Joel David Hamkins

Last updated
Joel David Hamkins
Joel Hamkins, July 1994 (headshot).jpg
NationalityAmerican
Alma mater University of California, Berkeley
California Institute of Technology
Scientific career
Fields Mathematics, Philosophy
Institutions University of Notre Dame
University of Oxford
City University of New York
Doctoral advisor W. Hugh Woodin

Joel David Hamkins is an American mathematician and philosopher who is O'Hara Professor of Philosophy and Mathematics at the University of Notre Dame. [1] He has made contributions in mathematical and philosophical logic, set theory and philosophy of set theory (particularly the idea of the set-theoretic multiverse), in computability theory, and in group theory.

Contents

Biography

After earning a Bachelor of Science in mathematics at the California Institute of Technology, Hamkins earned his Ph.D. in mathematics in 1994 at the University of California, Berkeley under the supervision of W. Hugh Woodin, with a dissertation entitled Lifting and Extending Measures by Forcing; Fragile Measurability. He joined the faculty of the City University of New York in 1995, where he was a member of the doctoral faculties in Mathematics, in Philosophy and in Computer Science at the CUNY Graduate Center and professor of mathematics at the College of Staten Island. He has also held various faculty or visiting fellow positions at University of California at Berkeley, Kobe University, Carnegie Mellon University, University of Münster, Georgia State University, University of Amsterdam, the Fields Institute, New York University and the Isaac Newton Institute. [2]

In September 2018, Hamkins moved to the University of Oxford to become Professor of Logic in the Faculty of Philosophy and Sir Peter Strawson Fellow in Philosophy in University College, Oxford. [3] In January 2022 he moved to the University of Notre Dame [4] as the O'Hara Professor of Philosophy and Mathematics.

Research contributions

Hamkins research work is cited, [5] and he gives talks, [6] including events for the general public. [7] [8] [9] [10] Hamkins was interviewed on his research by Richard Marshall in 2013 for 3:AM Magazine , as part of an ongoing interview series for that magazine of prominent philosophers and public intellectuals, [11] and he is occasionally interviewed by the popular science media about issues in the philosophy of mathematics. [12] [13]

Set theory

In set theory, Hamkins has investigated the indestructibility phenomenon of large cardinals, proving that small forcing necessarily ruins the indestructibility of supercompact and other large cardinals [14] and introducing the lottery preparation as a general method of forcing indestructibility. [15] Hamkins introduced the modal logic of forcing and proved with Benedikt Löwe that if ZFC is consistent, then the ZFC-provably valid principles of forcing are exactly those in the modal theory known as S4.2. [16] Hamkins, Linetsky and Reitz proved that every countable model of Gödel-Bernays set theory has a class forcing extension to a pointwise definable model, in which every set and class is definable without parameters. [17] Hamkins and Reitz introduced the ground axiom, which asserts that the set-theoretic universe is not a forcing extension of any inner model by set forcing. Hamkins proved that any two countable models of set theory are comparable by embeddability, and in particular that every countable model of set theory embeds into its own constructible universe. [18]

Philosophy of set theory

In his philosophical work, Hamkins has defended a multiverse perspective of mathematical truth, [19] [20] arguing that diverse concepts of set give rise to different set-theoretic universes with different theories of mathematical truth. He argues that the Continuum Hypothesis question, for example, "is settled on the multiverse view by our extensive knowledge about how it behaves in the multiverse, and as a result it can no longer be settled in the manner formerly hoped for." (Hamkins 2012) Elliott Mendelson writes of Hamkins's work on the set-theoretic multiverse that, "the resulting study is an array of new fantastic, and sometimes bewildering, concepts and results that already have yielded a flowering of what amounts to a new branch of set theory. This ground-breaking paper gives us a glimpse of the amazingly fecund developments spearheaded by the author and...others..." [21]

Infinitary computability

Hamkins introduced with Jeff Kidder and Andy Lewis the theory of infinite-time Turing machines, a part of the subject of hypercomputation, with connections to descriptive set theory. [22]

In other computability work, Hamkins and Miasnikov proved that the classical halting problem for Turing machines, although undecidable, is nevertheless decidable on a set of asymptotic probability one, one of several results in generic-case complexity showing that a difficult or unsolvable problem can be easy on average. [23]

Group theory

In group theory, Hamkins proved that every group has a terminating transfinite automorphism tower. [24] With Simon Thomas, he proved that the height of the automorphism tower of a group can be modified by forcing.

Infinite chess

On the topic of infinite chess, Hamkins, Brumleve and Schlicht proved that the mate-in-n problem of infinite chess is decidable. [25] Hamkins and Evans investigated transfinite game values in infinite chess, proving that every countable ordinal arises as the game value of a position in infinite three-dimensional chess. [26]

MathOverflow

Hamkins is the top-rated [27] user by reputation score on MathOverflow. [28] [29] [30] Gil Kalai describes him as "one of those distinguished mathematicians whose arrays of MO answers in their areas of interest draw coherent deep pictures for these areas that you probably cannot find anywhere else." [31]

Related Research Articles

In mathematics, specifically set theory, the continuum hypothesis is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states that

there is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and the real numbers,

Mathematical logic is the study of formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory. Research in mathematical logic commonly addresses the mathematical properties of formal systems of logic such as their expressive or deductive power. However, it can also include uses of logic to characterize correct mathematical reasoning or to establish foundations of mathematics.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Integer sequence</span> Ordered list of whole numbers

In mathematics, an integer sequence is a sequence of integers.

Hypercomputation or super-Turing computation is a set of models of computation that can provide outputs that are not Turing-computable. For example, a machine that could solve the halting problem would be a hypercomputer; so too would one that can correctly evaluate every statement in Peano arithmetic.

Reverse mathematics is a program in mathematical logic that seeks to determine which axioms are required to prove theorems of mathematics. Its defining method can briefly be described as "going backwards from the theorems to the axioms", in contrast to the ordinary mathematical practice of deriving theorems from axioms. It can be conceptualized as sculpting out necessary conditions from sufficient ones.

In mathematics, the axiom of dependent choice, denoted by , is a weak form of the axiom of choice that is still sufficient to develop much of real analysis. It was introduced by Paul Bernays in a 1942 article that explores which set-theoretic axioms are needed to develop analysis.

In mathematics, an unfoldable cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number.

In mathematics and computer science, Zeno machines are a hypothetical computational model related to Turing machines that are capable of carrying out computations involving a countably infinite number of algorithmic steps. These machines are ruled out in most models of computation.

Determinacy is a subfield of set theory, a branch of mathematics, that examines the conditions under which one or the other player of a game has a winning strategy, and the consequences of the existence of such strategies. Alternatively and similarly, "determinacy" is the property of a game whereby such a strategy exists. Determinacy was introduced by Gale and Stewart in 1950, under the name "determinateness".

Gentzen's consistency proof is a result of proof theory in mathematical logic, published by Gerhard Gentzen in 1936. It shows that the Peano axioms of first-order arithmetic do not contain a contradiction, as long as a certain other system used in the proof does not contain any contradictions either. This other system, today called "primitive recursive arithmetic with the additional principle of quantifier-free transfinite induction up to the ordinal ε0", is neither weaker nor stronger than the system of Peano axioms. Gentzen argued that it avoids the questionable modes of inference contained in Peano arithmetic and that its consistency is therefore less controversial.

In the mathematical discipline of set theory, there are many ways of describing specific countable ordinals. The smallest ones can be usefully and non-circularly expressed in terms of their Cantor normal forms. Beyond that, many ordinals of relevance to proof theory still have computable ordinal notations. However, it is not possible to decide effectively whether a given putative ordinal notation is a notation or not ; various more-concrete ways of defining ordinals that definitely have notations are available.

In proof theory, ordinal analysis assigns ordinals to mathematical theories as a measure of their strength. If theories have the same proof-theoretic ordinal they are often equiconsistent, and if one theory has a larger proof-theoretic ordinal than another it can often prove the consistency of the second theory.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Infinity</span> Mathematical concept

Infinity is something which is boundless, endless, or larger than any natural number. It is often denoted by the infinity symbol .

In set theory, the ground axiom states that the universe of set theory is not a nontrivial set-forcing extension of an inner model. The axiom was introduced by Hamkins (2005) and Reitz (2007).

In mathematical set theory, a worldly cardinal is a cardinal κ such that the rank Vκ is a model of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory.

In mathematical set theory, the multiverse view is that there are many models of set theory, but no "absolute", "canonical" or "true" model. The various models are all equally valid or true, though some may be more useful or attractive than others. The opposite view is the "universe" view of set theory in which all sets are contained in some single ultimate model.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Infinite chess</span> Variation of chess

Infinite chess is any variation of the game of chess played on an unbounded chessboard. Versions of infinite chess have been introduced independently by multiple players, chess theorists, and mathematicians, both as a playable game and as a model for theoretical study. It has been found that even though the board is unbounded, there are ways in which a player can win the game in a finite number of moves.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Joan Bagaria</span>

Joan Bagaria Pigrau is a Catalan mathematician, logician and set theorist at ICREA and University of Barcelona. He has made many contributions concerning forcing, large cardinals, infinite combinatorics and their applications to other areas of mathematics. He earned his Ph.D. in Logic & the Methodology of Science at Berkeley in 1991 under the supervision of Haim Judah and W. Hugh Woodin. Since 2001, he has been ICREA Research Professor at University of Barcelona. He served as the first president of the European Set Theory Society (2007–11). He is also a talented teacher.

The Higher Infinite: Large Cardinals in Set Theory from their Beginnings is a monograph in set theory by Akihiro Kanamori, concerning the history and theory of large cardinals, infinite sets characterized by such strong properties that their existence cannot be proven in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZFC). This book was published in 1994 by Springer-Verlag in their series Perspectives in Mathematical Logic, with a second edition in 2003 in their Springer Monographs in Mathematics series, and a paperback reprint of the second edition in 2009 (ISBN 978-3-540-88866-6).

References

  1. "Joel David Hamkins". University of Notre Dame . Retrieved 2022-01-05.
  2. "Curriculum Vita" (PDF). Retrieved 5 February 2020.
  3. Hamkins, Joel David (May 17, 2018). "Oxford University, Professor of Logic & Sir Peter Strawson Fellow, University College Oxford".
  4. "Notre Dame Hires Hamkins from Oxford and Montero from CUNY". 23 September 2021.
  5. J. D. Hamkins: Google Scholar profile.
  6. List of talks, from Hamkins's web page.
  7. The Span of Infinity, Helix Center roundtable, October 25, 2014. (Hamkins was a panelist.)
  8. J. D. Hamkins, plenary General Public Lecture, Higher infinity and the Foundations of Mathematics, American Association for the Advancement of Science, Pacific Division, June, 2014.
  9. A Meeting at the Crossroads - Science, Performance and the Art of Possibility, The Intrinsic Value Project, Underground Zero, New York City, July 9 & 10, 2014. (Hamkins was a panelist.)
  10. The Future of Infinity: Solving Math's Most Notorious Problem, World Science Festival, New York City, June 1, 2013. (Hamkins was a panelist.)
  11. Richard Marshall, Playing Infinite Chess, 3AM Magazine, March 25, 2013.
  12. Jacob Aron, Mathematicians Think Like Machines for Perfect Proofs New Scientist, 26 June 2013.
  13. Erica Klarreich, Infinite Wisdom, Science News, Volume 164, Number 9, August 30, 2003, page 139.
  14. Hamkins, Joel David (1998). "Small Forcing Makes any Cardinal Superdestructible". The Journal of Symbolic Logic. 63 (1): 51–58. arXiv: 1607.00684 . doi:10.2307/2586586. JSTOR   2586586. S2CID   40252670.
  15. Hamkins, Joel David (2000). "The Lottery Preparation". Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 101 (2–3): 103–146. doi:10.1016/S0168-0072(99)00010-X. S2CID   15579965.
  16. Hamkins, Joel David; Löwe, Benedikt (2008). "The modal logic of forcing". Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 360 (4): 1793–1817. arXiv: math/0509616 . doi:10.1090/s0002-9947-07-04297-3. S2CID   14724471.
  17. Hamkins, Joel David (2013). "David Linetsky and Jonas Reitz, Pointwise definable models of set theory". The Journal of Symbolic Logic. 78 (1): 139–156. arXiv: 1105.4597 . doi:10.2178/jsl.7801090. S2CID   43689192.
  18. Hamkins, Joel David (2013). "Every countable model of set theory embeds into its own constructible universe". J. Math. Log. 13 (2): 1350006. arXiv: 1207.0963 . doi:10.1142/S0219061313500062. S2CID   18836919.
  19. Hamkins, Joel David (2012). "The set-theoretic multiverse". The Review of Symbolic Logic. 5 (3): 416–449. arXiv: 1108.4223 . doi:10.1017/S1755020311000359. S2CID   33807508.
  20. J. D. Hamkins, The multiverse perspective on determinateness in set theory, talk at the Exploring the Frontiers of Incompleteness, Harvard University, October 19, 2011. video
  21. Elliott Mendelson, Zentralblatt review of J. D. Hamkins, The set-theoretic multiverse, Review of Symbolic Logic, 5, Number 3, pages 416-449 (2012), Zbl   1260.03103.
  22. Hamkins, Joel David; Lewis, Andy (2000). "Infinite-time Turing machines". The Journal of Symbolic Logic. 65 (2): 567–604. arXiv: math/9808093 . doi:10.2307/2586556. JSTOR   2586556. S2CID   125601911.
  23. Hamkins, Joel David; Miasnikov, Alexei (2006). "The Halting Problem Is Decidable on a Set of Asymptotic Probability One". Notre Dame J. Formal Logic. 47 (4): 515–524. arXiv: math/0504351 . doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1168352664. S2CID   15005164.
  24. Hamkins, Joel David (1998). "Every group has a terminating automorphism tower". Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society. 126 (11): 3223–3226. doi: 10.1090/s0002-9939-98-04797-2 .
  25. Brumleve, Dan; Hamkins, Joel David; Schlicht, Philipp (2012). "The mate-in-n problem of infinite chess is decidable". In Cooper, S. Barry; Dawar, Anuj; Löwe, Benedikt (eds.). How the World Computes – Turing Centenary Conference and 8th Conference on Computability in Europe, CiE 2012, Cambridge, United Kingdom, June 18–23, 2012. Proceedings. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Vol. 7318. Springer. pp. 78–88. arXiv: 1201.5597 . doi:10.1007/978-3-642-30870-3_9.
  26. C. D. A. Evans and J. D. Hamkins, "Transfinite game values in infinite chess," Integers, volume 14, Paper Number G2, 36, 2014.
  27. MathOverflow users, by reputation score.
  28. MathOverflow announcement of Hamkins breaking 100,000 reputation score, September 17, 2014.
  29. MathOverflow announcement of Hamkins posting 1000th answer, January 30, 2014.
  30. Erica Klarreich, The Global Math Commons, Simons Foundation Science News, May 18, 2011.
  31. Gil Kalai on Hamkins's MathOverflow achievements, January 29, 2014.