Pointclass

Last updated

In the mathematical field of descriptive set theory, a pointclass is a collection of sets of points, where a point is ordinarily understood to be an element of some perfect Polish space. In practice, a pointclass is usually characterized by some sort of definability property; for example, the collection of all open sets in some fixed collection of Polish spaces is a pointclass. (An open set may be seen as in some sense definable because it cannot be a purely arbitrary collection of points; for any point in the set, all points sufficiently close to that point must also be in the set.)

Contents

Pointclasses find application in formulating many important principles and theorems from set theory and real analysis. Strong set-theoretic principles may be stated in terms of the determinacy of various pointclasses, which in turn implies that sets in those pointclasses (or sometimes larger ones) have regularity properties such as Lebesgue measurability (and indeed universal measurability), the property of Baire, and the perfect set property.

Basic framework

In practice, descriptive set theorists often simplify matters by working in a fixed Polish space such as Baire space or sometimes Cantor space, each of which has the advantage of being zero dimensional, and indeed homeomorphic to its finite or countable powers, so that considerations of dimensionality never arise. Yiannis Moschovakis provides greater generality by fixing once and for all a collection of underlying Polish spaces, including the set of all naturals, the set of all reals, Baire space, and Cantor space, and otherwise allowing the reader to throw in any desired perfect Polish space. Then he defines a product space to be any finite Cartesian product of these underlying spaces. Then, for example, the pointclass of all open sets means the collection of all open subsets of one of these product spaces. This approach prevents from being a proper class, while avoiding excessive specificity as to the particular Polish spaces being considered (given that the focus is on the fact that is the collection of open sets, not on the spaces themselves).

Boldface pointclasses

The pointclasses in the Borel hierarchy, and in the more complex projective hierarchy, are represented by sub- and super-scripted Greek letters in boldface fonts; for example, is the pointclass of all closed sets, is the pointclass of all Fσ sets, is the collection of all sets that are simultaneously Fσ and Gδ, and is the pointclass of all analytic sets.

Sets in such pointclasses need be "definable" only up to a point. For example, every singleton set in a Polish space is closed, and thus . Therefore, it cannot be that every set must be "more definable" than an arbitrary element of a Polish space (say, an arbitrary real number, or an arbitrary countable sequence of natural numbers). Boldface pointclasses, however, may (and in practice ordinarily do) require that sets in the class be definable relative to some real number, taken as an oracle. In that sense, membership in a boldface pointclass is a definability property, even though it is not absolute definability, but only definability with respect to a possibly undefinable real number.

Boldface pointclasses, or at least the ones ordinarily considered, are closed under Wadge reducibility; that is, given a set in the pointclass, its inverse image under a continuous function (from a product space to the space of which the given set is a subset) is also in the given pointclass. Thus a boldface pointclass is a downward-closed union of Wadge degrees.

Lightface pointclasses

The Borel and projective hierarchies have analogs in effective descriptive set theory in which the definability property is no longer relativized to an oracle, but is made absolute. For example, if one fixes some collection of basic open neighborhoods (say, in Baire space, the collection of sets of the form {xωωs is an initial segment of x} for each fixed finite sequence s of natural numbers), then the open, or , sets may be characterized as all (arbitrary) unions of basic open neighborhoods. The analogous sets, with a lightface , are no longer arbitrary unions of such neighborhoods, but computable unions of them. That is, a set is lightface , also called effectively open, if there is a computable set S of finite sequences of naturals such that the given set is the union of the sets {xωωs is an initial segment of x} for s in S.

A set is lightface if it is the complement of a set. Thus each set has at least one index, which describes the computable function enumerating the basic open sets from which it is composed; in fact it will have infinitely many such indices. Similarly, an index for a set B describes the computable function enumerating the basic open sets in the complement of B.

A set A is lightface if it is a union of a computable sequence of sets (that is, there is a computable enumeration of indices of sets such that A is the union of these sets). This relationship between lightface sets and their indices is used to extend the lightface Borel hierarchy into the transfinite, via recursive ordinals. This produces the hyperarithmetic hierarchy, which is the lightface analog of the Borel hierarchy. (The finite levels of the hyperarithmetic hierarchy are known as the arithmetical hierarchy.)

A similar treatment can be applied to the projective hierarchy. Its lightface analog is known as the analytical hierarchy.

Summary

Each class is at least as large as the classes above it.

Lightface Boldface
Σ0
0
= Π0
0
= Δ0
0
(sometimes the same as Δ0
1
)
Σ0
0
= Π0
0
= Δ0
0
(if defined)
Δ0
1
= recursive
Δ0
1
= clopen
Σ0
1
= recursively enumerable
Π0
1
= co-recursively enumerable
Σ0
1
= G = open
Π0
1
= F = closed
Δ0
2
Δ0
2
Σ0
2
Π0
2
Σ0
2
= Fσ
Π0
2
= Gδ
Δ0
3
Δ0
3
Σ0
3
Π0
3
Σ0
3
= Gδσ
Π0
3
= Fσδ
Σ0
= Π0
= Δ0
= Σ1
0
= Π1
0
= Δ1
0
= arithmetical
Σ0
= Π0
= Δ0
= Σ1
0
= Π1
0
= Δ1
0
= boldface arithmetical
Δ0
α
recursive)
Δ0
α
countable)
Σ0
α
Π0
α
Σ0
α
Π0
α
Σ0
ωCK
1
= Π0
ωCK
1
= Δ0
ωCK
1
= Δ1
1
= hyperarithmetical
Σ0
ω1
= Π0
ω1
= Δ0
ω1
= Δ1
1
= B = Borel
Σ1
1
= lightface analytic
Π1
1
= lightface coanalytic
Σ1
1
= A = analytic
Π1
1
= CA = coanalytic
Δ1
2
Δ1
2
Σ1
2
Π1
2
Σ1
2
= PCA
Π1
2
= CPCA
Δ1
3
Δ1
3
Σ1
3
Π1
3
Σ1
3
= PCPCA
Π1
3
= CPCPCA
Σ1
= Π1
= Δ1
= Σ2
0
= Π2
0
= Δ2
0
= analytical
Σ1
= Π1
= Δ1
= Σ2
0
= Π2
0
= Δ2
0
= P = projective

Related Research Articles

In mathematics, a Borel set is any set in a topological space that can be formed from open sets through the operations of countable union, countable intersection, and relative complement. Borel sets are named after Émile Borel.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Arithmetical hierarchy</span> Hierarchy of complexity classes for formulas defining sets

In mathematical logic, the arithmetical hierarchy, arithmetic hierarchy or Kleene–Mostowski hierarchy classifies certain sets based on the complexity of formulas that define them. Any set that receives a classification is called arithmetical. The arithmetical hierarchy was invented independently by Kleene (1943) and Mostowski (1946).

In the mathematical field of topology, a Gδ set is a subset of a topological space that is a countable intersection of open sets. The notation originated from the German nouns Gebiet'open set' and Durchschnitt'intersection'. Historically Gδ sets were also called inner limiting sets, but that terminology is not in use anymore. Gδ sets, and their dual, F𝜎 sets, are the second level of the Borel hierarchy.

In mathematical logic, descriptive set theory (DST) is the study of certain classes of "well-behaved" subsets of the real line and other Polish spaces. As well as being one of the primary areas of research in set theory, it has applications to other areas of mathematics such as functional analysis, ergodic theory, the study of operator algebras and group actions, and mathematical logic.

In mathematical logic and descriptive set theory, the analytical hierarchy is an extension of the arithmetical hierarchy. The analytical hierarchy of formulas includes formulas in the language of second-order arithmetic, which can have quantifiers over both the set of natural numbers, , and over functions from to . The analytical hierarchy of sets classifies sets by the formulas that can be used to define them; it is the lightface version of the projective hierarchy.

In the mathematical field of descriptive set theory, a subset of a Polish space is an analytic set if it is a continuous image of a Polish space. These sets were first defined by Luzin (1917) and his student Souslin (1917).

In the mathematical field of descriptive set theory, a subset of a Polish space is projective if it is for some positive integer . Here is

In set theory, the Baire space is the set of all infinite sequences of natural numbers with a certain topology. This space is commonly used in descriptive set theory, to the extent that its elements are often called "reals". It is denoted NN, ωω, by the symbol or also ωω, not to be confused with the countable ordinal obtained by ordinal exponentiation.

In set theory, a prewellordering on a set is a preorder on that is strongly connected and well-founded in the sense that the induced relation defined by is a well-founded relation.

A subset of a topological space has the property of Baire, or is called an almost open set, if it differs from an open set by a meager set; that is, if there is an open set such that is meager.

Determinacy is a subfield of set theory, a branch of mathematics, that examines the conditions under which one or the other player of a game has a winning strategy, and the consequences of the existence of such strategies. Alternatively and similarly, "determinacy" is the property of a game whereby such a strategy exists. Determinacy was introduced by Gale and Stewart in 1950, under the name "determinateness".

Effective descriptive set theory is the branch of descriptive set theory dealing with sets of reals having lightface definitions; that is, definitions that do not require an arbitrary real parameter. Thus effective descriptive set theory combines descriptive set theory with recursion theory.

In descriptive set theory, within mathematics, Wadge degrees are levels of complexity for sets of reals. Sets are compared by continuous reductions. The Wadge hierarchy is the structure of Wadge degrees. These concepts are named after William W. Wadge.

In mathematical logic, the Borel hierarchy is a stratification of the Borel algebra generated by the open subsets of a Polish space; elements of this algebra are called Borel sets. Each Borel set is assigned a unique countable ordinal number called the rank of the Borel set. The Borel hierarchy is of particular interest in descriptive set theory.

The low basis theorem is one of several basis theorems in computability theory, each of which showing that, given an infinite subtree of the binary tree , it is possible to find an infinite path through the tree with particular computability properties. The low basis theorem, in particular, shows that there must be a path which is low; that is, the Turing jump of the path is Turing equivalent to the halting problem .

In computability theory, hyperarithmetic theory is a generalization of Turing computability. It has close connections with definability in second-order arithmetic and with weak systems of set theory such as Kripke–Platek set theory. It is an important tool in effective descriptive set theory.

In descriptive set theory, the Borel determinacy theorem states that any Gale–Stewart game whose payoff set is a Borel set is determined, meaning that one of the two players will have a winning strategy for the game. A Gale–Stewart game is a possibly infinite two-player game, where both players have perfect information and no randomness is involved.

In computability theory, a Π01 class is a subset of 2ω of a certain form. These classes are of interest as technical tools within recursion theory and effective descriptive set theory. They are also used in the application of recursion theory to other branches of mathematics.

This is a glossary of set theory.

In computability theory, there are a number of basis theorems. These theorems show that particular kinds of sets always must have some members that are, in terms of Turing degree, not too complicated. One family of basis theorems concern nonempty effectively closed sets ; these theorems are studied as part of classical computability theory. Another family of basis theorems concern nonempty lightface analytic sets ; these theorems are studied as part of hyperarithmetical theory.

References