Natural law

Last updated

Natural law [1] (Latin : ius naturale, lex naturalis) is a system of law based on a close observation of natural order and human nature, from which values, thought by natural law's proponents to be intrinsic to human nature, can be deduced and applied independently of positive law (the express enacted laws of a state or society). [2] According to the theory of law called jusnaturalism, all people have inherent rights, conferred not by act of legislation but by "God, nature, or reason". [3] Natural law theory can also refer to "theories of ethics, theories of politics, theories of civil law, and theories of religious morality". [4]

Contents

In Western tradition, natural law was anticipated by the pre-Socratics, for example, in their search for principles that governed the cosmos and human beings. The concept of natural law was documented in ancient Greek philosophy, including Aristotle, [5] and was mentioned in ancient Roman philosophy by Cicero. References to it are also found in the Old and New Testaments of the Bible, and were later expounded upon in the Middle Ages by Christian philosophers such as Albert the Great and Thomas Aquinas. The School of Salamanca made notable contributions during the Renaissance.

Although the central ideas of natural law had been part of Christian thought since the Roman Empire, its foundation as a consistent system was laid by Aquinas, who synthesized and condensed his predecessors' ideas into his Lex Naturalis (lit.'Natural law'). [6] Aquinas argues that because human beings have reason, and because reason is a spark of the divine, all human lives are sacred and of infinite value compared to any other created object, meaning everyone is fundamentally equal and bestowed with an intrinsic basic set of rights that no one can remove.

Modern natural law theory took shape in the Age of Enlightenment, combining inspiration from Roman law, Christian scholastic philosophy, and contemporary concepts such as social contract theory. It was used in challenging the theory of the divine right of kings, and became an alternative justification for the establishment of a social contract, positive law, and government—and thus legal rights—in the form of classical republicanism. John Locke was a key Enlightenment-era proponent of natural law, stressing its role in the justification of property rights and the right to revolution. [7] In the early decades of the 21st century, the concept of natural law is closely related to the concept of natural rights and has libertarian and conservative proponents. [8] Indeed, many philosophers, jurists and scholars use natural law synonymously with natural rights (Latin : ius naturale ) or natural justice; [9] others distinguish between natural law and natural right. [10]

Some scholars point out that the concept of natural law has been used by philosophers throughout history also in a different sense from those mentioned above, e.g. for the law of the strongest, which can be observed to hold among all members of the animal kingdom, or as the principle of self-preservation, inherent as an instinct in all living beings. [11]

History

Ancient Greece

Plato

Plato did not have an explicit theory of natural law (he rarely used the phrase "natural law" except in Gorgias 484 and Timaeus 83e), but his concept of nature, according to John Wild, contains some of the elements of many natural law theories. [12] According to Plato, we live in an orderly universe. [13] The basis of this orderly universe or nature are the forms, most fundamentally the Form of the Good, which Plato calls "the brightest region of Being". [14] The Form of the Good is the cause of all things, and a person who sees it is led to act wisely. [15] In the Symposium , the Good is closely identified with the Beautiful, [16] and Plato describes how Socrates's experience of the Beautiful enabled him to resist the temptations of wealth and sex. [17] In the Republic , the ideal community is "a city which would be established in accordance with nature". [18]

Aristotle

Plato (left) and Aristotle (right), a detail of The School of Athens, a fresco by Raphael Sanzio 01 Plato Aristotle.jpg
Plato (left) and Aristotle (right), a detail of The School of Athens , a fresco by Raphael

Greek philosophy emphasized the distinction between "nature" (physis, φúσις) and "law", "custom", or "convention" (nomos, νóμος).[ citation needed ] What the law commanded is expected to vary from place to place, but what is "by nature" should be the same everywhere. A "law of nature" therefore has the flavor more of a paradox than something that obviously existed. [10] Against the conventionalism that the distinction between nature and custom could engender, Socrates and his philosophic heirs, Plato and Aristotle, posited the existence of natural justice or natural right (dikaion physikon, δίκαιον φυσικόν, Latin ius naturale). Of these, Aristotle is often said to be the father of natural law. [9]

Aristotle's association with natural law may be due to Thomas Aquinas's interpretation of his work. [19] But whether Aquinas correctly read Aristotle is in dispute.[ citation needed ] According to some, Aquinas conflates natural law and natural right, the latter of which Aristotle posits in Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics (Book IV of the Eudemian Ethics ). According to this interpretation, Aquinas's influence was such as to affect a number of early translations of these passages in an unfortunate manner, though more recent translations render them more literally. [20] Aristotle notes that natural justice is a species of political justice, specifically the scheme of distributive and corrective justice that would be established under the best political community; if this took the form of law, it could be called a natural law, though Aristotle does not discuss this and suggests in the Politics that the best regime may not rule by law at all. [21]

The best evidence of Aristotle's having thought there is a natural law is in the Rhetoric , where Aristotle notes that, aside from the "particular" laws that each people has set up for itself, there is a "common" law that is according to nature. [22] Specifically, he quotes Sophocles and Empedocles:

Universal law is the law of Nature. For there really is, as every one to some extent divines, a natural justice and injustice that is binding on all men, even on those who have no association or covenant with each other. It is this that Sophocles' Antigone clearly means when she says that the burial of Polyneices was a just act in spite of the prohibition: she means that it was just by nature:

"Not of to-day or yesterday it is,
But lives eternal: none can date its birth."

And so Empedocles, when he bids us kill no living creature, he is saying that to do this is not just for some people, while unjust for others:

"Nay, but, an all-embracing law, through the realms of the sky
Unbroken it stretcheth, and over the earth's immensity." [23]

Some critics believe that this remark's context suggests only that Aristotle advised that it can be rhetorically advantageous to appeal to such a law, especially when the "particular" law of one's own city is averse to the case being made, not that there actually is such a law. [9] Moreover, they write that Aristotle considered two of the three candidates for a universally valid, natural law provided in this passage to be wrong. [10] Aristotle's paternity of natural law tradition is consequently disputed.

Stoic natural law

The development of this tradition of natural justice into one of natural law is usually attributed to the Stoics. The rise of natural law as a universal system coincided with the rise of large empires and kingdoms in the Greek world. [24] [ full citation needed ] Whereas the "higher" law that Aristotle suggested one could appeal to was emphatically natural, in contradistinction to being the result of divine positive legislation, the Stoic natural law was indifferent to either the natural or divine source of the law: the Stoics asserted the existence of a rational and purposeful order to the universe (a divine or eternal law), and the means by which a rational being lived in accordance with this order was the natural law, which inspired actions that accorded with virtue. [10]

As the English historian A. J. Carlyle notes:

There is no change in political theory so startling in its completeness as the change from the theory of Aristotle to the later philosophical view represented by Cicero and Seneca ... We think that this cannot be better exemplified than with regard to the theory of the equality of human nature." [25] Charles H. McIlwain likewise observes that "the idea of the equality of men is the most profound contribution of the Stoics to political thought" and that "its greatest influence is in the changed conception of law that in part resulted from it. [26]

Natural law first appeared among the Stoics, who believed that God is everywhere and in everyone (see classical pantheism). According to this belief, there is a "divine spark" within us that helps us live in accordance with nature. The Stoics believed there is a way in which the universe has been designed, and that natural law helps us to harmonize with this.[ citation needed ]

Ancient Rome

In the Fifth Book of his History of the Roman Republic Livy puts a formulation of the Natural Law into the mouth of Marcus Furius Camillus during the siege of the Falerii "You, villain, have not come with your villainous offer to a nation or a commander like yourself. Between us and the Faliscans there is no fellowship based on a formal compact as between man and man, but the fellowship which is based on natural instincts exists between us, and will continue to do so. There are rights of war as there are rights of peace, and we have learnt to wage our wars with justice no less than with courage. We do not use our weapons against those of an age which is spared even in the capture of cities, but against those who are armed as we are, and who without any injury or provocation from us attacked the Roman camp at Veii. These men you, as far as you could, have vanquished by an unprecedented act of villainy; I shall vanquish them as I vanquished Veii, by Roman arts, by courage and strategy and force of arms."

Marcus Tullius Cicero Thorvaldsen Cicero.jpg
Marcus Tullius Cicero

Cicero wrote in his De Legibus that both justice and law originate from what nature has given to humanity, from what the human mind embraces, from the function of humanity, and from what serves to unite humanity. [27] For Cicero, natural law obliges us to contribute to the general good of the larger society. [28] The purpose of positive laws is to provide for "the safety of citizens, the preservation of states, and the tranquility and happiness of human life." In this view, "wicked and unjust statutes" are "anything but 'laws,'" because "in the very definition of the term 'law' there inheres the idea and principle of choosing what is just and true." [29] Law, for Cicero, "ought to be a reformer of vice and an incentive to virtue." [30] Cicero expressed the view that "the virtues which we ought to cultivate, always tend to our own happiness, and that the best means of promoting them consists in living with men in that perfect union and charity which are cemented by mutual benefits." [28]

In De Re Publica , he writes:

There is indeed a law, right reason, which is in accordance with nature; existing in all, unchangeable, eternal. Commanding us to do what is right, forbidding us to do what is wrong. It has dominion over good men, but possesses no influence over bad ones. No other law can be substituted for it, no part of it can be taken away, nor can it be abrogated altogether. Neither the people or the senate can absolve from it. It is not one thing at Rome, and another thing at Athens: one thing to-day, and another thing to-morrow; but it is eternal and immutable for all nations and for all time. [31]

Cicero influenced the discussion of natural law for many centuries to come, up through the era of the American Revolution. The jurisprudence of the Roman Empire was rooted in Cicero, who held "an extraordinary grip ... upon the imagination of posterity" as "the medium for the propagation of those ideas which informed the law and institutions of the empire." [32] Cicero's conception of natural law "found its way to later centuries notably through the writings of Isidore of Seville and the Decretum of Gratian." [33] Thomas Aquinas, in his summary of medieval natural law, quoted Cicero's statement that "nature" and "custom" were the sources of a society's laws. [34]

The Renaissance Italian historian Leonardo Bruni praised Cicero as the person "who carried philosophy from Greece to Italy, and nourished it with the golden river of his eloquence." [35] The legal culture of Elizabethan England, exemplified by Sir Edward Coke, was "steeped in Ciceronian rhetoric." [36] The Scottish moral philosopher Francis Hutcheson, as a student at Glasgow, "was attracted most by Cicero, for whom he always professed the greatest admiration." [37] More generally in eighteenth-century Great Britain, Cicero's name was a household word among educated people. [37] Likewise, "in the admiration of early Americans Cicero took pride of place as orator, political theorist, stylist, and moralist." [38]

The British polemicist Thomas Gordon "incorporated Cicero into the radical ideological tradition that travelled from the mother country to the colonies in the course of the eighteenth century and decisively shaped early American political culture." [39] Cicero's description of the immutable, eternal, and universal natural law was quoted by Burlamaqui [40] and later by the American revolutionary legal scholar James Wilson. [41] Cicero became John Adams's "foremost model of public service, republican virtue, and forensic eloquence." [42] Adams wrote of Cicero that "as all the ages of the world have not produced a greater statesman and philosopher united in the same character, his authority should have great weight." [43] Thomas Jefferson "first encountered Cicero as a schoolboy while learning Latin, and continued to read his letters and discourses throughout his life. He admired him as a patriot, valued his opinions as a moral philosopher, and there is little doubt that he looked upon Cicero's life, with his love of study and aristocratic country life, as a model for his own." [44] Jefferson described Cicero as "the father of eloquence and philosophy." [45]

Christianity

Paul's Epistle to the Romans is generally considered the Scriptural authority for the Christian idea of natural law as something that was endowed in all men, contrasted with an idea of law as something revealed (for example, the law revealed to Moses by God). [46]

"For when the Gentiles, which have not the law, do by nature the things contained in the law, these, having not the law, are a law unto themselves: Which shew the work of the law written in their hearts, their conscience also bearing witness, and their thoughts the meanwhile accusing or else excusing one another." [47]

The intellectual historian A. J. Carlyle has commented on this passage, "There can be little doubt that St Paul's words imply some conception analogous to the 'natural law' in Cicero, a law written in men's hearts, recognized by man's reason, a law distinct from the positive law of any State, or from what St Paul recognized as the revealed law of God. It is in this sense that St Paul's words are taken by the Fathers of the fourth and fifth centuries like St Hilary of Poitiers, St Ambrose, and St Augustine, and there seems no reason to doubt the correctness of their interpretation." [48]

Because of its origins in the Old Testament, early Church Fathers, especially those in the West, saw natural law as part of the natural foundation of Christianity. The most notable among these was Augustine of Hippo, who equated natural law with humanity's prelapsarian state; as such, a life according to unbroken human nature was no longer possible and persons needed instead to seek healing and salvation through the divine law and grace of Jesus Christ. Augustine was also among the earliest to examine the legitimacy of the laws of man, and attempt to define the boundaries of what laws and rights occur naturally based on wisdom and conscience, instead of being arbitrarily imposed by mortals, and if people are obligated to obey laws that are unjust. [49]

The natural law was inherently teleological as well as deontological. For Christians, natural law is how human beings manifest the divine image in their life. This mimicry of God's own life is impossible to accomplish except by means of the power of grace. Thus, whereas deontological systems merely require certain duties be performed, Christianity explicitly states that no one can, in fact, perform any duties if grace is lacking. For Christians, natural law flows not from divine commands, but from the fact that humanity is made in God's image, humanity is empowered by God's grace. Living the natural law is how humanity displays the gifts of life and grace, the gifts of all that is good.

Consequences are in God's hands, consequences are generally not within human control, thus in natural law, actions are judged by three things: (1) the person's intent, (2) the circumstances of the act and (3) the nature of the act. The apparent good or evil consequence resulting from the moral act is not relevant to the act itself. The specific content of the natural law is therefore determined by how each person's acts mirror God's internal life of love. Insofar as one lives the natural law, temporal satisfaction may or may not be attained, but salvation will be attained. The state, in being bound by the natural law, is conceived as an institution whose purpose is to assist in bringing its subjects to true happiness. True happiness derives from living in harmony with the mind of God as an image of the living God.[ citation needed ]

After the Protestant Reformation, some Protestant denominations maintained parts of the Catholic concept of natural law. The English theologian Richard Hooker from the Church of England adapted Thomistic notions of natural law to Anglicanism five principles: to live, to learn, to reproduce, to worship God, and to live in an ordered society. [50] [ irrelevant citation ]

Catholic natural law jurisprudence

Early natural christian law thinkers

In Catholic countries in the tradition of the early Christian law and in the twelfth century, Gratian equated the natural law with divine law. Albertus Magnus would address the subject a century later, and his pupil, Thomas Aquinas, in his Summa Theologica I-II qq. 90–106, restored Natural Law to its independent state, asserting natural law as the rational creature's participation in the eternal law. [51] Yet, since human reason could not fully comprehend the Eternal law, it needed to be supplemented by revealed Divine law. See also Biblical law in Christianity. [52]

Thomas Aquinas

Aquinas taught that all human or positive laws were to be judged by their conformity to the natural law. An unjust law is not a law, in the full sense of the word. It retains merely the 'appearance' of law insofar as it is duly constituted and enforced in the same way a just law is, but is itself a 'perversion of law.' [53] At this point, the natural law was not only used to pass judgment on the moral worth of various laws, but also to determine what those laws meant in the first place. This principle laid the seed for possible societal tension with reference to tyrants. [54]

The Catholic Church holds the view of natural law introduced by Albertus Magnus and elaborated by Thomas Aquinas, [55] particularly in his Summa Theologica , and often as filtered through the School of Salamanca. This view is also shared by some Protestants, [56] and was delineated by Anglican writer C. S. Lewis in his works Mere Christianity and The Abolition of Man . [57]

The Catholic Church understands human beings to consist of body and soul, and that the two are inextricably linked. [58] Humans are capable of discerning the difference between good and evil because they have a conscience. [59] There are many manifestations of the good that we can pursue. Some, like procreation, are common to other animals, while others, like the pursuit of truth, are inclinations peculiar to the capacities of human beings. [60]

To know what is right, one must use one's reason and apply it to Thomas Aquinas' precepts. This reason is believed to be embodied, in its most abstract form, in the concept of a primary precept: "Good is to be sought, evil avoided." [61] Aquinas explains that:

there belongs to the natural law, first, certain most general precepts, that are known to all; and secondly, certain secondary and more detailed precepts, which are, as it were, conclusions following closely from first principles. As to those general principles, the natural law, in the abstract, can nowise be blotted out from men's hearts. But it is blotted out in the case of a particular action, insofar as reason is hindered from applying the general principle to a particular point of practice, on account of concupiscence or some other passion, as stated above (77, 2). But as to the other, i.e., the secondary precepts, the natural law can be blotted out from the human heart, either by evil persuasions, just as in speculative matters errors occur in respect of necessary conclusions; or by vicious customs and corrupt habits, as among some men, theft, and even unnatural vices, as the Apostle states (Rm. i), were not esteemed sinful. [62]

However, while the primary and immediate precepts cannot be "blotted out", the secondary precepts can be. Therefore, for a deontological ethical theory they are open to a surprisingly large amount of interpretation and flexibility. Any rule that helps humanity to live up to the primary or subsidiary precepts can be a secondary precept, for example:

  • Drunkenness is wrong because it injures one's health, and worse, destroys one's ability to reason, which is fundamental to humans as rational animals (i.e., does not support self-preservation).
  • Theft is wrong because it destroys social relations, and humans are by nature social animals (i.e., does not support the subsidiary precept of living in society).

Natural moral law is concerned with both exterior and interior acts, also known as action and motive. Simply doing the right thing is not enough; to be truly moral one's motive must be right as well. For example, helping an old lady across the road (good exterior act) to impress someone (bad interior act) is wrong. However, good intentions don't always lead to good actions. The motive must coincide with the cardinal or theological virtues. Cardinal virtues are acquired through reason applied to nature; they are:

  1. Prudence
  2. Justice
  3. Temperance
  4. Fortitude

The theological virtues are:

  1. Faith
  2. Hope
  3. Charity

According to Aquinas, to lack any of these virtues is to lack the ability to make a moral choice. For example, consider a person who possesses the virtues of justice, prudence, and fortitude, yet lacks temperance. Due to their lack of self-control and desire for pleasure, despite their good intentions, they will find themself swaying from the moral path.

School of Salamanca

Based on the works of Thomas Aquinas, the members of the School of Salamanca were in the 16th and 17th centuries the first people to develop a modern approach of natural law, which greatly influence Grotius. [63] For Leonardus Lessius, natural law ensues from the rationnal nature and the natural state of everything : That way it is immutable on the contrary of positive law, which stems from divine or human will. [64]

Jurists and theologians claimed thus the right to observe the conformity of the positive law with natural law. For Domingo de Soto, the theologians task is to assess the moral foundations of civil law. [65] Due to this review right based on natural law, Soto criticised the new Spanish charities' laws on the pretext that they violated the fondamental rights of the poors, [66] or that Juan de Mariana considered that the consent of population was needed in matter of taxation or money alteration. [67] Criticized by protestant thinkers like Friedrich Balduin  [ de ] and Samuel von Pufendorf, [68] this view was salvage by the pope Leo XIII in this encyclic Sapientiae Christianae , in which he asked the members of clergy to analyse modern legislation in view of higher norms. [69]

Natural law played also a great role in the diffusion of a contractual consensualism. [70] First recognize by glossators and postglossators before the ecclesiastic courts, [71] it's only in the 16th century that civil law allow the principle of contracts bindingness due on the basis of pure consent. [72] As Pedro de Oñate said "Consequently, natural law, canon law and Hispanic law entirely agree and innumerable difficulties, frauds, litigations and disputes have been removed thanks to such great consensus and clarity in the laws. To the contracting parties, liberty has very wisely been restored" [73]

Besides, natural law also requires the respect of the commutative justice in contractual relation: [74] both parties are binded to respect the notion of just prices [75] on penalty of sin. [76]

Modern Catechism

The Catechism of the Catholic Church describes it in the following way: "The natural law expresses the original moral sense which enables man to discern by reason the good and the evil, the truth and the lie: 'The natural law is written and engraved in the soul of each and every man, because it is human reason ordaining him to do good and forbidding him to sin . . . But this command of human reason would not have the force of law if it were not the voice and interpreter of a higher reason to which our spirit and our freedom must be submitted.'" [77]

The natural law consists, for the Catholic Church, of one supreme and universal principle from which are derived all our natural moral obligations or duties. Thomas Aquinas resumes the various ideas of Catholic moral thinkers about what this principle is: since good is what primarily falls under the apprehension of the practical reason, the supreme principle of moral action must have the good as its central idea, and therefore the supreme principle is that good is to be done and evil avoided. [78]

Islamic natural law

Abū Rayhān al-Bīrūnī, a medieval scholar, scientist, and polymath, understood "natural law" as the survival of the fittest. He argued that the antagonism between human beings can be overcome only through a divine law, which he believed to have been sent through prophets. This is also said to be the general position of the Ashari school, the largest school of Sunni theology, [79] as well as Ibn Hazm. Conceptualized thus, all "laws" are viewed as originating from subjective attitudes actuated by cultural conceptions and individual preferences, and so the notion of "divine revelation" is justified as some kind of "divine intervention" that replaces human positive laws, which are criticized as being relative, with a single divine positive law. This, however, also entails that anything may be included in "the divine law" as it would in "human laws", but unlike the latter, "God's law" is seen as binding regardless of the nature of the commands by virtue of "God's might": since God is not subject to human laws and conventions, He may command what He wills just as He may do what He wills.

The Maturidi school, the second-largest school of Sunni theology, as well as the Mu'tazilites, posits the existence of a form of natural, or "objective", law that humans can comprehend. Abu Mansur al-Maturidi stated that the human mind could know of the existence of God and the major forms of "good" and "evil" without the help of revelation. Al-Maturidi gives the example of stealing, which, he believes, is known to be evil by reason alone due to people's working hard for their property. Similarly, killing, fornication, and drunkenness are all "discernible evils" that the human mind could know of according to al-Maturidi. Likewise, Averroes (Ibn Rushd), in his treatise on Justice and Jihad and his commentary on Plato's Republic, writes that the human mind can know of the unlawfulness of killing and stealing and thus of the five maqasid or higher intents of the Islamic sharia, or the protection of religion, life, property, offspring, and reason. His Aristotelian commentaries also influenced the subsequent Averroist movement and the writings of Thomas Aquinas. [80]

Ibn Qayyim Al-Jawziyya also posited that human reason could discern between "great sins" and "good deeds".[ citation needed ] Nonetheless, he, like Ibn Taymiyah, emphasized the authority of "divine revelation" and asserted that it must be followed even if it "seems" to contradict human reason, though he stressed that most, if not all, of "God's commands" are both sensible (that is, rationalizable) and advantageous to humans in both "this life" and "the hereafter".

The concept of Istislah in Islamic law bears some similarities to the natural law tradition in the West, as exemplified by Thomas Aquinas. However, whereas natural law deems good what is self-evidently good, according as it tends towards the fulfillment of the person, istislah typically calls good whatever is related to one of five "basic goods". Many jurists, theologians, and philosophers attempted to abstract these "basic and fundamental goods" from legal precepts. Al-Ghazali, for instance, defined them as religion, life, reason, lineage, and property, while others add "honor" also.[ citation needed ]

Brehon law

Early Irish law, An Senchus Mor (The Great Tradition) mentions in a number of places recht aicned or natural law. This is a concept predating European legal theory, and reflects a type of law that is universal and may be determined by reason and observation of natural action. Neil McLeod identifies concepts that law must accord with: fír (truth) and dliged (right or entitlement). These two terms occur frequently, though Irish law never strictly defines them. Similarly, the term córus (law in accordance with proper order) occurs in some places, and even in the titles of certain texts. These were two very real concepts to the jurists and the value of a given judgment with respect to them was apparently ascertainable. McLeod has also suggested that most of the specific laws mentioned have passed the test of time and thus their truth has been confirmed, while other provisions are justified in other ways because they are younger and have not been tested over time. [81]

The laws were written in the oldest dialect of the Irish language, called Bérla Féini [Bairla-faina], which even at the time was so difficult that persons about to become brehons had to be specially instructed in it, the length of time from beginning to becoming a learned Brehon was usually 20 years. Although under the law any third person could fulfill the duty if both parties agreed, and both were sane. [82] It has been included in an Ethno-Celtic breakaway subculture, as it has religious undertones and freedom of religious expression allows it to once again be used as a valid system in Western Europe. [83]

English jurisprudence

Heinrich A. Rommen remarked upon "the tenacity with which the spirit of the English common law retained the conceptions of natural law and equity which it had assimilated during the Catholic Middle Ages, thanks especially to the influence of Henry de Bracton (d. 1268) and Sir John Fortescue (d. cir. 1476)." [84] Bracton's translator notes that Bracton "was a trained jurist with the principles and distinctions of Roman jurisprudence firmly in mind"; but Bracton adapted such principles to English purposes rather than copying slavishly. [85] In particular, Bracton turned the imperial Roman maxim that "the will of the prince is law" on its head, insisting that the king is under the law. [86]

The legal historian Charles F. Mullett has noted Bracton's "ethical definition of law, his recognition of justice, and finally his devotion to natural rights." [87] Bracton considered justice to be the "fountain-head" from which "all rights arise." [88] For his definition of justice, Bracton quoted the twelfth-century Italian jurist Azo: "'Justice is the constant and unfailing will to give to each his right.'" [89] Bracton's work was the second legal treatise studied by the American historical figure Thomas Jefferson as a young apprentice lawyer. [90]

Fortescue stressed "the supreme importance of the law of God and of nature" in works that "profoundly influenced the course of legal development in the following centuries." [91] The legal scholar Ellis Sandoz has noted that "the historically ancient and the ontologically higher law—eternal, divine, natural—are woven together to compose a single harmonious texture in Fortescue's account of English law." [92] As the legal historian Norman Doe explains: "Fortescue follows the general pattern set by Aquinas. The objective of every legislator is to dispose people to virtue. It is by means of law that this is accomplished. Fortescue's definition of law (also found in Accursius and Bracton), after all, was 'a sacred sanction commanding what is virtuous [honesta] and forbidding the contrary.'" [93] Fortescue cited the great Italian Leonardo Bruni for his statement that "virtue alone produces happiness." [94]

Christopher St. Germain's The Doctor and Student was a classic of English jurisprudence,. [95] [96] Norman Doe notes that St. Germain's view "is essentially Thomist," quoting Thomas Aquinas's definition of law as "an ordinance of reason made for the common good by him who has charge of the community, and promulgated." [97]

Sir Edward Coke was the preeminent jurist of his time. [98] Coke's preeminence extended across the ocean: "For the American revolutionary leaders, 'law' meant Sir Edward Coke's custom and right reason." [99] [100] Coke defined law as "perfect reason, which commands those things that are proper and necessary and which prohibits contrary things." [101] For Coke, human nature determined the purpose of law; and law was superior to any one person's reason or will. [102] Coke's discussion of natural law appears in his report of Calvin's Case (1608): "The law of nature is that which God at the time of creation of the nature of man infused into his heart, for his preservation and direction." In this case the judges found that "the ligeance or faith of the subject is due unto the King by the law of nature: secondly, that the law of nature is part of the law of England: thirdly, that the law of nature was before any judicial or municipal law: fourthly, that the law of nature is immutable." To support these findings, the assembled judges (as reported by Coke, who was one of them) cited as authorities Aristotle, Cicero, and the Apostle Paul; as well as Bracton, Fortescue, and St. Germain. [103]

After Coke, the most famous common law jurist of the seventeenth century is Sir Matthew Hale. Hale wrote a treatise on natural law that circulated among English lawyers in the eighteenth century and survives in three manuscript copies. [104] This natural-law treatise has been published as Of the Law of Nature (2015). [105] Hale's definition of the natural law reads: "It is the Law of Almighty God given by him to Man with his Nature discovering the morall good and moral evill of Moral Actions, commanding the former, and forbidding the latter by the secret voice or dictate of his implanted nature, his reason, and his concience." [106]

He viewed natural law as antecedent, preparatory, and subsequent to civil government, [107] and stated that human law "cannot forbid what the Law of Nature injoins, nor Command what the Law of Nature prohibits." [108] He cited as authorities Plato, Aristotle, Cicero, Seneca, Epictetus, and the Apostle Paul. [109] He was critical of Hobbes's reduction of natural law to self-preservation and Hobbes's account of the state of nature, [110] but drew positively on Hugo Grotius's De jure belli ac pacis , Francisco Suárez's Tractatus de legibus ac deo legislatore, and John Selden's De jure naturali et gentium juxta disciplinam Ebraeorum. [111]

As early as the thirteenth century, it was held that "the law of nature...is the ground of all laws" [112] and by the Chancellor and Judges that "it is required by the law of nature that every person, before he can be punish'd, ought to be present; and if absent by contumacy, he ought to be summoned and make default." [113] [114] Further, in 1824, we find it held that "proceedings in our Courts are founded upon the law of England, and that law is again founded upon the law of nature and the revealed law of God. If the right sought to be enforced is inconsistent with either of these, the English municipal courts cannot recognize it." [115]

Hobbes

Thomas Hobbes Thomas Hobbes.jpeg
Thomas Hobbes

By the 17th century, the medieval teleological view came under intense criticism from some quarters. Thomas Hobbes instead founded a contractarian theory of legal positivism on what all men could agree upon: what they sought (happiness) was subject to contention, but a broad consensus could form around what they feared, such as violent death at the hands of another. The natural law was how a rational human being, seeking to survive and prosper, would act. Natural law, therefore, was discovered by considering humankind's natural rights, whereas previously it could be said that natural rights were discovered by considering the natural law.

In Hobbes' opinion, the only way natural law could prevail was for men to submit to the commands of the sovereign. Because the ultimate source of law now comes from the sovereign, and the sovereign's decisions need not be grounded in morality, legal positivism is born. Jeremy Bentham's modifications on legal positivism further developed the theory.

As used by Thomas Hobbes in his treatises Leviathan and De Cive , natural law is "a precept, or general rule, found out by reason, by which a man is forbidden to do that which is destructive of his life, or takes away the means of preserving the same; and to omit that by which he thinks it may best be preserved." [116]

According to Hobbes, there are nineteen Laws. The first two are expounded in chapter XIV of Leviathan ("of the first and second natural laws; and of contracts"); the others in chapter XV ("of other laws of nature").

  • The first law of nature is that every man ought to endeavour peace, as far as he has hope of obtaining it; and when he cannot obtain it, that he may seek and use all helps and advantages of war.
  • The second law of nature is that a man be willing, when others are so too, as far forth, as for peace, and defence of himself he shall think it necessary, to lay down this right to all things; and be contented with so much liberty against other men, as he would allow other men against himself.
  • The third law is that men perform their covenants made. In this law of nature consisteth the fountain and original of justice... when a covenant is made, then to break it is unjust and the definition of injustice is no other than the not performance of covenant. And whatsoever is not unjust is just.
  • The fourth law is that a man which receiveth benefit from another of mere grace, endeavour that he which giveth it, have no reasonable cause to repent him of his good will. Breach of this law is called ingratitude.
  • The fifth law is complaisance: that every man strive to accommodate himself to the rest. The observers of this law may be called sociable; the contrary, stubborn, insociable, forward, intractable.
  • The sixth law is that upon caution of the future time, a man ought to pardon the offences past of them that repenting, desire it.
  • The seventh law is that in revenges, men look not at the greatness of the evil past, but the greatness of the good to follow.
  • The eighth law is that no man by deed, word, countenance, or gesture, declare hatred or contempt of another. The breach of which law is commonly called contumely.
  • The ninth law is that every man acknowledge another for his equal by nature. The breach of this precept is pride.
  • The tenth law is that at the entrance into the conditions of peace, no man require to reserve to himself any right, which he is not content should be reserved to every one of the rest. The breach of this precept is arrogance, and observers of the precept are called modest.
  • The eleventh law is that if a man be trusted to judge between man and man, that he deal equally between them.
  • The twelfth law is that such things as cannot be divided, be enjoyed in common, if it can be; and if the quantity of the thing permit, without stint; otherwise proportionably to the number of them that have right.
  • The thirteenth law is the entire right, or else...the first possession (in the case of alternating use), of a thing that can neither be divided nor enjoyed in common should be determined by lottery.
  • The fourteenth law is that those things which cannot be enjoyed in common, nor divided, ought to be adjudged to the first possessor; and in some cases to the first born, as acquired by lot.
  • The fifteenth law is that all men that mediate peace be allowed safe conduct.
  • The sixteenth law is that they that are at controversie, submit their Right to the judgement of an Arbitrator.
  • The seventeenth law is that no man is a fit Arbitrator in his own cause.
  • The eighteenth law is that no man should serve as a judge in a case if greater profit, or honour, or pleasure apparently ariseth [for him] out of the victory of one party, than of the other.
  • The nineteenth law is that in a disagreement of fact, the judge should not give more weight to the testimony of one party than another, and absent other evidence, should give credit to the testimony of other witnesses.

Hobbes's philosophy includes a frontal assault on the founding principles of the earlier natural legal tradition, [117] disregarding the traditional association of virtue with happiness, [118] and likewise re-defining "law" to remove any notion of the promotion of the common good. [119] Hobbes has no use for Aristotle's association of nature with human perfection, inverting Aristotle's use of the word "nature". Hobbes posits a primitive, unconnected state of nature in which men, having a "natural proclivity...to hurt each other" also have "a Right to every thing, even to one anothers body"; [120] and "nothing can be Unjust" in this "warre of every man against every man" in which human life is "solitary, poore, nasty, brutish, and short." [121]

Rejecting Cicero's view that people join in society primarily through "a certain social spirit which nature has implanted in man," [122] Hobbes declares that men join in society simply for the purpose of "getting themselves out from that miserable condition of Warre, which is necessarily consequent...to the naturall Passions of men, when there is no visible Power to keep them in awe." [123] As part of his campaign against the classical idea of natural human sociability, Hobbes inverts that fundamental natural legal maxim, the Golden Rule. Hobbes's version is "Do not that to another, which thou wouldst not have done to thy selfe." [124]

Cumberland's rebuttal of Hobbes

The English cleric Richard Cumberland wrote a lengthy and influential attack on Hobbes's depiction of individual self-interest as the essential feature of human motivation. Historian Knud Haakonssen has noted that in the eighteenth century, Cumberland was commonly placed alongside Alberico Gentili, Hugo Grotius and Samuel Pufendorf "in the triumvirate of seventeenth-century founders of the 'modern' school of natural law." [125] The eighteenth-century philosophers Shaftesbury and Hutcheson "were obviously inspired in part by Cumberland." [126] Historian Jon Parkin likewise describes Cumberland's work as "one of the most important works of ethical and political theory of the seventeenth century." [127]

Parkin observes that much of Cumberland's material "is derived from Roman Stoicism, particularly from the work of Cicero, as "Cumberland deliberately cast his engagement with Hobbes in the mould of Cicero's debate between the Stoics, who believed that nature could provide an objective morality, and Epicureans, who argued that morality was human, conventional and self-interested." [128] In doing so, Cumberland de-emphasized the overlay of Christian dogma (in particular, the doctrine of "original sin" and the corresponding presumption that humans are incapable of "perfecting" themselves without divine intervention) that had accreted to natural law in the Middle Ages.

By way of contrast to Hobbes's multiplicity of laws, Cumberland states in the very first sentence of his Treatise of the Laws of Nature that "all the Laws of Nature are reduc'd to that one, of Benevolence toward all Rationals." [129] He later clarifies: "By the name Rationals I beg leave to understand, as well God as Man; and I do it upon the Authority of Cicero." Cumberland argues that the mature development ("perfection") of human nature involves the individual human willing and acting for the common good. [130]

For Cumberland, human interdependence precludes Hobbes's natural right of each individual to wage war against all the rest for personal survival. However, Haakonssen warns against reading Cumberland as a proponent of "enlightened self-interest". Rather, the "proper moral love of humanity" is "a disinterested love of God through love of humanity in ourselves as well as others." [131] Cumberland concludes that actions "principally conducive to our Happiness" are those that promote "the Honour and Glory of God" and also "Charity and Justice towards men." [132]

Cumberland emphasizes that desiring the well-being of our fellow humans is essential to the "pursuit of our own Happiness." [133] He cites "reason" as the authority for his conclusion that happiness consists in "the most extensive Benevolence," but he also mentions as "Essential Ingredients of Happiness" the "Benevolent Affections," meaning "Love and Benevolence towards others," as well as "that Joy, which arises from their Happiness." [134]

American jurisprudence

The U.S. Declaration of Independence states that it has become necessary for the people of the United States to assume "the separate and equal station to which the Laws of Nature and of Nature's God entitle them." Some early American lawyers and judges perceived natural law as too tenuous, amorphous, and evanescent a legal basis for grounding concrete rights and governmental limitations. [135] Natural law did, however, serve as authority for legal claims and rights in some judicial decisions, legislative acts, and legal pronouncements. [136] Robert Lowry Clinton argues that the U.S. Constitution rests on a common law foundation and the common law, in turn, rests on a classical natural law foundation. [137]

European liberal natural law

Dr Alberico Gentili, the founder of the science of international law Dr Sir Albericus Gentilis (Father of international law).png
Dr Alberico Gentili, the founder of the science of international law

Liberal natural law grew out of the medieval Christian natural law theories and out of Hobbes' revision of natural law, sometimes in an uneasy balance of the two.

Sir Alberico Gentili and Hugo Grotius based their philosophies of international law on natural law. In particular, Grotius's writings on freedom of the seas and just war theory directly appealed to natural law. About natural law itself, he wrote that "even the will of an omnipotent being cannot change or abrogate" natural law, which "would maintain its objective validity even if we should assume the impossible, that there is no God or that he does not care for human affairs." ( De iure belli ac pacis , Prolegomeni XI). This is the famous argument etiamsi daremus (non esse Deum), that made natural law no longer dependent on theology. However, German church-historians Ernst Wolf and M. Elze disagreed and wrote that Grotius' concept of natural law did have a theological basis. [138] In Grotius' view, the Old Testament contained moral precepts (e.g. the Decalogue) which Christ confirmed and therefore were still valid. Moreover, they were useful in explaining the content of natural law. Both biblical revelation and natural law originated in God and could therefore not contradict each other. [139]

In a similar way, Samuel Pufendorf gave natural law a theological foundation and applied it to his concepts of government and international law. [140]

John Locke incorporated natural law into many of his theories and philosophy, especially in Two Treatises of Government . There is considerable debate about whether his conception of natural law was more akin to that of Aquinas (filtered through Richard Hooker) or Hobbes' radical reinterpretation, though the effect of Locke's understanding is usually phrased in terms of a revision of Hobbes upon Hobbesian contractarian grounds. Locke turned Hobbes' prescription around, saying that if the ruler went against natural law and failed to protect "life, liberty, and property," people could justifiably overthrow the existing state and create a new one. [141]

While Locke spoke in the language of natural law, the content of this law was by and large protective of natural rights, and it was this language that later liberal thinkers preferred. Political philosopher Jeremy Waldron has pointed out that Locke's political thought was based on "a particular set of Protestant Christian assumptions." [142] To Locke, the content of natural law was identical with biblical ethics as laid down especially in the Decalogue, Christ's teaching and exemplary life, and Paul's admonitions. [143] Locke derived the concept of basic human equality, including the equality of the sexes ("Adam and Eve"), from Genesis 1, 26–28, the starting-point of the theological doctrine of Imago Dei. [144] One of the consequences is that as all humans are created equally free, governments need the consent of the governed. [145]

Thomas Jefferson, arguably echoing Locke, appealed to unalienable rights in the Declaration of Independence , "We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness." [146] The Lockean idea that governments need the consent of the governed was also fundamental to the Declaration of Independence, as the American Revolutionaries used it as justification for their separation from the British crown. [147]

The Belgian philosopher of law Frank van Dun is one among those who are elaborating a secular conception [148] of natural law in the liberal tradition. Anarcho-capitalist theorist Murray Rothbard argues that "the very existence of a natural law discoverable by reason is a potentially powerful threat to the status quo and a standing reproach to the reign of blindly traditional custom or the arbitrary will of the State apparatus." [149] Austrian school economist Ludwig von Mises states that he relaid the general sociological and economic foundations of the liberal doctrine upon utilitarianism, rather than natural law, but R. A. Gonce argues that "the reality of the argument constituting his system overwhelms his denial." [150] Murray Rothbard, however, says that Gonce makes a lot of errors and distortions in the analysis of Mises's works, including making confusions about the term which Mises uses to refer to scientific laws, "laws of nature", saying it characterizes Mises as a natural law philosopher. [151] David Gordon notes, "When most people speak of natural law, what they have in mind is the contention that morality can be derived from human nature. If human beings are rational animals of such-and-such a sort, then the moral virtues are...(filling in the blanks is the difficult part)." [152]

Nobel Prize winning Austrian economist and social theorist F. A. Hayek said that, originally, "the term 'natural' was used to describe an orderliness or regularity that was not the product of deliberate human will. Together with 'organism' it was one of the two terms generally understood to refer to the spontaneously grown in contrast to the invented or designed. Its use in this sense had been inherited from the stoic philosophy, had been revived in the twelfth century, and it was finally under its flag that the late Spanish Schoolmen developed the foundations of the genesis and functioning of spontaneously formed social institutions." [153]

The idea that 'natural' was "the product of designing reason" is a product of a seventeenth century rationalist reinterpretation of the law of nature. Luis Molina, for example, when referred to the 'natural' price, explained that it is "so called because 'it results from the thing itself without regard to laws and decrees, but is dependent on many circumstances which alter it, such as the sentiments of men, their estimation of different uses, often even in consequence of whims and pleasures." [154] And even John Locke, when talking about the foundations of natural law and explaining what he thought when citing "reason", said: "By reason, however, I do not think is meant here that faculty of the understanding which forms traint of thought and deduces proofs, but certain definite principles of action from which spring all virtues and whatever is necessary for the proper moulding of morals." [155]

This anti-rationalist approach to human affairs, for Hayek, was the same which guided Scottish enlightenment thinkers, such as Adam Smith, David Hume and Adam Ferguson, to make their case for liberty. [156] For them, no one can have the knowledge necessary to plan society, and this "natural" or "spontaneous" order of society shows how it can efficiently "plan" bottom-up. [157] Also, the idea that law is just a product of deliberate design, denied by natural law and linked to legal positivism, can easily generate totalitarianism: "If law is wholly the product of deliberate design, whatever the designer decrees to be law is just by definition and unjust law becomes a contradiction in terms. The will of the duly authorized legislator is then wholly unfettered and guided solely by his concrete interests." [158] This idea is wrong because law cannot be just a product of "reason": "no system of articulated law can be applied except within a framework of generally recognized but often unarticulated rules of justice." [159]

However, a secular critique of the natural law doctrine was stated by Pierre Charron in his De la sagesse (1601): "The sign of a natural law must be the universal respect in which it is held, for if there was anything that nature had truly commanded us to do, we would undoubtedly obey it universally: not only would every nation respect it, but every individual. Instead there is nothing in the world that is not subject to contradiction and dispute, nothing that is not rejected, not just by one nation, but by many; equally, there is nothing that is strange and (in the opinion of many) unnatural that is not approved in many countries, and authorized by their customs."[ citation needed ]

Contemporary jurisprudence

One modern articulation of the concept of natural laws was given by Belina and Dzudzek: [160]

"By constant repetition, those practices develop into structures in the form of discourses which can become so natural that we abstract from their societal origins, that the latter are forgotten and seem to be natural laws."

In jurisprudence, natural law can refer to the several doctrines:

These meanings can either oppose or complement each other, although they share the common trait that they rely on inherence as opposed to design in finding just laws.

Whereas legal positivism would say that a law can be unjust without it being any less a law, a natural law jurisprudence would say that there is something legally deficient about an unjust norm.

Besides utilitarianism and Kantianism, natural law jurisprudence has in common with virtue ethics that it is a live option for a first principles ethics theory in analytic philosophy.

The concept of natural law was very important in the development of the English common law. In the struggles between Parliament and the monarch, Parliament often made reference to the Fundamental Laws of England, which were at times said to embody natural law principles since time immemorial and set limits on the power of the monarchy. According to William Blackstone, however, natural law might be useful in determining the content of the common law and in deciding cases of equity, but was not itself identical with the laws of England. Nonetheless, the implication of natural law in the common law tradition has meant that the great opponents of natural law and advocates of legal positivism, like Jeremy Bentham, have also been staunch critics of the common law.

Today, the most cited authors in literature related to natural law are, in their order: Aquinas, John Finnis, John Locke, Lon Fuller, Ronald Dworkin, and James Wilson, who participated in drafting the U.S. Declaration of Independence. [161] It shows how Aquinas has still a significant influence on the topic. The second Australian professor at Oxford University, John Finnis, is the most prominent contemporary natural law jurist alive. Other authors, like the Americans Germain Grisez, Robert P. George, and Canadian Joseph Boyle and Brazilian Emídio Brasileiro are also constructing a new version of natural law. They created a school called "New Natural Law", originated by Grisez. It focuses on "basic human goods", such as human life, knowledge, and aesthetic experience, which are self-evidently and intrinsically worthwhile, and states that these goods reveal themselves as being incommensurable with one another.

The 19th-century anarchist and legal theorist Lysander Spooner was also a figure in the expression of modern natural law.

The tensions between natural law and positive law have played, and continue to play, a key role in the development of international law. [162]

U.S. Supreme Court justices Clarence Thomas [163] [164] [165] and Neil Gorsuch [166] [167] are proponents of natural law.

Methodology

The authors and supporters of natural law use various methods to develop and articulate their ideas. Here are some of the commonly employed methods:

1. Rational Inquiry and Human Reason: Natural law theorists often engage in rational inquiry to explore the nature of human beings, their moral obligations, and the principles that govern human conduct. They rely on logical reasoning and philosophical analysis to derive principles of natural law. Most Modern scholars dedicated to natural law will follow this rationalistic approach.

2. Observation of Nature: Natural law authors sometimes draw on observations of the natural world and human behavior to derive moral principles. According to Aristotle [168] and Aquinas, [169] it is possible to examine the humans powers and inclinations, to detect what kind of goods are achievable and deserve to be reached.

3. Historical and Comparative Analysis: Some authors of natural law examine historical legal systems and comparative law to identify common moral principles embedded within them. They may explore ancient legal codes, religious texts, and philosophical treatises to uncover ethical norms that have stood the test of time. To some extent, Montesquieu and Max Gluckman did a similar analysis, although the latter under another school of thought. [170]

4. Axiology and Theology: Natural law theorists often incorporate resort to several ends and values to detect principles and rules of natural law. For instance, John Finnis develops natural law based on seven basic good (life, knowledge, play, aesthetic experience, sociability, practical reasonableness, religion) that he believes are self-evident. [171]

5. Dialogue, Debate, Experience, Interpretation and other schools: Several natural law methods have been developed in different schools. Some authors engage in scholarly dialogue and debate with other philosophers and ethicists. They present their arguments, respond to objections, and refine their theories through critical discussion and exchange of ideas. Michael Moore has presented his realistic interpretational approach to the law. [172] Quite different will be the view of Lon Fuller. It's important to note that the methods employed by authors of natural law may vary depending on their specific philosophical perspectives and the historical context in which they work. Different natural law theorists may emphasize different approaches in their efforts to articulate the foundations and implications of natural law.

Nevertheless, Riofrio [173] has detected in a quantitative and qualitative analysis of the most cited papers of natural law, that authors dedicated to natural law usually take into account some elements to deduce others. For instance, Finnis deduces legal principles and natural rights from the seven basic goods; [171] Aquinas deduces the human goods from the human powers, [169] and so on. The elements of the so-called "Natural Law Formula", [173] are the following ones: being (of people and things) - potencies of human beings and things - aims and inclinations of those potencies; means - human values or goods - ethical and legal principles - rules - natural and positive rights - cases and circumstances.

See also

Notes

  1. "Natural Law". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 2022-02-23. Retrieved 2020-10-19.
  2. Finnis, John (2020), "Natural Law Theories", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2020 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, archived from the original on 2021-09-10, retrieved 2020-10-19
  3. Kelsen, Hans (2007). General Theory of Law And State. The Lawbook Exchange. p. 392.
  4. Murphy, Mark (2019), "The Natural Law Tradition in Ethics", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, archived from the original on 2021-11-13, retrieved 2020-10-19
  5. Rommen, Heinrich A. (1959) [1947]. The Natural Law: A Study in Legal and Social Philosophy. Translated by Hanley, Thomas R. B. Herder Book Co. p. 5. ISBN   978-0865971615.
  6. Maritain, Jacques (9 October 2018), Human Rights and Natural Law, UNESCO, archived from the original on 13 November 2021, retrieved 15 September 2021
  7. Locke, John. "The Project Gutenberg eBook of Second Treatise Of Government, by John Locke". www.gutenberg.org. Archived from the original on May 30, 2024. Retrieved 2024-06-11.
  8. van Duffel, Siegfried. "Libertarian Natural Rights" (PDF).
  9. 1 2 3 Shellens, Max Solomon (1959). "Aristotle on Natural Law". Natural Law Forum. 4 (1): 72–100. doi:10.1093/ajj/4.1.72. Archived from the original on 2021-12-12. Retrieved 2020-09-10.
  10. 1 2 3 4 Strauss, Leo (1968). "Natural Law". International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences. London: Macmillan Publishers.
  11. Vacura, Miroslav (2022). "Three concepts of natural law". Philosophy and Society. 33 (3): 601–620. doi: 10.2298/FID2203601V . ISSN   2683-3867.
  12. Wild, John (1953). Plato's Modern Enemies and the Theory of Natural Law . Chicago: University of Chicago Press. p.  136.
  13. Plato, Gorgias 508a.
  14. Plato, The Republic , 518b–d.
  15. Plato, The Republic, 540a, 517b–d.
  16. Plato, Symposium , 205e–206a.
  17. Plato, Symposium, 211d–e.
  18. Plato, The Republic, 428e9.
  19. Jaffa, Harry (1979) [1952]. Thomism and Aristotelianism. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press.
  20. Corbett, Ross J. (April 2012). The Philosophic Context of the Development of Natural Law. Midwest Political Science Association. SSRN   2021235.
  21. Corbett, Ross J. (Summer 2009). "The Question of Natural Law in Aristotle". History of Political Thought. 30 (2): 229–250.
  22. Aristotle, Rhetoric 1373b2–1378.
  23. Aristotle, Rhetoric, Book I – Chapter 13, "Book I - Chapter 13 : Aristotle's Rhetoric". Archived from the original on 2015-02-13. Retrieved 2012-12-22.
  24. Lloyd's Introduction to Jurisprudence, Seventh Edition.
  25. Carlyle, A. J. (1903). A History of Medieval Political Theory in the West. Vol. 1. Edinburgh: William Blackwood and Sons. pp. 8–9.
  26. McIlwain, Charles H. (1932). The Growth of Political Thought in the West: From the Greeks to the End of the Middle Ages. New York: The Macmillan Company. pp. 114–115.
  27. Cicero, De Legibus, bk. 1, sec. 16–17.
  28. 1 2 Barham, Francis (1842). "Introduction". The Political Works of Marcus Tullius Cicero. London: Edmund Spettigue.
  29. Cicero, De Legibus (Keyes translation), bk. 2, sec. 11.
  30. Cicero, De Legibus (Keyes translation), bk. 1, sec. 58.
  31. "Full text of "The republic of Cicero"". Archived from the original on 2017-03-03. Retrieved 2017-10-05.
  32. Cochrane, Charles Norris (1957). Christianity and Classical Culture: A Study of Thought and Action from Augustus to Augustine. New York: Oxford University Press. p.  39.
  33. Corwin, Edward S. (1955). The "Higher Law" Background of American Constitutional Law . Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. pp.  17–18. ISBN   978-0801490125.
  34. Thomas Aquinas, Treatise on Law (Summa Theologica, Questions 90–97), ed. Stanley Parry (Chicago: Henry Regnery Company, 1969), p. 18
  35. Quoted in Quentin Skinner, The Foundations of Modern Political Thought(Cambridge, 1978), vol. 1, p. 89.
  36. Boyer, Allen D. (2004). "Sir Edward Coke, Ciceronianus: Classical Rhetoric and the Common Law Tradition". In Allen D. Boyer (ed.). Law, Liberty, and Parliament: Selected Essays on the Writings of Sir Edward Coke. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund. pp. 224–225.
  37. 1 2 Scott, William Robert (1966) [1900]. Francis Hutcheson: His Life, Teaching, and Position in the History of Philosophy. New York: Augustus M. Kelley.
  38. Reinhold, Meyer (1984). Classica Americana: The Greek and Roman Heritage in the United States . Detroit: Wayne State University Press. p.  150. ISBN   978-0814317440.
  39. Botein, Stephen (April–May 1978). "Cicero as Role Model for Early American Lawyers: A Case Study in Classical 'Influence'". The Classical Journal. 73 (4): 315.
  40. Burlamaqui, Jean Jacques (2006) [1763]. The Principles of Natural and Politic Law. Trans. Thomas Nugent. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund. book I, part 2, ch. 5, sec. 11.
  41. Wilson, James (1967). "Of the Law of Nature". In McCloskey, Robert Green (ed.). The Works of James Wilson. Vol. 1. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. pp. 145–146.
  42. Farrell, James M. (December 1989). "John Adams's Autobiography: The Ciceronian Paradigm and the Quest for Fame". The New England Quarterly. 62 (4): 506. doi:10.2307/366395. JSTOR   366395.
  43. Adams, John (1979) [1797]. A Defence of the Constitutions of Government of the United States of America. Vol. 1 (3 ed.). Darmstadt: Scientia Verlag Aalen. xvii–xviii.
  44. Wilson, Douglas L., ed. (1989). Jefferson's Literary Commonplace Book. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. p. 159.
  45. Jefferson to Amos J. Cook, 21 Jan. 1816; quoted in Jefferson's Literary Commonplace Book, p. 161.
  46. Melvin, Kranzberg (1980). Ethnics in an Age of Pervasive Technology. Routledge. ISBN   9780891586869. In the Epistle to the Romans, Paul explicitly refers to the doctrine of natural law as the endowment of all men
  47. Romans 2:14–15
  48. Carlyle, A. J. (1903). A History of Medieval Political Theory in the West. Vol. 1. New York: G.P. Putnam's Sons. p. 83. Archived from the original on 2016-06-08.
  49. "Augustine on Law and Order — Lawexplores.com".
  50. Natural Law aspects of theory (PDF) (PDF). Rsrevision.com. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2014-10-26.
  51. Summa Theologica, I-II, Q. 91, Art. 2 Archived 2007-07-04 at the Wayback Machine "I answer that"
  52. Summa Theologica, Q. 95, A. 2.
  53. Summa Theologica, Q. 95, A. 2.
  54. Burns, Tony (2000). "Aquinas's Two Doctrines of Natural Law". Political Studies. 48 (5): 929–946. doi:10.1111/1467-9248.00288. S2CID   143492747.
  55. Pope John Paul II, Veritatis Splendor Archived 2014-10-27 at the Wayback Machine , n. 44; International Theological Commission, The Search for Universal Ethics: A New Look at the Natural Law, n. 37.
  56. A Biblical Case for Natural Law, by David VanDrunen. Studies in Christian Social Ethics and Economics, no. 1. Grand Rapids: Acton Institute, 2006.
  57. Raymond Paul Tripp (1975). Man's "natural powers": essays for and about C. S. Lewis. Society for New Language Study. ISBN   978-0905019017.
  58. Pope John Paul II, Veritatis Splendor Archived 2014-10-27 at the Wayback Machine , n. 48.
  59. Pope John Paul II, Veritatis Splendor Archived 2014-10-27 at the Wayback Machine , n. 54 ff.
  60. International Theological Commission, The Search for Universal Ethics: A New Look at the Natural Law, n. 46.
  61. Summa Theologica I–II, Q. 94, A. 2.
  62. Summa Theologica I–II, Q. 94, A. 6.
  63. Decock 2013, p. 62.
  64. Decock 2013, p. 83.
  65. Decock 2013, p. 43.
  66. Decock, Wim (2022). "Mendicité et migration. Domingo de Soto, O.P., sur les droits fondamentaux des pauvres". Revue de droit canonique (in French). 72 (1–2): 243–265.
  67. Decock, Wim (2016). "Spanish Scholastics on Money and Credit". In D. Fox; W. Ernst (eds.). Money in the Western Legal Tradition: Middle Ages to Bretton Woods. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 272–277.
  68. Decock 2013, p. 48-49.
  69. Decock, Wim (2021). "Neo-thomism, Law and Society. A Prolegomenon to Further Study". In W. Decock; B. Raymaekers; P. Heyrman (eds.). Neo-Thomism in Action. Law and Society Reshaped by Neo-Scholastic Philosophy. 1880-1960. Louvain: Leuven University Press. p. 18.
  70. Decock 2013, p. 144.
  71. Decock 2013, p. 109.
  72. Decock 2013, p. 153-162.
  73. Pedro de Oñate, De Contractibus, t.1, tract.1, disp.2, sect.5, num.166, p.40
  74. Decock 2013, p. 508.
  75. Decock 2013, p. 523.
  76. Decock 2013, p. 561.
  77. "Catechism of the Catholic Church - IntraText - I. The Natural Moral Law". The Holy See. Archived from the original on Jan 24, 2021. Retrieved 2020-11-17.
  78. Fox, J. (1910). "Catholic Encyclopedia: Natural Law". New Advent. Transcribed by WGKofron. Retrieved 2020-11-17.
  79. Corbin, Henry (1993) [1964]. History of Islamic Philosophy. Translated by Liadain Sherrard and Philip Sherrard. London; Kegan Paul International in association with Islamic Publications for The Institute of Ismaili Studies. p. 39. ISBN   0710304161. (original in French.)
  80. Roeber, A. G. (October 2001). "What the Law Requires Is Written on Their Hearts: Noachic and Natural Law among German-Speakers in Early Modern North America". William and Mary Quarterly . Third Series. 58 (4): 883–912 [887]. doi:10.2307/2674504. JSTOR   2674504.
  81. Neil McLeod, The Concept of Law in Ancient Irish Jurisprudence, in "Irish Jurist" 17 (1982)
  82. Ireland; Ireland. Commissioners for Publishing the Ancient Laws and Institutes of Ireland (1865–1901). Ancient Laws and Institutes of Ireland Volume 1. Kelly - University of Toronto. Dublin : Printed for H. M. Stationery Office; A. Thom.
  83. "Heritage: Other: Brehon law". Archived from the original on 2017-08-24. Retrieved 2017-08-24.
  84. Rommen, Heinrich A. (1998) [1947]. The Natural Law: A Study in Legal and Social History and Philosophy. Trans. and rev. Thomas R. Hanley. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund. pp. 100–101.
  85. Thorne, Samuel E. (1968). "Translator's Introduction". In de Bracton, Henry (ed.). Of the Laws and Customs of England. Vol. 1. trans. Samuel E. Thorne. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, Belknap Press and The Selden Society. p. xxxiii.
  86. McIlwain, Charles Howard (1958) [1947]. Constitutionalism: Ancient and Modern (rev. ed.). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. pp. 71–89.
  87. Mullett, Charles F. (1966) [1933]. Fundamental Law and the American Revolution 1760–1776 . New York: Octagon Books. p.  33.
  88. de Bracton, Henry (1968). Of the Laws and Customs of England. Vol. 2. trans. Samuel E. Thorne. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, Belknap Press and The Selden Society. p. 22.
  89. de Bracton, Henry (1968). Of the Laws and Customs of England. Vol. 2. trans. Samuel E. Thorne. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, Belknap Press and The Selden Society. p. 23.
  90. Brown, Imogene E. (1981). American Aristides: A Biography of George Wythe. East Brunswick, NJ: Associated University Presses. p. 77.
  91. Hazeltine, Harold Dexter (1949). "General Preface: The Age of Littleton and Fortescue". In Fortescue, John (ed.). De Laudibus Legum Anglie. ed. and trans. S. B. Chrimes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. l, xxviii.
  92. Sandoz, Ellis (1993). "Editor's Introduction". The Roots of Liberty: Magna Carta, Ancient Constitution, and the Anglo-American Tradition of Rule of Law. ed. Ellis Sandoz. Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press. p. 7.
  93. Doe, Norman (1990). Fundamental Authority in Late Medieval English Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 49.
  94. Fortescue, John (1949). Chrimes, S. B. (ed.). De Laudibus Legum Anglie. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 11.
  95. Vinogradoff, Paul (Oct 1908). "Reason and Conscience in Sixteenth-Century Jurisprudence". Law Quarterly Review. 96: 373–374.
  96. Doe, Norman (1990). Fundamental Authority in Late Medieval English Law. Cambridge University Press. pp. 112–113.
  97. Doe, Norman (1990). Fundamental Authority in Late Medieval English Law. Cambridge University Press. p. 113., note 23, citing Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, 1a, 2ae, 90, 4.
  98. Sir Edward Coke, The Selected Writings and Speeches of Sir Edward Coke, ed. Steve Sheppard (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 2003), vol. 1, p. xxvii.
  99. John Phillip Reid, In a Defiant Stance: The Conditions of Law in Massachusetts Bay, The Irish Comparison, and the Coming of the American Revolution (University Park, Penn.: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 1977), 71.
  100. Thomas Jefferson wrote to James Madison in 1826 that before the Revolution, the first volume of Coke's Institutes of the Laws of England "was the universal elementary book of law students, and a sounder Whig never wrote, nor of profounder learning in the orthodox doctrines of the British constitution, or in what were called English liberties." See The Writings of Thomas Jefferson, vol. 16, p. 155.
  101. John Underwood Lewis, "Sir Edward Coke (1552–1634): His Theory of 'Artificial Reason' as a Context for Modern Basic Legal Theory," in Law, Liberty, and Parliament: Selected Essays on the Writings of Sir Edward Coke, ed. Allen D. Boyer (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 2004), pp. 108–109; citing Edward Coke, First Part of the Institutes, 319b.
  102. Lewis, "Sir Edward Coke (1552–1634): His Theory of 'Artificial Reason' as a Context for Modern Basic Legal Theory", p. 120.
  103. Sir Edward Coke, The Selected Writings and Speeches of Sir Edward Coke, ed. Steve Sheppard (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 2003), vol. 1, pp. 195–197.
  104. British Library, London, Add. MS 18235, fols. 41–147 [1693]; Harley MS 7159, fols. 1–266 [1696]; Hargrave MS 485 [late-eighteenth century]
  105. Matthew Hale, Of the Law of Nature Archived 2016-05-14 at the Wayback Machine , ed. David S. Sytsma (CLP Academic, 2015).
  106. Hale, Of the Law of Nature, 41.
  107. Hale, Of the Law of Nature, 85–106.
  108. Hale, Of the Law of Nature, 194.
  109. Hale, Of the Law of Nature, 41, 52, 64, 150–151.
  110. Hale, Of the Law of Nature, 43, 86, 94.
  111. Hale, Of the Law of Nature, 7–8, 17, 49, 63, 111–119, 192.
  112. 8 Edw 4 fol. 12
  113. 9 Ed. 4 fol. 14
  114. Fort. 206
  115. 2 B. & C. 471
  116. Hobbes, Leviathan , pt. 1, ch. 14 (p. 64)
  117. Paul A. Rahe, Republics Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution (Chapel Hill, 1992), pp. 372–373
  118. A Hobbes Dictionary: "Happiness : A Hobbes Dictionary : Blackwell Reference Online". Archived from the original on 2012-01-11. Retrieved 2010-05-23.
  119. James R. Stoner, Jr., Common Law and Liberal Theory: Coke, Hobbes, and the Origins of American Constitutionalism (Lawrence, Kansas, 1992), 71; see also John Phillip Reid, "In the Taught Tradition: The Meaning of Law in Massachusetts-Bay Two-Hundred Years Ago", Suffolk University Law Review 14 (1980), 938–940.
  120. Thomas Hobbes, De Cive (The Citizen), ed. Sterling P. Lamprecht (New York, 1949; orig. 1642), ch. 2, sec. 2 (p. 29).
  121. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, or the Matter, Forme, & Power of a Common-Wealth Ecclesiasticall and Civill (Mineola, N.Y., 2006; orig. 1651), pt. 1, ch. 14 (p. 72); p. 1, ch. 13 (pp. 21, 70).
  122. Cicero, De re publica (Keyes translation), bk. 1, ch. 25, sec. 39
  123. Hobbes, Leviathan, pt. 2, ch. 17 (p. 93)
  124. Hobbes, Leviathan, pt. 1, ch. 15 (p. 79)(emphasis in original). See also Rahe, Republics Ancient and Modern, p. 387.
  125. Knud Haakonssen, "The Character and Obligation of Natural Law according to Richard Cumberland", in English Philosophy in the Age of Locke, ed. M.A. Stewart (Oxford, 2000), 29.
  126. Haakonssen, Natural Law and Moral Philosophy: From Grotius to the Scottish Enlightenment (Cambridge, 1996), 51.
  127. Jon Parkin, Science, Religion and Politics in Restoration England: Richard Cumberland's De Legibus Naturae (Bury St. Edmunds, United Kingdom, 1999), 8.
  128. Parkin, 8.
  129. Richard Cumberland, A Treatise of the Laws of Nature, trans. John Maxwell (Indianapolis, 2005; orig. 1727), "Contents" (p. 237). Cumberland's treatise was originally published in Latin in 1672. A Latin edition was published in Germany in 1684.
  130. Cumberland, ch. 1, sec. 33 (p. 356)
  131. Haakonssen, "The Character and Obligation of Natural Law according to Richard Cumberland," pp. 34, 35.
  132. Cumberland, ch. 5, sec. 13 (pp. 523–524).
  133. Cumberland, ch. 5, sec. 12 (p. 525)
  134. Cumberland, ch. 5, sec. 15 (pp. 527–528).
  135. Douglas E. Edlin (Jul 2006). "Judicial Review without a Constitution". Polity. 38 (3). Palgrave Macmillan Journals: 345–368. doi:10.1057/palgrave.polity.2300065. JSTOR   3877071. S2CID   154594418.
  136. Reid, John Phillip (1986). Constitutional History of the American Revolution: The Authority of Rights . University of Wisconsin Press. pp.  90–91.
  137. Clinton, Robert Lowry (1997). God and Man in the Law: The Foundations of Anglo-American Constitutionalism. University Press of Kansas.
  138. Ernst Wolf, Naturrecht, in Die Religion in Geschichte und Gegenwart, 3. Auflage, Band IV (1960), Tübingen (Germany), col. 1357
  139. M. Elze, Grotius, Hugo, in Die Religion in Geschichte und Gegenwart, 3. Auflage, Band II (1958), col. 1885
  140. H. Hohlwein, Pufendorf, Samuel Freiherr von, in Die Religion in Geschichte und Gegenwart, 3. Auflage, Band V (1961), col. 721
  141. John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, Second Treatise, Chapter 13, §149
  142. Jeremy Waldron (2002), God, Locke, and Equality: Christian Foundations in Locke's Political Thought. Cambridge University Press, p. 13
  143. Jeremy Waldron, God, Locke, and Equality, pp. 12–15, 45–46, 95–97, 195–198, 230
  144. Jeremy Waldron, God, Locke, and Equality, pp. 21–43
  145. Jeremy Waldron, God, Locke, and Equality, p. 136
  146. Pangle, The Spirit of Modern Republicanism (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988), 209.
  147. Cf. Robert Middlekauff (2005),The Glorious Cause: The American Revolution, 1763–1789, Revised and Expanded Edition, Oxford University Press, ISBN   978-0195315882, pp. 49–52, 136
  148. "Natural law, positive law, justice [natuurrecht, droit naturel]". Archived from the original on 2007-12-13. Retrieved 2007-12-28.
  149. Rothbard, Murray (April 1999). "Natural Law Versus Positive Law" (PDF). The Ethics of Liberty. p. 17. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2013-11-26.
  150. R. A. Gonce (Apr 1973). "Natural Law and Ludwig von Mises' Praxeology and Economic Science". Southern Economic Journal. 39 (4). Southern Economic Association: 490–507. doi:10.2307/1056701. JSTOR   1056701.
  151. Rothbard, Murray (Summer 1980). "Ludwig von Mises and Natural Law: A Comment on Professor Gonce". The Journal of Libertarian Studies. IV.
  152. Gordon, David. "Review of In Defense of Natural Law by Robert George". Ludwig von Mises Institute. Archived from the original on 2014-09-14.
  153. Hayek, Friedrich. Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics (PDF). pp. 97–98. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2016-10-11.
  154. Hayek, Friedrich (1982) [1973]. Law, Legislation and Liberty (PDF). London: Routledge. p. 21. ISBN   0415098688. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2016-10-08.
  155. Locke, John (1954). Essays Concerning the Law of Nature. Oxford: W. von Leyden. p. 111.
  156. Hayek, Friedrich. Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics (PDF). pp. 98–99. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2016-10-11.
  157. Hayek, Friedrich (1991). The Trend of Economic Thinking (PDF). Routledge. pp. 22–24. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2016-08-29. Retrieved 2016-08-21.
  158. Hayek, Friedrich (1978). The Constitution of Liberty (PDF). The University of Chicago Press. pp. 238–239. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2016-09-26.
  159. Hayek, Friedrich. Studies In Philosophy, Politics And Economics (PDF). p. 102. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2016-10-11.
  160. Schnelzer, Nadine (2016). Libya in the Arab Spring: The Constitutional Discourse since the Fall of Gaddafi. New York City: Springer. p. 12. ISBN   978-3658113810.
  161. Riofrio, Juan Carlos (2022). "The Natural Law Formula and the Missing Link: Tracing and Updating Aquinas' Methodology". Forum Prawnicze. 74 (6): 5–31.
  162. Singh, Prabhakar (March 2008). "From 'narcissistic' positive international law to 'universal' natural international law: the dialectics of 'absentee colonialism'". African Journal of International and Comparative Law. 16 (1). Edinburgh, Scotland: Edinburgh University Press: 56–82. doi:10.3366/E0954889008000066.
  163. Toobin, Jeffrey (2007). The Nine: Inside the Secret World of the Supreme Court. Random House. p. 31. ISBN   978-0385516402.
  164. Woodward, Kenneth (September 23, 1991). "Natural Law, An Elusive Tradition". Newsweek . New York City. Archived from the original on June 5, 2014. Retrieved April 20, 2009.
  165. Epstein, Aaron (August 30, 1991). "The Natural Law According To Clarence Thomas". The Seattle Times . Archived from the original on September 29, 2012. Retrieved April 20, 2009.
  166. Kengor, Paul. "Neil Gorsuch and Natural Law". NCR. Archived from the original on February 14, 2021. Retrieved April 30, 2017.
  167. Kelleher, J. Paul (March 20, 2017). "Neil Gorsuch's "natural law" philosophy is a long way from Justice Scalia's originalism". Vox. Archived from the original on February 14, 2021. Retrieved March 9, 2018.
  168. "The Nicomachean ethics | WorldCat.org". www.worldcat.org. Retrieved 2023-05-11.
  169. 1 2 "SUMMA THEOLOGICA | WorldCat.org". www.worldcat.org. Retrieved 2023-05-11.
  170. "The Spirit of laws | WorldCat.org". www.worldcat.org. Retrieved 2023-05-11.
  171. 1 2 "Natural law and natural rights | WorldCat.org". www.worldcat.org (in Spanish). Retrieved 2023-05-11.
  172. Fernando Atria Lemaitre; MacCormick, Neil, eds. (2017). "Michael S. Moore (1985), 'A Natural Law Theory of Interpretation', Southern California Law Review, 58, pp. 277-398". Law and Legal Interpretation. doi:10.4324/9781315197470. ISBN   9781315197470 . Retrieved 2023-05-11.
  173. 1 2 Riofrio, Juan Carlos (2022-12-31). "The Natural Law Formula and the Missing Link: Tracing and Updating Aquinas' Methodology". Forum Prawnicze. 6 (74): 5–31. doi: 10.32082/fp.6(74).2022.1070 . ISSN   2081-688X.

Related Research Articles

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Jurisprudence</span> Theoretical study of law

Jurisprudence, also known as theory of law or philosophy of law, is the examination in a general perspective of what law is and what it ought to be. It investigates issues such as the definition of law; legal validity; legal norms and values; as well as the relationship between law and other fields of study, including economics, ethics, history, sociology, and political philosophy.

Political philosophy, or political theory, is the philosophical study of government, addressing questions about the nature, scope, and legitimacy of public agents and institutions and the relationships between them. Its topics include politics, justice, liberty, property, rights, law, and authority: what they are, if they are needed, what makes a government legitimate, what rights and freedoms it should protect, what form it should take, what the law is, and what duties citizens owe to a legitimate government, if any, and when it may be legitimately overthrown, if ever.

Reason is the capacity of consciously applying logic by drawing valid conclusions from new or existing information, with the aim of seeking the truth. It is associated with such characteristically human activities as philosophy, religion, science, language, mathematics, and art, and is normally considered to be a distinguishing ability possessed by humans. Reason is sometimes referred to as rationality.

Will, within philosophy, is a faculty of the mind. Will is important as one of the parts of the mind, along with reason and understanding. It is considered central to the field of ethics because of its role in enabling deliberate action.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Divine command theory</span> Meta-ethical theory of morality

Divine command theory is a meta-ethical theory which proposes that an action's status as morally good is equivalent to whether it is commanded by God. The theory asserts that what is moral is determined by God's commands and that for a person to be moral he is to follow God's commands. Followers of both monotheistic and polytheistic religions in ancient and modern times have often accepted the importance of God's commands in establishing morality.

In ethics, political philosophy, social contract theory, religion, and international law, the term state of nature describes the hypothetical way of life that existed before humans organised themselves into societies or civilisations. Philosophers of the state of nature theory propose that there was a historical period before societies existed, and seek answers to the questions: "What was life like before civil society?", "How did government emerge from such a primitive start?", and "What are the hypothetical reasons for entering a state of society by establishing a nation-state?".

Some philosophers distinguish two types of rights, natural rights and legal rights.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness</span> Phrase in the United States Declaration of Independence

"Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness" is a well-known phrase from the United States Declaration of Independence. The phrase gives three examples of the unalienable rights which the Declaration says have been given to all humans by their Creator, and which governments are created to protect. Like the other principles in the Declaration of Independence, this phrase is not legally binding, but has been widely referenced and seen as an inspiration for the basis of government.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Euthyphro dilemma</span> Ethical problem on the origin of morality posed by Socrates

The Euthyphro dilemma is found in Plato's dialogue Euthyphro, in which Socrates asks Euthyphro, "Is the pious loved by the gods because it is pious, or is it pious because it is loved by the gods?" (10a)

Early modern philosophy The early modern era of philosophy was a progressive movement of Western thought, exploring through theories and discourse such topics as mind and matter, is a period in the history of philosophy that overlaps with the beginning of the period known as modern philosophy. It succeeded the medieval era of philosophy. Early modern philosophy is usually thought to have occurred between the 16th and 18th centuries, though some philosophers and historians may put this period slightly earlier. During this time, influential philosophers included Descartes, Locke, Hume, and Kant, all of whom contributed to the current understanding of philosophy.

<i>Two Treatises of Government</i> 1689 Work by John Locke

Two Treatises of Government is a work of political philosophy published anonymously in 1689 by John Locke. The First Treatise attacks patriarchalism in the form of sentence-by-sentence refutation of Robert Filmer's Patriarcha, while the Second Treatise outlines Locke's ideas for a more civilized society based on natural rights and contract theory. The book is a key foundational text in the theory of liberalism.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Positive law</span> Laws that oblige or specify an action

Positive laws are human-made laws that oblige or specify an action. Positive law also describes the establishment of specific rights for an individual or group. Etymologically, the name derives from the verb to posit.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Justice (virtue)</span> Cardinal virtue

Justice is one of the four cardinal virtues in classical European philosophy and Roman Catholicism. It is the moderation or mean between selfishness and selflessness — between having more and having less than one's fair share.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">John Finnis</span> Australian legal scholar and philosopher

John Mitchell Finnis is an Australian legal philosopher and jurist specializing in jurisprudence and the philosophy of law. He is an original interpreter of Aristotle and Aquinas, and counts Germain Grisez as a major influence and collaborator. He has made contributions to epistemology, metaphysics, and moral philosophy.

<i>Summa Theologica</i> Theological treatise by Thomas Aquinas

The Summa Theologiae or Summa Theologica, often referred to simply as the Summa, is the best-known work of Thomas Aquinas (1225–1274), a scholastic theologian and Doctor of the Church. It is a compendium of all of the main theological teachings of the Catholic Church, intended to be an instructional guide for theology students, including seminarians and the literate laity. Presenting the reasoning for almost all points of Christian theology in the West, topics of the Summa follow the following cycle: God; Creation, Man; Man's purpose; Christ; the Sacraments; and back to God.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Thomas Aquinas</span> Italian Dominican theologian and philosopher (1225–1274)

Thomas Aquinas was an Italian Dominican friar and priest, the foremost Scholastic thinker, as well one of the most influential philosophers and theologians in the Western tradition. He was from the county of Aquino in the Kingdom of Sicily.

<i>Natural Law and Natural Rights</i> 1980 book by John Finnis

Natural Law and Natural Rights is a book by John Finnis first published by Oxford University Press, as part of the Clarendon Law Series. Finnis develops a philosophy of Law in the tradition of Aristotle and Thomas Aquinas – Natural Law. His presentation and defence of Natural Law can be explored from three perspectives. First, polemical, by contradistinction with other philosophies of Law. Second, through its particular methodology, based on practical reasoning. Third, through its substantive content in the form of basic human goods. In addition, his 2011 edition included an extensive postscript, which is briefly discussed in the fourth section. The book is written as a collection of essays on a wide range of topics guided by an overall theme.

The philosophy of human rights attempts to examine the underlying basis of the concept of human rights and critically looks at its content and justification. Several theoretical approaches have been advanced to explain how and why the concept of human rights developed.

<i>Treatise on Law</i> Work of legal philosophy by Thomas Aquinas

Treatise on Law is Thomas Aquinas' major work of legal philosophy. It forms questions 90–108 of the Prima Secundæ of the Summa Theologiæ, Aquinas' masterwork of Scholastic philosophical theology. Along with Aristotelianism, it forms the basis not only for the legal theory of Catholic canon law, but provides a model for natural law theories generally.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Iusnaturalism</span> Theory of law

Jusnaturalism or iusnaturalism is a theory of law, which holds that legal norms follow a human universal knowledge on justice and harmony of relations. Thus, it views enacted laws that contradict such universal knowledge as unjust and illegitimate. Modern theorists considered as iusnaturalists include Hugo Grotius, Immanuel Kant, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, and Franz von Zeiller, among others.

References