Conjectural history

Last updated

Conjectural history is a type of historiography isolated in the 1790s by Dugald Stewart, who termed it "theoretical or conjectural history," as prevalent in the historians and early social scientists of the Scottish Enlightenment. As Stewart saw it, such history makes space for speculation about causes of events, by postulating natural causes that could have had such an effect. His concept was to be identified closely with the French terminology histoire raisonnée, and the usage of "natural history" by David Hume in his work The Natural History of Religion . It was related to "philosophical history", a broader-based kind of historical theorising, but concentrated on the early history of man in a type of rational reconstruction that had little contact with evidence. [1] [2] [3]

Contents

Such conjectural history was the antithesis of the narrative history being written at the time by Edward Gibbon and William Robertson. Stewart defended it as more universal in its application to humankind, even at the cost of detailed documentation. [4] It was not concerned with the political narrative and public life, but saw itself as an investigative "moral science". [5] General philosophical history was somewhat closer to narrative history than conjectural history could be, with its reliance in part on tenuous arguments on the nature of feudalism and early ethnographical reports from European travellers. [6] For Stewart the Dissertation on the Origin of Languages by Adam Smith was an important example. [7] To justify the procedures of conjectural history, there needed to be an assumption of the uniformity of human nature, or as Stewart put it, the "capacities of the human mind". [8]

Conjectural history has been identified as "the core of a theory" of progress within Scottish philosophical history of the period. [9] Pocock writes that Scottish conjectural history was "of considerable importance to Gibbon and the creation of philosophical historiography". [10] By the 1780s there were European historians of culture who worked in a different way, preferring an inductive method to the pure deductions of conjectural history. [11] In the later development of anthropology and archaeology, opposition to the whole "conjectural history" tradition led to the development of culture history. [12]

Early Modern context

There was nothing new in the idea of stages of society on its own, but social thinking itself was changing in Early Modern Europe, particularly on civil society in its components, civility and "society".

Models and the "savage"

Hodgen comments, in a chapter From Hierarchy to History, on the widespread use of "conjectural series" for historical explanation in the Early Modern period. The great chain of being was a static idea. "Stage series" had roots in classical thought, but might be associated with cyclic models, or incorporate ideas of decline with those of progress. She writes that in time

... it seems certain that hierarchical ideas, temporalized to suit the needs of the conjectural historian of culture, were mixed with historical assumptions concerning the savage as a conjectural first member of these conjectural series. [13]

Early Modern natural history

While the Natural History of Pliny the Elder was a classical Roman encyclopedic work, "natural history" had several different meanings in the Early Modern period. The one relevant in this article is the Baconian natural history, i.e. a systematic collection of observable information on natural phenomena. A natural history did not belong to natural philosophy, which was theoretical. [14]

Histoire raisonnée

The histoire raisonnée was a genre of historical writing developed in France in the 17th century, with concerns for the individual in social context, and the description of culture and customs as integral to history. It grew out of humanist historiography with its close relationship to classical Roman and Greek models, but brought to the surface social matters, in particular as they could explain the motivations of individuals. With Géraud de Cordemoy there came an interest in causality as playing a part in historical movement, as distinct from the humanist acceptance of personal fates being subject to Fortune. [15]

Stadial history

Contemporary terminology is stadial history, or in other words the discussion of stages of society by theoretical means (see sociocultural evolution#Stadial theory). Stadial theory as an innovation is attributed to the jurist Samuel Pufendorf. [16] Grotius had already used conjectural history to discuss Aquinas on private property. [17]

Some basic conjectural history on human civilization was therefore discussed in the 17th century. Later Jean-Jacques Rousseau rejected the concept of the state of nature, and with Count Buffon debated the rise of civilization. The Scottish contribution then took the theory to a new level, with its anthropocentrism and detailed explanations of human manipulation of nature. [18] It laid emphasis on a typical society at its beginnings, regarding evidence from contemporary reports (particularly of Native Americans) as valid. [19]

Conjectural histories of language and writing

Adam Smith in lectures on rhetoric, given from 1748, [20] advanced a speculative history of language; he wrote that he had been prompted by a 1747 work of Gabriel Girard. He was then interested in our awareness of literary style. [21] This is the example that Dugald Stewart took up in coining the phrase "conjectural history". Elements would have been recognised at the time as drawing on the Bible, and in classical literature Lucretius; it is now considered Smith was influenced by Montesquieu on law and government. The theory on language and its typology over time has been seen as typical of Smith's historical approach; and even the foundation of his later well-known work on political economy. Caveats have also been entered, by David Raphael: it cannot be stretched to Smith's history of astronomy; and the term can be seen as a misnomer. [22] [23]

Monboddo, on the other hand, wrote at length a conjectural history of language because he emphasised the history of manners. [24] William Warburton had proposed a stadial conjectural history of writing in his Divine Legation of Moses , a work supporting biblical authority, around 1740. It was taken up in France after the translation in Essai sur les hiéroglyphes des Égyptiens . Where writing moved from pictograms to alphabets, he saw language use as having moved analogously from gestures to forms and figures of speech. [25]

The four stages theory

The term "conjectural history" was not generally accepted in Stewart's time. [26] There was an orthodox four stages theory of society, the stages being:

  1. hunting;
  2. pasturage;
  3. agriculture; and
  4. commerce.

This ladder-like ordering was taken to be a strict, linear progression, or unilineal evolution. Some economic determinism applied, in the sense that the baseline of subsistence was assumed to have a serious effect on social matters. The stages were supposed to represent progress on a moral level, as well as that of economic complexity. French as well as Scottish Enlightenment writers subscribed to such a pattern. [27]

The invention of this type of theory (three or four stages) is attributed to a number of European writers from the 1750s onwards, such as Adam Smith, Turgot and Vico. [28] In the Scottish context it appears in works from 1758 by David Dalrymple and Lord Kames; it has been argued that their source was the Edinburgh lectures of Smith on jurisprudence. [29] In France it was published at much the same time, also, by Claude Pierre Goujet, Claude Adrien Helvétius, and François Quesnay. [16] Smith's "natural progress of opulence" is a closely related theory. [30]

Representative works

Besides Adam Smith, prominent Scottish authors in the field of conjectural history included Adam Ferguson, David Hume, Lord Kames, John Millar, and Lord Monboddo, writing from the later 1750s to later 1770s. [31] Smith, Kames and Millar were content to adhere to the four stage theory. [32] Monboddo's stadial history was more complex, and very much more controversial. He included primates and feral children as material. [33] Robertson in his History of America moves between narrative and conjectural history. [34]

Adam Ferguson, An Essay on the History of Civil Society (1767)

Ferguson in this work attempted a rigorous identification of the hunter stage with the so-called barbarian or savage, and was very alive to the whole scheme as full of tensions within human possibility. [35] He argued against the foundation story in the style of classical history, proposing instead that unintended consequences could have more to do with the "establishment" of a society than a self-conscious law-giver. [36]

John Millar, Observations concerning the Distinction of Ranks in Society (1771)

Millar argued in terms of a "system of manners" associated with each of the four stages. [37] He also discussed the advance of freedom, and denounced slavery. [38] As property became more complex, it followed that government did so also. [39] Poovey states that this work makes apparent the relationship of conjectural history with the experimental moral philosophy of Thomas Reid and George Turnbull. [40]

Lord Kames, Sketches of the History of Man (1774)

Kames has been called the leader of Scottish conjectural history, and had objections he expressed in correspondence to both Rousseau and the approach of Montesquieu, as reducing the role of human nature, which he thought was not a constant but the goal of the investigation. [11] The connection was that conjectural history was to be used as a framework of a discussion of natural law. [26] In writing to Basel in search of a suitable opponent to Rousseau, Kames prompted a work from Isaak Iselin, Ueber die Geschichte der Menschheit (1764), which is also a conjectural history. [11] [41]

The Sketches was a collection of essays on social, cultural and political topics. [42] In it the author collected some ethnographic and miscellaneous information, assembling in particular a long chapter intended as a "history of women". [43] [44] There was a second edition (Edinburgh, 1778) and a third (Dublin, 1779). Kames was an early polygenist, or was an environmental monogenist only with scepticism about the adequacy of the theory. [45] In any case he argued that his approach could be reconciled with the scriptural ethnography, via the story of the Tower of Babel. [46] While he stated that he had collected materials for a history for 30 years, Kames's work as written up was unsystematic, even rambling. [47] His scheme of conjectural history includes the idea that the providential order allows the historian to write in the absence of a full factual basis. [48] A German translation by Anton Ernst Klausing appeared as Versuche über die Geschichte des Menschen from 1774. [49]

Later developments

The tradition comes to an end

Mainstream conjectural and philosophical history, in the Scottish style, hardly survived as a living tradition into the 1790s. Works went out of print; younger authors such as John Adams, William Alexander and John Logan failed to renew the ideas, with Alexander's History of Women (1779) being criticised as shallow. [50] [51] Dugald Stewart's formulation of conjectural history was published in 1794, in his Account of Adam Smith for the Transactions of the Royal Society of Edinburgh. [52] The question has been raised as to Stewart's intention then in describing the tradition in that way, and John Burrow has argued that he wished to dissociate Smith from political radicalism. [53]

Where stadial theory appeared in later authors, the original thrust was distorted. [50] Hopfl has said that the heirs were James Mill, John Stuart Mill, and Auguste Comte. [54] Hawthorne writes instead of the historical/sociological insights of the Scots being lost in the British context, despite the "tension between a 'natural' account of civil society and a developing sense of the factual importance and moral difficulties of individualism" having become apparent, to utilitarianism and vaguer evolutionism. [55]

Religious opposition

The Encyclopædia Britannica, in its second edition but particularly in its third edition (1797), attacked the premises of conjectural history from a biblical angle. In the second edition James Tytler opposed the polygenist approach of Kames. The third edition, under the editorship of George Gleig, featured "Savage" as a new topic, and expanded articles "Society" and "Moral philosophy". Cross-referenced to theological and biblical topics, and to articles by David Doig who had answered Kames with Two Letters on the Savage State from 1775/6, these articles in particular argued the orthodox Christian case. Robert Heron contributed to the article "Society", and took aim at the four stages theory, claiming polygenism followed from it (in contradiction to the Bible). Further, the assumption of a baseline state of savagery also seemed to Heron to be implicated with polygenism; and he with Doig attacked the assumption as echoing Lucretius and Democritus, and godless materialist spontaneous generation of humankind, implicit in the whole idea of conjectural history. [56] The articles on "Beauty" and "Love" were also changed to remove the influence of Kames, as part of the consistent assertion of scriptural monogenism. [57]

Relationship to antiquarianism

Conjectural argument had a bad name in 18th century British antiquarian circles. An austere and sceptical approach centred on facts, as adopted by Richard Gough and James Douglas, was favoured in the second half of the century. [58] On the other hand, the interpretations of the stadial theory were quite welcome, and while popularised by the Scottish school, did not seem innovative in the sense of a break with Early Modern historiography, and concerns with natural law and civic humanism. The urban history of John Trussel was a precursor. The discussion of the breakdown of the feudal system was a topic of considerable antiquarian interest. [59] The stadial history was embraced by Thomas Pownall. [58]

Conjectural history of peoples

Charles Athanase Walckenaer in 1798 took up the four stage theory, augmented to five stages, by dividing "hunting" into "gathering" followed by a pure hunting stage. This was an effort to classify peoples of the world by development. [60] Early anthropology carried into the 19th century assumptions about the search for origins of civilisation, and unilineal evolution, as appropriate tools for investigating societies. It was widely assumed, further, that current "peoples" were a window into the past. These approaches were seen in Lewis Henry Morgan. Eventually, in the 20th century, field work and structural functionalism led to a rejection of the whole paradigm. [61]

"Scottish orientalism"

Related Research Articles

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Adam Smith</span> Scottish economist and philosopher (1723–1790)

Adam Smith was a Scottish economist and philosopher who was a pioneer in the thinking of political economy and key figure during the Scottish Enlightenment. Seen by some as "The Father of Economics" or "The Father of Capitalism", he wrote two classic works, The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759) and An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (1776). The latter, often abbreviated as The Wealth of Nations, is considered his magnum opus and the first modern work that treats economics as a comprehensive system and as an academic discipline. Smith refuses to explain the distribution of wealth and power in terms of God's will and instead appeals to natural, political, social, economic and technological factors and the interactions between them. Among other economic theories, the work introduced Smith's idea of absolute advantage.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">David Hume</span> Scottish philosopher. (1711–1776)

David Hume was a Scottish Enlightenment philosopher, historian, economist, librarian, and essayist, who is best known today for his highly influential system of philosophical empiricism, skepticism, and naturalism. Beginning with A Treatise of Human Nature (1739–40), Hume strove to create a naturalistic science of man that examined the psychological basis of human nature. Hume argued against the existence of innate ideas, positing that all human knowledge derives solely from experience. This places him with Francis Bacon, Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and George Berkeley as an empiricist.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Henry Home, Lord Kames</span> Scottish writer, philosopher, advocate, judge, and agricultural improver

Henry Home, Lord Kames was a Scottish writer, philosopher and judge who played a major role in Scotland's Agricultural Revolution. A central figure of the Scottish Enlightenment, he was a founding member of the Philosophical Society of Edinburgh and active in The Select Society. Home acted as patron to some of the most influential thinkers of the Scottish Enlightenment, including philosopher David Hume, economist Adam Smith, writer James Boswell, philosopher William Cullen and naturalist John Walker.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Science</span> Systematic endeavor for gaining knowledge

Science is a systematic endeavor that builds and organizes knowledge in the form of testable explanations and predictions about the universe.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Scottish Enlightenment</span> Intellectual movement in 18th–19th century Scotland

The Scottish Enlightenment was the period in 18th- and early-19th-century Scotland characterised by an outpouring of intellectual and scientific accomplishments. By the eighteenth century, Scotland had a network of parish schools in the Scottish Lowlands and five universities. The Enlightenment culture was based on close readings of new books, and intense discussions which took place daily at such intellectual gathering places in Edinburgh as The Select Society and, later, The Poker Club, as well as within Scotland's ancient universities.

Group rights, also known as collective rights, are rights held by a group as a whole rather than individually by its members; in contrast, individual rights are rights held by individual people; even if they are group-differentiated, which most rights are, they remain individual rights if the right-holders are the individuals themselves. Historically, group rights have been used both to infringe upon and to facilitate individual rights, and the concept remains controversial.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Dugald Stewart</span> Scottish philosopher and mathematician (1753-1828)

Dugald Stewart was a Scottish philosopher and mathematician. Today regarded as one of the most important figures of the later Scottish Enlightenment, he was renowned as a populariser of the work of Francis Hutcheson and Adam Smith. Trained in mathematics, medicine and philosophy, his lectures at the University of Edinburgh were widely disseminated by his many influential students. In 1783 he was a joint founder of the Royal Society of Edinburgh. In most contemporary documents he is referred to as Prof Dougal Stewart.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Adam Ferguson</span> Scottish philosopher and historian (1723–1816)

Adam Ferguson,, also known as Ferguson of Raith, was a Scottish philosopher and historian of the Scottish Enlightenment.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Matthew Stewart (mathematician)</span> Scottish mathematician (1717–1785)

Matthew Stewart FRS FRSE (1717–1785) was a Scottish mathematician and minister of the Church of Scotland.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">John Walker (natural historian)</span> Scottish minister and natural historian (1731–1803)

John Walker FRSE (1731–1803) was a Scottish minister and natural historian. He was Regius Professor of Natural history at the University of Edinburgh from 1779 to 1803. He was joint founder of the Royal Society of Edinburgh in 1783 and Moderator of the General Assembly of the Church of Scotland in 1790.

Jacques Claude Marie Vincent de Gournay, a French economist, became an intendant of commerce. Some historians of economics believe that he coined the phrase laissez faire, laissez passer. Evidence was to be found when the French State parted the West Indies Company privilege - monopoly - on the slave trade. He is also credited with coining the term "bureaucracy". Together with François Quesnay, whose disciple he was, he was a leader of the Physiocratic School.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">John Millar (philosopher)</span> Scottish philosopher, jurist and historian (1735–1801)

John Millar of Glasgow was a Scottish philosopher, historian and Regius Professor of Civil Law at the University of Glasgow from 1761 to 1800.

<i>How the Scots Invented the Modern World</i> Book by Arthur L. Herman

How the Scots Invented the Modern World: The True Story of How Western Europe's Poorest Nation Created Our World & Everything in It is a non-fiction book written by American historian Arthur Herman. The book examines the origins of the Scottish Enlightenment and what impact it had on the modern world. Herman focuses principally on individuals, presenting their biographies in the context of their individual fields and also in terms of the theme of Scottish contributions to the world.

Shannon C. Stimson is an American political theorist and historian of ideas, whose more recent work and teaching spans the economic and political thought of the early modern period through the nineteenth century. She is the Thomas and Dorothy Leavey Chair in the Government department at Georgetown University. Her academic posts have included appointments at Harvard University (1984-1991), UC Berkeley (1991-2014), the Fulbright Professorship in the United Kingdom, the Christensen Fellowship of St. Catherine's College, Oxford, the John K. Castle Chair in Ethics, Politics and Economics at Yale University and she has been a Distinguished Academic Visitor at Queens' College, Cambridge on two occasions. Her research has been supported through fellowships from the Mellon Foundation, the National Endowment for the Humanities, the American Association of University Women, as well as by several prize fellowships. Her articles have appeared in numerous edited volumes, journals of political thought, economics, the history of economic thought, and political science in America and Europe. She has served on the editorial boards of the American Political Science Review, the Adam Smith Review, and the Journal of Politics.

Scottish orientalism refers to the collective views of a group of Scottish scholars of oriental languages, informed by the Scottish Enlightenment, and applied to the culture and administration of the Indian subcontinent though the East India Company, from the end of the 18th century to the middle of the 19th century.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Scottish common sense realism</span> Realist school of philosophy

Scottish common sense realism, also known as the Scottish school of common sense, is a realist school of philosophy that originated in the ideas of Scottish philosophers Thomas Reid, Adam Ferguson, James Beattie, and Dugald Stewart during the 18th-century Scottish Enlightenment. Reid emphasized man's innate ability to perceive common ideas and that this process is inherent in and interdependent with judgement. Common sense, therefore, is the foundation of philosophical inquiry. Though best remembered for its opposition to the pervasive philosophy of David Hume, Scottish common sense philosophy is influential and evident in the works of Thomas Jefferson and late 18th-century American politics.

Events from the year 1828 in Scotland.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Basil William Douglas</span>

Basil William Douglas, Lord Daer FRSE (1763-1794) was a Scottish nobleman who, in his short life, developed a reputation as an agricultural improver and an advocate of parliamentary reform. He was an active member of, among other radical societies, the "Friends of the People". He is one of the small group of people to whom Robert Burns dedicated poetry.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Panmure House (Edinburgh)</span>

Panmure House is a 17th-century townhouse located in Edinburgh's Canongate. It is the only surviving residence of renowned Scottish philosopher Adam Smith, who lived there between 1778 and 1790. Situated close to the Scottish Parliament, in the heart of a UNESCO World Heritage Site, the House is an important monument of Scottish intellectual history. During his time living at Panmure House, Smith continued to study and write, producing four new editions of his magnum opus The Wealth of Nations between 1778 and 1789. He was still at work on the final edition of his 1759 master work, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, when he died at Panmure House in 1790. The House is now a centre for economic and social research and debate in Smith’s name, managed by Heriot-Watt University.

Ian Simpson Ross was a Scottish academic and biographer of Adam Smith.

References

Notes

  1. Adam Smith (1 May 1980). The Glasgow Edition of the Works and Correspondence of Adam Smith: III: Essays on Philosophical Subjects : With Dugald Stewart's 'Account of Adam Smith': With Dugald Stewart's 'Account of Adam Smith'. Oxford University Press. p. 293. ISBN   978-0-19-159117-4 . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  2. Gordon MacIntyre (1 September 2003). Dugald Stewart: The Pride and Ornament of Scotland. Sussex Academic Press. p. 253. ISBN   978-1-903900-34-5 . Retrieved 1 March 2013.
  3. Frank Palmeri (2003). Satire, History, Novel: Narrative Forms, 1665–1815. University of Delaware Press. pp. 231–2. ISBN   978-0-87413-829-0 . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  4. Nisbet and Costa, p. 629.
  5. Mark Salber Phillips (1 May 2000). Society and Sentiment: Genres of Historical Writing in Britain, 1740–1820 . Princeton University Press. p.  171. ISBN   978-1-4008-2362-8 . Retrieved 3 March 2013.
  6. Rosemary Sweet (1997). Writing of Urban Histories in 18th Century England. Oxford University Press. pp. 143–4. ISBN   978-0-19-820669-9 . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  7. Broadie, Alexander. "Scottish Philosophy in the 18th Century". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy .
  8. Alexander Broadie, ed. (1997). The Scottish Enlightenment: An Anthology. Canongate Books. pp. 25–6. ISBN   978-0-86241-738-3.
  9. Mark Salber Phillips (1 May 2000). Society and Sentiment: Genres of Historical Writing in Britain, 1740–1820 . Princeton University Press. pp.  171–2. ISBN   978-1-4008-2362-8 . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  10. Pocock, p. 305.
  11. 1 2 3 Michael C. Carhart (2007). The Science of Culture in Enlightenment Germany. Harvard University Press. pp. 159–60. ISBN   978-0-674-02617-9 . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  12. Dr Alan Barnard; Jonathan Spencer (1 September 2003). Encyclopedia of Social and Cultural Anthropology. Routledge. p. 898. ISBN   978-0-203-45803-7 . Retrieved 1 March 2013.
  13. Hodgen, p. 467.
  14. G. N. Cantor; M. J. S. Hodge, R. C. Olby; J. R. R. Christie (6 August 2012). Companion to the History of Modern Science. Routledge. p. 260. ISBN   978-1-134-97751-2 . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  15. Leffler, pp. 223–9.
  16. 1 2 Martin Fitzpatrick; Peter Jones; Christa Knellwolf; Iain McCalman (22 July 2004). Enlightenment World. Routledge. pp. 258–9. ISBN   978-1-134-60784-6 . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  17. Istvan Hont (2005). Jealousy Of Trade: International Competition and the Nation State in Historical Perspective. Harvard University Press. pp. 422–3. ISBN   978-0-674-01038-3 . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  18. Nathaniel Wolloch (1 May 2011). History and Nature in the Enlightenment: Praise of the Mastery of Nature in Eighteenth-Century Historical Literature. Ashgate Publishing, Ltd. pp. 92–4. ISBN   978-1-4094-2115-3 . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  19. Hopfl, pp. 24–5.
  20. Ian Simpson Ross (23 September 2010). The Life of Adam Smith. OUP Oxford. p. 80. ISBN   978-0-19-161394-4.
  21. Adam Smith: The Rhetoric of Propriety. SUNY Press. 2006. p. 83. ISBN   978-0-7914-8262-9.
  22. Ian Simpson Ross (23 September 2010). The Life of Adam Smith. OUP Oxford. pp. 85–7. ISBN   978-0-19-161394-4.
  23. Gordon Bigelow (20 November 2003). Fiction, Famine, and the Rise of Economics in Victorian Britain and Ireland. Cambridge University Press. p. 50. ISBN   978-1-139-44085-1.
  24. Mark Salber Phillips (1 May 2000). Society and Sentiment: Genres of Historical Writing in Britain, 1740–1820 . Princeton University Press. p.  151. ISBN   978-1-4008-2362-8.
  25. Jorge Cañizares-Esguerra (2001). How to Write the History of the New World: Histories, Epistemologies, and Identities in the Eighteenth-century Atlantic World. Stanford University Press. pp. 109–111. ISBN   978-0-8047-4693-9.
  26. 1 2 Karen O'Brien (5 June 1997). Narratives of Enlightenment: Cosmopolitan History from Voltaire to Gibbon . Cambridge University Press. pp.  132–3. ISBN   978-0-521-46533-5 . Retrieved 1 March 2013.
  27. Michael Rosen (1996). On Voluntary Servitude: False Consciousness and the Theory of Ideology. Harvard University Press. p. 117. ISBN   978-0-674-63779-5 . Retrieved 1 March 2013.
  28. Ter Ellingson (17 December 2000). The Myth of the Noble Savage. University of California Press. p. 159. ISBN   978-0-520-92592-2 . Retrieved 1 March 2013.
  29. Knud Haakonssen (6 March 2006). The Cambridge Companion to Adam Smith. Cambridge University Press. p. 225 note 18. ISBN   978-0-521-77924-1 . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  30. James Noggle (9 February 2012). The Temporality of Taste in Eighteenth-Century British Writing. Oxford University Press. p. 165. ISBN   978-0-19-964243-4 . Retrieved 1 March 2013.
  31. William Zachs (1992). Without Regard to Good Manners: A biography of Gilbert Stuart (1743–1786). Edinburgh University Press. p. 12. ISBN   978-0-7486-0319-0.
  32. Porscha Fermanis (2009). John Keats and the Ideas of the Enlightenment. Edinburgh University Press. p. 67. ISBN   978-0-7486-3780-5 . Retrieved 1 March 2013.
  33. Alexander Broadie (10 April 2003). The Cambridge Companion to the Scottish Enlightenment. Cambridge University Press. p. 82. ISBN   978-0-521-00323-0 . Retrieved 1 March 2013.
  34. Hopfl, p. 21.
  35. Pocock, pp. 330–5.
  36. Hopfl, p. 30.
  37. James Chandler (26 June 1999). England in 1819: The Politics of Literary Culture and the Case of Romantic Historicism. University of Chicago Press. p. 128. ISBN   978-0-226-10109-5 . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  38. Lynn Avery Hunt (28 February 2008). Measuring Time, Making History. Central European University Press. p. 60. ISBN   978-963-9776-14-2 . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  39. Porter, Roy (2001). Enlightenment. Penguin Books. p. 253. ISBN   978-0-14-025028-2.
  40. Mary Poovey (1 December 1998). A History of the Modern Fact: Problems of Knowledge in the Sciences of Wealth and Society. University of Chicago Press. p. 223. ISBN   978-0-226-67525-1 . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  41. Knud Haakonssen (2006). The Cambridge History of Eighteenth-Century Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. p. 1140 note 62. ISBN   978-0-521-86743-6 . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  42. Elizabeth Sauer (2010). Reading the Nation in English Literature: A Critical Reader. Taylor & Francis. p. 92. ISBN   978-0-415-44524-5 . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  43. Dr Alan Barnard; Jonathan Spencer (1 September 2003). Encyclopedia of Social and Cultural Anthropology. Routledge. p. 280. ISBN   978-0-203-45803-7 . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  44. Frank Trentmann (1 October 2003). Paradoxes of Civil Society: New Perspectives on Modern German and British History. Berghahn Books. p. 69. ISBN   978-1-57181-143-1 . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  45. John P. Jackson, Jr.; Nadine M. Weidman (15 October 2004). Race, Racism, And Science,: Social Impact And Interaction. ABC-CLIO. p. 39. ISBN   978-1-85109-448-6 . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  46. Benjamin H. Isaac (13 February 2006). The Invention of Racism in Classical Antiquity. Princeton University Press. pp. 9–10 note 17. ISBN   978-0-691-12598-5 . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  47. George W. Stocking (2001). Delimiting Anthropology: Occasional Essays and Reflections. Univ of Wisconsin Press. p. 89. ISBN   978-0-299-17450-7 . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  48. Mary Poovey (1 December 1998). A History of the Modern Fact: Problems of Knowledge in the Sciences of Wealth and Society. University of Chicago Press. pp. 227–8. ISBN   978-0-226-67525-1 . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  49. Henry Home (1993). Memoirs of the life and writings of the Honourable Henry Home of Kames. Routledge, Thoemmes. p. xlii. ISBN   978-0-415-08104-7 . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  50. 1 2 Ulrich Broich (2007). Reactions to Revolutions: The 1790s and Their Aftermath. LIT Verlag Münster. pp. 232–3. ISBN   978-3-8258-7427-8 . Retrieved 3 March 2013.
  51. Mark Salber Phillips (1 May 2000). Society and Sentiment: Genres of Historical Writing in Britain, 1740–1820 . Princeton University Press. p.  163. ISBN   978-1-4008-2362-8 . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  52. Adam Smith (1 May 1980). The Glasgow Edition of the Works and Correspondence of Adam Smith: III: Essays on Philosophical Subjects: With Dugald Stewart's 'Account of Adam Smith'. Oxford University Press. p. 268. ISBN   978-0-19-159117-4 . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  53. John Wyon Burrow (1966). Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory. CUP Archive. p. 54. ISBN   978-0-521-04393-9 . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  54. Hopfl, p. 32.
  55. Geoffrey Hawthorn (1987). Enlightenment and Despair: A History of Social Theory . Cambridge University Press. p.  31. ISBN   978-0-521-33721-2.
  56. Aa.vv. (2001). Storia della Storiografia. N. 39. Editoriale Jaca Book. pp. 54–6. ISBN   978-88-16-72039-8 . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  57. Bo Stråth (29 September 2010). Europe and the Other and Europe As the Other. Peter Lang. pp. 224–5. ISBN   978-90-5201-650-4 . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  58. 1 2 Sweet, pp. 20–3.
  59. Rosemary Sweet (1997). Writing of Urban Histories in 18th Century England. Oxford University Press. pp. 143–8. ISBN   978-0-19-820669-9 . Retrieved 3 March 2013.
  60. Martin S. Staum (20 August 2003). Labeling People: French Scholars on Society, Race, and Empire, 1815–1848. McGill-Queen's Press - MQUP. pp. 13–4. ISBN   978-0-7735-7124-2 . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  61. Giorgio Ausenda (1 February 2003). After Empire: Towards an Ethnology of Europe's Barbarians. Boydell & Brewer. pp. 96–7. ISBN   978-0-85115-853-2 . Retrieved 5 March 2013.