considering a counterfactual. They proposed assessing what would have happened to the treatment group if they had not received the treatment and comparing that outcome to that of the control group. If they matched, confounding was said to be absent. [4] : 154
Pearl's causal metamodel involves a three-level abstraction he calls the ladder of causation. The lowest level, Association (seeing/observing), entails the sensing of regularities or patterns in the input data, expressed as correlations. The middle level, Intervention (doing), predicts the effects of deliberate actions, expressed as causal relationships. The highest level, Counterfactuals (imagining), involves constructing a theory of (part of) the world that explains why specific actions have specific effects and what happens in the absence of such actions. [4]
One object is associated with another if observing one changes the probability of observing the other. Example: shoppers who buy toothpaste are more likely to also buy dental floss. Mathematically:
or the probability of (purchasing) floss given (the purchase of) toothpaste. Associations can also be measured via computing the correlation of the two events. Associations have no causal implications. One event could cause the other, the reverse could be true, or both events could be caused by some third event (unhappy hygienist shames shopper into treating their mouth better ). [4]
This level asserts specific causal relationships between events. Causality is assessed by experimentally performing some action that affects one of the events. Example: after doubling the price of toothpaste, what would be the new probability of purchasing? Causality cannot be established by examining history (of price changes) because the price change may have been for some other reason that could itself affect the second event (a tariff that increases the price of both goods). Mathematically:
where do is an operator that signals the experimental intervention (doubling the price). [4] The operator indicates performing the minimal change in the world necessary to create the intended effect, a "mini-surgery" on the model with as little change from reality as possible. [6]
The highest level, counterfactual, involves consideration of an alternate version of a past event, or what would happen under different circumstances for the same experimental unit. For example, what is the probability that, if a store had doubled the price of floss, the toothpaste-purchasing shopper would still have bought it?
Counterfactuals can indicate the existence of a causal relationship. Models that can answer counterfactuals allow precise interventions whose consequences can be predicted. At the extreme, such models are accepted as physical laws (as in the laws of physics, e.g., inertia, which says that if force is not applied to a stationary object, it will not move). [4]
Statistics revolves around the analysis of relationships among multiple variables. Traditionally, these relationships are described as correlations, associations without any implied causal relationships. Causal models attempt to extend this framework by adding the notion of causal relationships, in which changes in one variable cause changes in others. [2]
Twentieth century definitions of causality relied purely on probabilities/associations. One event () was said to cause another if it raises the probability of the other (). Mathematically this is expressed as:
Such definitions are inadequate because other relationships (e.g., a common cause for and ) can satisfy the condition. Causality is relevant to the second ladder step. Associations are on the first step and provide only evidence to the latter. [4]
A later definition attempted to address this ambiguity by conditioning on background factors. Mathematically:
where is the set of background variables and represents the values of those variables in a specific context. However, the required set of background variables is indeterminate (multiple sets may increase the probability), as long as probability is the only criterion[ clarification needed ]. [4]
Other attempts to define causality include Granger causality, a statistical hypothesis test that causality (in economics) can be assessed by measuring the ability to predict the future values of one time series using prior values of another time series. [4]
A cause can be necessary, sufficient, contributory or some combination. [7]
For x to be a necessary cause of y, the presence of y must imply the prior occurrence of x. The presence of x, however, does not imply that y will occur. [8] Necessary causes are also known as "but-for" causes, as in y would not have occurred but for the occurrence of x. [4] : 261
For x to be a sufficient cause of y, the presence of x must imply the subsequent occurrence of y. However, another cause z may independently cause y. Thus the presence of y does not require the prior occurrence of x. [8]
For x to be a contributory cause of y, the presence of x must increase the likelihood of y. If the likelihood is 100%, then x is instead called sufficient. A contributory cause may also be necessary. [9]
A causal diagram is a directed graph that displays causal relationships between variables in a causal model. A causal diagram includes a set of variables (or nodes). Each node is connected by an arrow to one or more other nodes upon which it has a causal influence. An arrowhead delineates the direction of causality, e.g., an arrow connecting variables and with the arrowhead at indicates that a change in causes a change in (with an associated probability). A path is a traversal of the graph between two nodes following causal arrows. [4]
Causal diagrams include causal loop diagrams, directed acyclic graphs, and Ishikawa diagrams. [4]
Causal diagrams are independent of the quantitative probabilities that inform them. Changes to those probabilities (e.g., due to technological improvements) do not require changes to the model. [4]
Causal models have formal structures with elements with specific properties. [4]
The three types of connections of three nodes are linear chains, branching forks and merging colliders. [4]
Chains are straight line connections with arrows pointing from cause to effect. In this model, is a mediator in that it mediates the change that would otherwise have on . [4] : 113
In forks, one cause has multiple effects. The two effects have a common cause. There exists a (non-causal) spurious correlation between and that can be eliminated by conditioning on (for a specific value of ). [4] : 114
"Conditioning on " means "given " (i.e., given a value of ).
An elaboration of a fork is the confounder:
In such models, is a common cause of and (which also causes ), making the confounder[ clarification needed ]. [4] : 114
In colliders, multiple causes affect one outcome. Conditioning on (for a specific value of ) often reveals a non-causal negative correlation between and . This negative correlation has been called collider bias and the "explain-away" effect as explains away the correlation between and . [4] : 115 The correlation can be positive in the case where contributions from both and are necessary to affect . [4] : 197
A mediator node modifies the effect of other causes on an outcome (as opposed to simply affecting the outcome). [4] : 113 For example, in the chain example above, is a mediator, because it modifies the effect of (an indirect cause of ) on (the outcome).
A confounder node affects multiple outcomes, creating a positive correlation among them. [4] : 114
An instrumental variable is one that: [4] : 246
Regression coefficients can serve as estimates of the causal effect of an instrumental variable on an outcome as long as that effect is not confounded. In this way, instrumental variables allow causal factors to be quantified without data on confounders. [4] : 249
For example, given the model:
is an instrumental variable, because it has a path to the outcome and is unconfounded, e.g., by .
In the above example, if and take binary values, then the assumption that does not occur is called monotonicity[ clarification needed ]. [4] : 253
Refinements to the technique[ clarification needed ] include creating an instrument[ clarification needed ] by conditioning on other variable[ clarification needed ] to block[ clarification needed ] the paths[ clarification needed ] between the instrument and the confounder[ clarification needed ] and combining multiple variables to form a single instrument[ clarification needed ]. [4] : 257
Definition: Mendelian randomization uses measured variation in genes of known function to examine the causal effect of a modifiable exposure on disease in observational studies. [10] [11]
Because genes vary randomly across populations, presence of a gene typically qualifies as an instrumental variable, implying that in many cases, causality can be quantified using regression on an observational study. [4] : 255
Independence conditions are rules for deciding whether two variables are independent of each other. Variables are independent if the values of one do not directly affect the values of the other. Multiple causal models can share independence conditions. For example, the models
and
have the same independence conditions, because conditioning on leaves and independent. However, the two models do not have the same meaning and can be falsified based on data (that is, if observational data show an association between and after conditioning on , then both models are incorrect). Conversely, data cannot show which of these two models are correct, because they have the same independence conditions.
Conditioning on a variable is a mechanism for conducting hypothetical experiments. Conditioning on a variable involves analyzing the values of other variables for a given value of the conditioned variable. In the first example, conditioning on implies that observations for a given value of should show no dependence between and . If such a dependence exists, then the model is incorrect. Non-causal models cannot make such distinctions, because they do not make causal assertions. [4] : 129–130
An essential element of correlational study design is to identify potentially confounding influences on the variable under study, such as demographics. These variables are controlled for to eliminate those influences. However, the correct list of confounding variables cannot be determined a priori. It is thus possible that a study may control for irrelevant variables or even (indirectly) the variable under study. [4] : 139
Causal models offer a robust technique for identifying appropriate confounding variables. Formally, Z is a confounder if "Y is associated with Z via paths not going through X". These can often be determined using data collected for other studies. Mathematically, if
X and Y are confounded (by some confounder variable Z). [4] : 151
Earlier, allegedly incorrect definitions of confounder include: [4] : 152
The latter is flawed in that given that in the model:
Z matches the definition, but is a mediator, not a confounder, and is an example of controlling for the outcome.
In the model
Traditionally, B was considered to be a confounder, because it is associated with X and with Y but is not on a causal path nor is it a descendant of anything on a causal path. Controlling for B causes it to become a confounder. This is known as M-bias. [4] : 161
For analysing the causal effect of X on Y in a causal model all confounder variables must be addressed (deconfounding). To identify the set of confounders, (1) every noncausal path between X and Y must be blocked by this set; (2) without disrupting any causal paths; and (3) without creating any spurious paths. [4] : 158
Definition: a backdoor path from variable X to Y is any path from X to Y that starts with an arrow pointing to X. [4] : 158
Definition: Given an ordered pair of variables (X,Y) in a model, a set of confounder variables Z satisfies the backdoor criterion if (1) no confounder variable Z is a descendent of X and (2) all backdoor paths between X and Y are blocked by the set of confounders.
If the backdoor criterion is satisfied for (X,Y), X and Y are deconfounded by the set of confounder variables. It is not necessary to control for any variables other than the confounders. [4] : 158 The backdoor criterion is a sufficient but not necessary condition to find a set of variables Z to decounfound the analysis of the causal effect of X on y.
When the causal model is a plausible representation of reality and the backdoor criterion is satisfied, then partial regression coefficients can be used as (causal) path coefficients (for linear relationships). [4] : 223 [12]
If the elements of a blocking path are all unobservable, the backdoor path is not calculable, but if all forward paths from have elements where no open paths connect , then , the set of all s, can measure . Effectively, there are conditions where can act as a proxy for .
Definition: a frontdoor path is a direct causal path for which data is available for all , [4] : 226 intercepts all directed paths to , there are no unblocked paths from to , and all backdoor paths from to are blocked by . [13]
The following converts a do expression into a do-free expression by conditioning on the variables along the front-door path. [4] : 226
Presuming data for these observable probabilities is available, the ultimate probability can be computed without an experiment, regardless of the existence of other confounding paths and without backdoor adjustment. [4] : 226
Queries are questions asked based on a specific model. They are generally answered via performing experiments (interventions). Interventions take the form of fixing the value of one variable in a model and observing the result. Mathematically, such queries take the form (from the example): [4] : 8
where the do operator indicates that the experiment explicitly modified the price of toothpaste. Graphically, this blocks any causal factors that would otherwise affect that variable. Diagramatically, this erases all causal arrows pointing at the experimental variable. [4] : 40
More complex queries are possible, in which the do operator is applied (the value is fixed) to multiple variables.
This article needs attention from an expert in Mathematics. The specific problem is: needed to understand do-Operator, see https://www.pymc.io/projects/examples/en/latest/causal_inference/interventional_distribution.html.(May 2024) |
The do calculus is the set of manipulations that are available to transform one expression into another, with the general goal of transforming expressions that contain the do operator into expressions that do not. Expressions that do not include the do operator can be estimated from observational data alone, without the need for an experimental intervention, which might be expensive, lengthy or even unethical (e.g., asking subjects to take up smoking). [4] : 231 The set of rules is complete (it can be used to derive every true statement in this system). [4] : 237 An algorithm can determine whether, for a given model, a solution is computable in polynomial time. [4] : 238
The calculus includes three rules for the transformation of conditional probability expressions involving the do operator.
Rule 1 permits the addition or deletion of observations.: [4] : 235
in the case that the variable set Z blocks all paths from W to Y and all arrows leading into X have been deleted. [4] : 234
Rule 2 permits the replacement of an intervention with an observation or vice versa.: [4] : 235
in the case that Z satisfies the back-door criterion. [4] : 234
Rule 3 permits the deletion or addition of interventions.: [4]
in the case where no causal paths connect X and Y. [4] : 234 : 235
The rules do not imply that any query can have its do operators removed. In those cases, it may be possible to substitute a variable that is subject to manipulation (e.g., diet) in place of one that is not (e.g., blood cholesterol), which can then be transformed to remove the do. Example:
Counterfactuals consider possibilities that are not found in data, such as whether a nonsmoker would have developed cancer had they instead been a heavy smoker. They are the highest step on Pearl's causality ladder.
Definition: A potential outcome for a variable Y is "the value Y would have taken for individual[ clarification needed ]u, had X been assigned the value x". Mathematically: [4] : 270
The potential outcome is defined at the level of the individual u. [4] : 270
The conventional approach to potential outcomes is data-, not model-driven, limiting its ability to untangle causal relationships. It treats causal questions as problems of missing data and gives incorrect answers to even standard scenarios. [4] : 275
In the context of causal models, potential outcomes are interpreted causally, rather than statistically.
The first law of causal inference states that the potential outcome
can be computed by modifying causal model M (by deleting arrows into X) and computing the outcome for some x. Formally: [4] : 280
Examining a counterfactual using a causal model involves three steps. [14] The approach is valid regardless of the form of the model relationships, linear or otherwise. When the model relationships are fully specified, point values can be computed. In other cases (e.g., when only probabilities are available) a probability-interval statement, such as non-smoker x would have a 10-20% chance of cancer, can be computed. [4] : 279
Given the model:
the equations for calculating the values of A and C derived from regression analysis or another technique can be applied, substituting known values from an observation and fixing the value of other variables (the counterfactual). [4] : 278
Apply abductive reasoning (logical inference that uses observation to find the simplest/most likely explanation) to estimate u, the proxy for the unobserved variables on the specific observation that supports the counterfactual. [4] : 278 Compute the probability of u given the propositional evidence.
For a specific observation, use the do operator to establish the counterfactual (e.g., m=0), modifying the equations accordingly. [4] : 278
Calculate the values of the output (y) using the modified equations. [4] : 278
Direct and indirect (mediated) causes can only be distinguished via conducting counterfactuals. [4] : 301 Understanding mediation requires holding the mediator constant while intervening on the direct cause. In the model
M mediates X's influence on Y, while X also has an unmediated effect on Y. Thus M is held constant, while do(X) is computed.
The Mediation Fallacy instead involves conditioning on the mediator if the mediator and the outcome are confounded, as they are in the above model.
For linear models, the indirect effect can be computed by taking the product of all the path coefficients along a mediated pathway. The total indirect effect is computed by the sum of the individual indirect effects. For linear models mediation is indicated when the coefficients of an equation fitted without including the mediator vary significantly from an equation that includes it. [4] : 324
In experiments on such a model, the controlled direct effect (CDE) is computed by forcing the value of the mediator M (do(M = 0)) and randomly assigning some subjects to each of the values of X (do(X=0), do(X=1), ...) and observing the resulting values of Y. [4] : 317
Each value of the mediator has a corresponding CDE.
However, a better experiment is to compute the natural direct effect. (NDE) This is the effect determined by leaving the relationship between X and M untouched while intervening on the relationship between X and Y. [4] : 318
For example, consider the direct effect of increasing dental hygienist visits (X) from every other year to every year, which encourages flossing (M). Gums (Y) get healthier, either because of the hygienist (direct) or the flossing (mediator/indirect). The experiment is to continue flossing while skipping the hygienist visit.
The indirect effect of X on Y is the "increase we would see in Y while holding X constant and increasing M to whatever value M would attain under a unit increase in X". [4] : 328
Indirect effects cannot be "controlled" because the direct path cannot be disabled by holding another variable constant. The natural indirect effect (NIE) is the effect on gum health (Y) from flossing (M). The NIE is calculated as the sum of (floss and no-floss cases) of the difference between the probability of flossing given the hygienist and without the hygienist, or: [4] : 321
The above NDE calculation includes counterfactual subscripts (). For nonlinear models, the seemingly obvious equivalence [4] : 322
does not apply because of anomalies such as threshold effects and binary values. However,
works for all model relationships (linear and nonlinear). It allows NDE to then be calculated directly from observational data, without interventions or use of counterfactual subscripts. [4] : 326
Causal models provide a vehicle for integrating data across datasets, known as transport, even though the causal models (and the associated data) differ. E.g., survey data can be merged with randomized, controlled trial data. [4] : 352 Transport offers a solution to the question of external validity, whether a study can be applied in a different context.
Where two models match on all relevant variables and data from one model is known to be unbiased, data from one population can be used to draw conclusions about the other. In other cases, where data is known to be biased, reweighting can allow the dataset to be transported. In a third case, conclusions can be drawn from an incomplete dataset. In some cases, data from studies of multiple populations can be combined (via transportation) to allow conclusions about an unmeasured population. In some cases, combining estimates (e.g., P(W|X)) from multiple studies can increase the precision of a conclusion. [4] : 355
Do-calculus provides a general criterion for transport: A target variable can be transformed into another expression via a series of do-operations that does not involve any "difference-producing" variables (those that distinguish the two populations). [4] : 355 An analogous rule applies to studies that have relevantly different participants. [4] : 356
Any causal model can be implemented as a Bayesian network. Bayesian networks can be used to provide the inverse probability of an event (given an outcome, what are the probabilities of a specific cause). This requires preparation of a conditional probability table, showing all possible inputs and outcomes with their associated probabilities. [4] : 119
For example, given a two variable model of Disease and Test (for the disease) the conditional probability table takes the form: [4] : 117
Test | ||
---|---|---|
Disease | Positive | Negative |
Negative | 12 | 88 |
Positive | 73 | 27 |
According to this table, when a patient does not have the disease, the probability of a positive test is 12%.
While this is tractable for small problems, as the number of variables and their associated states increase, the probability table (and associated computation time) increases exponentially. [4] : 121
Bayesian networks are used commercially in applications such as wireless data error correction and DNA analysis. [4] : 122
A different conceptualization of causality involves the notion of invariant relationships. In the case of identifying handwritten digits, digit shape controls meaning, thus shape and meaning are the invariants. Changing the shape changes the meaning. Other properties do not (e.g., color). This invariance should carry across datasets generated in different contexts (the non-invariant properties form the context). Rather than learning (assessing causality) using pooled data sets, learning on one and testing on another can help distinguish variant from invariant properties. [15]
Causality is an influence by which one event, process, state, or object (acause) contributes to the production of another event, process, state, or object (an effect) where the cause is partly responsible for the effect, and the effect is partly dependent on the cause. In general, a process has many causes, which are also said to be causal factors for it, and all lie in its past. An effect can in turn be a cause of, or causal factor for, many other effects, which all lie in its future. Some writers have held that causality is metaphysically prior to notions of time and space.
Simpson's paradox is a phenomenon in probability and statistics in which a trend appears in several groups of data but disappears or reverses when the groups are combined. This result is often encountered in social-science and medical-science statistics, and is particularly problematic when frequency data are unduly given causal interpretations. The paradox can be resolved when confounding variables and causal relations are appropriately addressed in the statistical modeling.
A Bayesian network is a probabilistic graphical model that represents a set of variables and their conditional dependencies via a directed acyclic graph (DAG). While it is one of several forms of causal notation, causal networks are special cases of Bayesian networks. Bayesian networks are ideal for taking an event that occurred and predicting the likelihood that any one of several possible known causes was the contributing factor. For example, a Bayesian network could represent the probabilistic relationships between diseases and symptoms. Given symptoms, the network can be used to compute the probabilities of the presence of various diseases.
In physics, the principle of locality states that an object is influenced directly only by its immediate surroundings. A theory that includes the principle of locality is said to be a "local theory". This is an alternative to the concept of instantaneous, or "non-local" action at a distance. Locality evolved out of the field theories of classical physics. The idea is that for a cause at one point to have an effect at another point, something in the space between those points must mediate the action. To exert an influence, something, such as a wave or particle, must travel through the space between the two points, carrying the influence.
In statistics, a spurious relationship or spurious correlation is a mathematical relationship in which two or more events or variables are associated but not causally related, due to either coincidence or the presence of a certain third, unseen factor.
Counterfactual conditionals are conditional sentences which discuss what would have been true under different circumstances, e.g. "If Peter believed in ghosts, he would be afraid to be here." Counterfactuals are contrasted with indicatives, which are generally restricted to discussing open possibilities. Counterfactuals are characterized grammatically by their use of fake tense morphology, which some languages use in combination with other kinds of morphology including aspect and mood.
In probability theory, conditional independence describes situations wherein an observation is irrelevant or redundant when evaluating the certainty of a hypothesis. Conditional independence is usually formulated in terms of conditional probability, as a special case where the probability of the hypothesis given the uninformative observation is equal to the probability without. If is the hypothesis, and and are observations, conditional independence can be stated as an equality:
In statistics, econometrics, epidemiology and related disciplines, the method of instrumental variables (IV) is used to estimate causal relationships when controlled experiments are not feasible or when a treatment is not successfully delivered to every unit in a randomized experiment. Intuitively, IVs are used when an explanatory variable of interest is correlated with the error term (endogenous), in which case ordinary least squares and ANOVA give biased results. A valid instrument induces changes in the explanatory variable but has no independent effect on the dependent variable and is not correlated with the error term, allowing a researcher to uncover the causal effect of the explanatory variable on the dependent variable.
The Granger causality test is a statistical hypothesis test for determining whether one time series is useful in forecasting another, first proposed in 1969. Ordinarily, regressions reflect "mere" correlations, but Clive Granger argued that causality in economics could be tested for by measuring the ability to predict the future values of a time series using prior values of another time series. Since the question of "true causality" is deeply philosophical, and because of the post hoc ergo propter hoc fallacy of assuming that one thing preceding another can be used as a proof of causation, econometricians assert that the Granger test finds only "predictive causality". Using the term "causality" alone is a misnomer, as Granger-causality is better described as "precedence", or, as Granger himself later claimed in 1977, "temporally related". Rather than testing whether Xcauses Y, the Granger causality tests whether X forecastsY.
This glossary of statistics and probability is a list of definitions of terms and concepts used in the mathematical sciences of statistics and probability, their sub-disciplines, and related fields. For additional related terms, see Glossary of mathematics and Glossary of experimental design.
In causal inference, a confounder is a variable that influences both the dependent variable and independent variable, causing a spurious association. Confounding is a causal concept, and as such, cannot be described in terms of correlations or associations. The existence of confounders is an important quantitative explanation why correlation does not imply causation. Some notations are explicitly designed to identify the existence, possible existence, or non-existence of confounders in causal relationships between elements of a system.
In statistics, ignorability is a feature of an experiment design whereby the method of data collection does not depend on the missing data. A missing data mechanism such as a treatment assignment or survey sampling strategy is "ignorable" if the missing data matrix, which indicates which variables are observed or missing, is independent of the missing data conditional on the observed data.
In statistics, a mediation model seeks to identify and explain the mechanism or process that underlies an observed relationship between an independent variable and a dependent variable via the inclusion of a third hypothetical variable, known as a mediator variable. Rather than a direct causal relationship between the independent variable and the dependent variable, which is often false, a mediation model proposes that the independent variable influences the mediator variable, which in turn influences the dependent variable. Thus, the mediator variable serves to clarify the nature of the relationship between the independent and dependent variables.
In causal models, controlling for a variable means binning data according to measured values of the variable. This is typically done so that the variable can no longer act as a confounder in, for example, an observational study or experiment.
In the statistical analysis of observational data, propensity score matching (PSM) is a statistical matching technique that attempts to estimate the effect of a treatment, policy, or other intervention by accounting for the covariates that predict receiving the treatment. PSM attempts to reduce the bias due to confounding variables that could be found in an estimate of the treatment effect obtained from simply comparing outcomes among units that received the treatment versus those that did not. Paul R. Rosenbaum and Donald Rubin introduced the technique in 1983.
Causal reasoning is the process of identifying causality: the relationship between a cause and its effect. The study of causality extends from ancient philosophy to contemporary neuropsychology; assumptions about the nature of causality may be shown to be functions of a previous event preceding a later one. The first known protoscientific study of cause and effect occurred in Aristotle's Physics. Causal inference is an example of causal reasoning.
Causal inference is the process of determining the independent, actual effect of a particular phenomenon that is a component of a larger system. The main difference between causal inference and inference of association is that causal inference analyzes the response of an effect variable when a cause of the effect variable is changed. The study of why things occur is called etiology, and can be described using the language of scientific causal notation. Causal inference is said to provide the evidence of causality theorized by causal reasoning.
In statistics, econometrics, epidemiology, genetics and related disciplines, causal graphs are probabilistic graphical models used to encode assumptions about the data-generating process.
The Book of Why: The New Science of Cause and Effect is a 2018 nonfiction book by computer scientist Judea Pearl and writer Dana Mackenzie. The book explores the subject of causality and causal inference from statistical and philosophical points of view for a general audience.
Causal notation is notation used to express cause and effect.