Set (mathematics)

Last updated
A set of polygons in an Euler diagram Example of a set.svg
A set of polygons in an Euler diagram
This set equals the one depicted above since both have the very same elements. Example of a set rearranged.svg
This set equals the one depicted above since both have the very same elements.

In mathematics, a set is a collection of different [1] things; [2] [3] [4] these things are called elements or members of the set and are typically mathematical objects of any kind: numbers, symbols, points in space, lines, other geometrical shapes, variables, or even other sets. [5] A set may have a finite number of elements or be an infinite set. There is a unique set with no elements, called the empty set; a set with a single element is a singleton.

Contents

Sets are uniquely characterized by their elements; this means that two sets that have precisely the same elements are equal (they are the same set). [6] This property is called extensionality. In particular, this implies that there is only one empty set.

Sets are ubiquitous in modern mathematics. Indeed, set theory, more specifically Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, has been the standard way to provide rigorous foundations for all branches of mathematics since the first half of the 20th century. [5]

Definition and notation

Mathematical texts commonly denote sets by capital letters [7] [5] in italic, such as A, B, C. [8] A set may also be called a collection or family, especially when its elements are themselves sets.

Roster notation

Roster or enumeration notation defines a set by listing its elements between curly brackets, separated by commas: [9] [10] [11] [12]

A = {4, 2, 1, 3}
B = {blue, white, red}.

This notation was introduced by Ernst Zermelo in 1908. [13] In a set, all that matters is whether each element is in it or not, so the ordering of the elements in roster notation is irrelevant (in contrast, in a sequence, a tuple, or a permutation of a set, the ordering of the terms matters). For example, {2, 4, 6} and {4, 6, 4, 2} represent the same set. [14] [8] [15]

For sets with many elements, especially those following an implicit pattern, the list of members can be abbreviated using an ellipsis '...'. [16] [17] For instance, the set of the first thousand positive integers may be specified in roster notation as

{1, 2, 3, ..., 1000}.

Infinite sets in roster notation

An infinite set is a set with an infinite number of elements. If the pattern of its elements is obvious, an infinite set can be given in roster notation, with an ellipsis placed at the end of the list, or at both ends, to indicate that the list continues forever. For example, the set of nonnegative integers is

{0, 1, 2, 3, 4, ...},

and the set of all integers is

{..., −3, −2, −1, 0, 1, 2, 3, ...}.

Semantic definition

Another way to define a set is to use a rule to determine what the elements are:

Let A be the set whose members are the first four positive integers.
Let B be the set of colors of the French flag.

Such a definition is called a semantic description. [18] [19]

Set-builder notation

Set-builder notation specifies a set as a selection from a larger set, determined by a condition on the elements. [19] [20] [21] For example, a set F can be defined as follows:

In this notation, the vertical bar "|" means "such that", and the description can be interpreted as "F is the set of all numbers n such that n is an integer in the range from 0 to 19 inclusive". Some authors use a colon ":" instead of the vertical bar. [22]

Classifying methods of definition

Philosophy uses specific terms to classify types of definitions:

Membership

If B is a set and x is an element of B, this is written in shorthand as xB, which can also be read as "x belongs to B", or "x is in B". [23] The statement "y is not an element of B" is written as yB, which can also be read as "y is not in B". [24] [25]

For example, with respect to the sets A = {1, 2, 3, 4}, B = {blue, white, red}, and F = {n | n is an integer, and 0 ≤ n ≤ 19},

4 ∈ A and 12 ∈ F; and
20 ∉ F and green ∉ B.

The empty set

The empty set (or null set) is the unique set that has no members. It is denoted , , { }, [26] [27] ϕ, [28] or ϕ. [29]

Singleton sets

A singleton set is a set with exactly one element; such a set may also be called a unit set. [6] Any such set can be written as {x}, where x is the element. The set {x} and the element x mean different things; Halmos [30] draws the analogy that a box containing a hat is not the same as the hat.

Subsets

If every element of set A is also in B, then A is described as being a subset of B, or contained in B, written AB, [31] or BA. [32] The latter notation may be read B contains A, B includes A, or B is a superset of A. The relationship between sets established by ⊆ is called inclusion or containment. Two sets are equal if they contain each other: AB and BA is equivalent to A = B. [20]

If A is a subset of B, but A is not equal to B, then A is called a proper subset of B. This can be written AB. Likewise, BA means B is a proper superset of A, i.e. B contains A, and is not equal to A.

A third pair of operators ⊂ and ⊃ are used differently by different authors: some authors use AB and BA to mean A is any subset of B (and not necessarily a proper subset), [33] [24] while others reserve AB and BA for cases where A is a proper subset of B. [31]

Examples:

The empty set is a subset of every set, [26] and every set is a subset of itself: [33]

Euler and Venn diagrams

A is a subset of B.
B is a superset of A. Venn A subset B.svg
A is a subset of B.
B is a superset of A.

An Euler diagram is a graphical representation of a collection of sets; each set is depicted as a planar region enclosed by a loop, with its elements inside. If A is a subset of B, then the region representing A is completely inside the region representing B. If two sets have no elements in common, the regions do not overlap.

A Venn diagram, in contrast, is a graphical representation of n sets in which the n loops divide the plane into 2n zones such that for each way of selecting some of the n sets (possibly all or none), there is a zone for the elements that belong to all the selected sets and none of the others. For example, if the sets are A, B, and C, there should be a zone for the elements that are inside A and C and outside B (even if such elements do not exist).

Special sets of numbers in mathematics

The natural numbers
N
{\displaystyle \mathbb {N} }
are contained in the integers
Z
{\displaystyle \mathbb {Z} }
, which are contained in the rational numbers
Q
{\displaystyle \mathbb {Q} }
, which are contained in the real numbers
R
{\displaystyle \mathbb {R} }
, which are contained in the complex numbers
C
{\displaystyle \mathbb {C} } NumberSetinC.svg
The natural numbers are contained in the integers , which are contained in the rational numbers , which are contained in the real numbers , which are contained in the complex numbers

There are sets of such mathematical importance, to which mathematicians refer so frequently, that they have acquired special names and notational conventions to identify them.

Many of these important sets are represented in mathematical texts using bold (e.g. ) or blackboard bold (e.g. ) typeface. [34] These include

Each of the above sets of numbers has an infinite number of elements. Each is a subset of the sets listed below it.

Sets of positive or negative numbers are sometimes denoted by superscript plus and minus signs, respectively. For example, represents the set of positive rational numbers.

Functions

A function (or mapping ) from a set A to a set B is a rule that assigns to each "input" element of A an "output" that is an element of B; more formally, a function is a special kind of relation, one that relates each element of A to exactly one element of B. A function is called

An injective function is called an injection, a surjective function is called a surjection, and a bijective function is called a bijection or one-to-one correspondence.

Cardinality

The cardinality of a set S, denoted |S|, is the number of members of S. [35] For example, if B = {blue, white, red}, then |B| = 3. Repeated members in roster notation are not counted, [36] [37] so |{blue, white, red, blue, white}| = 3, too.

More formally, two sets share the same cardinality if there exists a bijection between them.

The cardinality of the empty set is zero. [38]

Infinite sets and infinite cardinality

The list of elements of some sets is endless, or infinite . For example, the set of natural numbers is infinite. [20] In fact, all the special sets of numbers mentioned in the section above are infinite. Infinite sets have infinite cardinality.

Some infinite cardinalities are greater than others. Arguably one of the most significant results from set theory is that the set of real numbers has greater cardinality than the set of natural numbers. [39] Sets with cardinality less than or equal to that of are called countable sets ; these are either finite sets or countably infinite sets (sets of the same cardinality as ); some authors use "countable" to mean "countably infinite". Sets with cardinality strictly greater than that of are called uncountable sets .

However, it can be shown that the cardinality of a straight line (i.e., the number of points on a line) is the same as the cardinality of any segment of that line, of the entire plane, and indeed of any finite-dimensional Euclidean space. [40]

The continuum hypothesis

The continuum hypothesis, formulated by Georg Cantor in 1878, is the statement that there is no set with cardinality strictly between the cardinality of the natural numbers and the cardinality of a straight line. [41] In 1963, Paul Cohen proved that the continuum hypothesis is independent of the axiom system ZFC consisting of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice. [42] (ZFC is the most widely-studied version of axiomatic set theory.)

Power sets

The power set of a set S is the set of all subsets of S. [20] The empty set and S itself are elements of the power set of S, because these are both subsets of S. For example, the power set of {1, 2, 3} is {∅, {1}, {2}, {3}, {1, 2}, {1, 3}, {2, 3}, {1, 2, 3}}. The power set of a set S is commonly written as P(S) or 2S. [20] [43] [8]

If S has n elements, then P(S) has 2n elements. [44] For example, {1, 2, 3} has three elements, and its power set has 23 = 8 elements, as shown above.

If S is infinite (whether countable or uncountable), then P(S) is uncountable. Moreover, the power set is always strictly "bigger" than the original set, in the sense that any attempt to pair up the elements of S with the elements of P(S) will leave some elements of P(S) unpaired. (There is never a bijection from S onto P(S).) [45]

Partitions

A partition of a set S is a set of nonempty subsets of S, such that every element x in S is in exactly one of these subsets. That is, the subsets are pairwise disjoint (meaning any two sets of the partition contain no element in common), and the union of all the subsets of the partition is S. [46] [47]

Basic operations

The complement of A in U Venn1010.svg
The complement of A in U

Suppose that a universal set U (a set containing all elements being discussed) has been fixed, and that A is a subset of U.

The union of A and B, denoted A [?] B Venn0111.svg
The union of A and B, denoted AB
The intersection of A and B, denoted A [?] B Venn0001.svg
The intersection of A and B, denoted AB
The set difference A \ B Venn0100.svg
The set differenceA \ B
The symmetric difference of A and B Venn0110.svg
The symmetric difference of A and B

Given any two sets A and B,

Examples:

The operations above satisfy many identities. For example, one of De Morgan's laws states that (AB)′ = A′ ∩ B (that is, the elements outside the union of A and B are the elements that are outside Aand outside B).

The cardinality of A × B is the product of the cardinalities of A and B. This is an elementary fact when A and B are finite. When one or both are infinite, multiplication of cardinal numbers is defined to make this true.

The power set of any set becomes a Boolean ring with symmetric difference as the addition of the ring and intersection as the multiplication of the ring.

Applications

Sets are ubiquitous in modern mathematics. For example, structures in abstract algebra, such as groups, fields and rings, are sets closed under one or more operations.

One of the main applications of naive set theory is in the construction of relations. A relation from a domain A to a codomain B is a subset of the Cartesian product A × B. For example, considering the set S = {rock, paper, scissors} of shapes in the game of the same name, the relation "beats" from S to S is the set B = {(scissors,paper), (paper,rock), (rock,scissors)}; thus x beats y in the game if the pair (x,y) is a member of B. Another example is the set F of all pairs (x, x2), where x is real. This relation is a subset of R × R, because the set of all squares is subset of the set of all real numbers. Since for every x in R, one and only one pair (x,...) is found in F, it is called a function. In functional notation, this relation can be written as F(x) = x2.

Principle of inclusion and exclusion

The inclusion-exclusion principle for two finite sets states that the size of their union is the sum of the sizes of the sets minus the size of their intersection. A union B.svg
The inclusion-exclusion principle for two finite sets states that the size of their union is the sum of the sizes of the sets minus the size of their intersection.

The inclusion–exclusion principle is a technique for counting the elements in a union of two finite sets in terms of the sizes of the two sets and their intersection. It can be expressed symbolically as

A more general form of the principle gives the cardinality of any finite union of finite sets:

History

The concept of a set emerged in mathematics at the end of the 19th century. [48] The German word for set, Menge, was coined by Bernard Bolzano in his work Paradoxes of the Infinite . [49] [50] [51]

Passage with a translation of the original set definition of Georg Cantor. The German word Menge for set is translated with aggregate here. Passage with the set definition of Georg Cantor.png
Passage with a translation of the original set definition of Georg Cantor. The German word Menge for set is translated with aggregate here.

Georg Cantor, one of the founders of set theory, gave the following definition at the beginning of his Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre: [52] [1]

A set is a gathering together into a whole of definite, distinct objects of our perception or our thought—which are called elements of the set.

Bertrand Russell introduced the distinction between a set and a class (a set is a class, but some classes, such as the class of all sets, are not sets; see Russell's paradox): [53]

When mathematicians deal with what they call a manifold, aggregate, Menge, ensemble, or some equivalent name, it is common, especially where the number of terms involved is finite, to regard the object in question (which is in fact a class) as defined by the enumeration of its terms, and as consisting possibly of a single term, which in that case is the class.

Naive set theory

The foremost property of a set is that it can have elements, also called members. Two sets are equal when they have the same elements. More precisely, sets A and B are equal if every element of A is an element of B, and every element of B is an element of A; this property is called the extensionality of sets. [23] As a consequence, e.g. {2, 4, 6} and {4, 6, 4, 2} represent the same set. Unlike sets, multisets can be distinguished by the number of occurrences of an element; e.g. [2, 4, 6] and [4, 6, 4, 2] represent different multisets, while [2, 4, 6] and [6, 4, 2] are equal. Tuples can even be distinguished by element order; e.g. (2, 4, 6) and (6, 4, 2) represent different tuples.

The simple concept of a set has proved enormously useful in mathematics, but paradoxes arise if no restrictions are placed on how sets can be constructed:

Naïve set theory defines a set as any well-defined collection of distinct elements, but problems arise from the vagueness of the term well-defined.

Axiomatic set theory

In subsequent efforts to resolve these paradoxes since the time of the original formulation of naïve set theory, the properties of sets have been defined by axioms. Axiomatic set theory takes the concept of a set as a primitive notion. [54] The purpose of the axioms is to provide a basic framework from which to deduce the truth or falsity of particular mathematical propositions (statements) about sets, using first-order logic. According to Gödel's incompleteness theorems however, it is not possible to use first-order logic to prove any such particular axiomatic set theory is free from paradox. [55]

See also

Notes

  1. 1 2 Cantor, Georg; Jourdain, Philip E.B. (Translator) (1915). Contributions to the founding of the theory of transfinite numbers. New York Dover Publications (1954 English translation). By an 'aggregate' (Menge) we are to understand any collection into a whole (Zusammenfassung zu einem Ganzen) M of definite and separate objects m of our intuition or our thought. Here: p.85
  2. P. K. Jain; Khalil Ahmad; Om P. Ahuja (1995). Functional Analysis. New Age International. p. 1. ISBN   978-81-224-0801-0.
  3. Samuel Goldberg (1 January 1986). Probability: An Introduction. Courier Corporation. p. 2. ISBN   978-0-486-65252-8.
  4. Thomas H. Cormen; Charles E Leiserson; Ronald L Rivest; Clifford Stein (2001). Introduction To Algorithms. MIT Press. p. 1070. ISBN   978-0-262-03293-3.
  5. 1 2 3 Halmos 1960, p.  1.
  6. 1 2 Stoll, Robert (1974). Sets, Logic and Axiomatic Theories . W. H. Freeman and Company. pp.  5. ISBN   9780716704577.
  7. Seymor Lipschutz; Marc Lipson (22 June 1997). Schaum's Outline of Discrete Mathematics. McGraw Hill Professional. p. 1. ISBN   978-0-07-136841-4.
  8. 1 2 3 "Introduction to Sets". www.mathsisfun.com. Retrieved 2020-08-19.
  9. Charles Roberts (24 June 2009). Introduction to Mathematical Proofs: A Transition. CRC Press. p. 45. ISBN   978-1-4200-6956-3.
  10. David Johnson; David B. Johnson; Thomas A. Mowry (June 2004). Finite Mathematics: Practical Applications (Docutech Version). W. H. Freeman. p. 220. ISBN   978-0-7167-6297-3.
  11. Ignacio Bello; Anton Kaul; Jack R. Britton (29 January 2013). Topics in Contemporary Mathematics. Cengage Learning. p. 47. ISBN   978-1-133-10742-2.
  12. Susanna S. Epp (4 August 2010). Discrete Mathematics with Applications. Cengage Learning. p. 13. ISBN   978-0-495-39132-6.
  13. A. Kanamori, "The Empty Set, the Singleton, and the Ordered Pair", p.278. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic vol. 9, no. 3, (2003). Accessed 21 August 2023.
  14. Stephen B. Maurer; Anthony Ralston (21 January 2005). Discrete Algorithmic Mathematics. CRC Press. p. 11. ISBN   978-1-4398-6375-6.
  15. D. Van Dalen; H. C. Doets; H. De Swart (9 May 2014). Sets: Naïve, Axiomatic and Applied: A Basic Compendium with Exercises for Use in Set Theory for Non Logicians, Working and Teaching Mathematicians and Students. Elsevier Science. p. 1. ISBN   978-1-4831-5039-0.
  16. Alfred Basta; Stephan DeLong; Nadine Basta (1 January 2013). Mathematics for Information Technology. Cengage Learning. p. 3. ISBN   978-1-285-60843-3.
  17. Laura Bracken; Ed Miller (15 February 2013). Elementary Algebra. Cengage Learning. p. 36. ISBN   978-0-618-95134-5.
  18. Halmos 1960, p.  4.
  19. 1 2 3 Frank Ruda (6 October 2011). Hegel's Rabble: An Investigation into Hegel's Philosophy of Right. Bloomsbury Publishing. p. 151. ISBN   978-1-4411-7413-0.
  20. 1 2 3 4 5 John F. Lucas (1990). Introduction to Abstract Mathematics. Rowman & Littlefield. p. 108. ISBN   978-0-912675-73-2.
  21. Weisstein, Eric W. "Set". Wolfram MathWorld. Retrieved 2020-08-19.
  22. Ralph C. Steinlage (1987). College Algebra. West Publishing Company. ISBN   978-0-314-29531-6.
  23. 1 2 Halmos 1960, p.  2.
  24. 1 2 Marek Capinski; Peter E. Kopp (2004). Measure, Integral and Probability. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 2. ISBN   978-1-85233-781-0.
  25. "Set Symbols". www.mathsisfun.com. Retrieved 2020-08-19.
  26. 1 2 Halmos 1960, p.  8.
  27. K.T. Leung; Doris Lai-chue Chen (1 July 1992). Elementary Set Theory, Part I/II. Hong Kong University Press. p. 27. ISBN   978-962-209-026-2.
  28. Aggarwal, M.L. (2021). "1. Sets". Understanding ISC Mathematics Class XI. Vol. 1. Arya Publications (Avichal Publishing Company). p. A=3.
  29. Sourendra Nath, De (January 2015). "Unit-1 Sets and Functions: 1. Set Theory". Chhaya Ganit (Ekadash Shreni). Scholar Books Pvt. Ltd. p. 5.
  30. Halmos 1960, Sect.2.
  31. 1 2 Felix Hausdorff (2005). Set Theory. American Mathematical Soc. p. 30. ISBN   978-0-8218-3835-8.
  32. Peter Comninos (6 April 2010). Mathematical and Computer Programming Techniques for Computer Graphics. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 7. ISBN   978-1-84628-292-8.
  33. 1 2 Halmos 1960, p.  3.
  34. 1 2 3 4 5 6 George Tourlakis (13 February 2003). Lectures in Logic and Set Theory: Volume 2, Set Theory. Cambridge University Press. p. 137. ISBN   978-1-139-43943-5.
  35. Yiannis N. Moschovakis (1994). Notes on Set Theory. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN   978-3-540-94180-4.
  36. Arthur Charles Fleck (2001). Formal Models of Computation: The Ultimate Limits of Computing. World Scientific. p. 3. ISBN   978-981-02-4500-9.
  37. William Johnston (25 September 2015). The Lebesgue Integral for Undergraduates. The Mathematical Association of America. p. 7. ISBN   978-1-939512-07-9.
  38. Karl J. Smith (7 January 2008). Mathematics: Its Power and Utility. Cengage Learning. p. 401. ISBN   978-0-495-38913-2.
  39. John Stillwell (16 October 2013). The Real Numbers: An Introduction to Set Theory and Analysis. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN   978-3-319-01577-4.
  40. David Tall (11 April 2006). Advanced Mathematical Thinking. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 211. ISBN   978-0-306-47203-9.
  41. Cantor, Georg (1878). "Ein Beitrag zur Mannigfaltigkeitslehre". Journal für die Reine und Angewandte Mathematik . 1878 (84): 242–258. doi:10.1515/crll.1878.84.242 (inactive 1 November 2024).{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: DOI inactive as of November 2024 (link)
  42. Cohen, Paul J. (December 15, 1963). "The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 50 (6): 1143–1148. Bibcode:1963PNAS...50.1143C. doi: 10.1073/pnas.50.6.1143 . JSTOR   71858. PMC   221287 . PMID   16578557.
  43. Halmos 1960, p.  19.
  44. Halmos 1960, p.  20.
  45. Edward B. Burger; Michael Starbird (18 August 2004). The Heart of Mathematics: An invitation to effective thinking. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 183. ISBN   978-1-931914-41-3.
  46. Toufik Mansour (27 July 2012). Combinatorics of Set Partitions. CRC Press. ISBN   978-1-4398-6333-6.
  47. Halmos 1960, p.  28.
  48. José Ferreirós (16 August 2007). Labyrinth of Thought: A History of Set Theory and Its Role in Modern Mathematics. Birkhäuser Basel. ISBN   978-3-7643-8349-7.
  49. Steve Russ (9 December 2004). The Mathematical Works of Bernard Bolzano. OUP Oxford. ISBN   978-0-19-151370-1.
  50. William Ewald; William Bragg Ewald (1996). From Kant to Hilbert Volume 1: A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics. OUP Oxford. p. 249. ISBN   978-0-19-850535-8.
  51. Paul Rusnock; Jan Sebestík (25 April 2019). Bernard Bolzano: His Life and Work. OUP Oxford. p. 430. ISBN   978-0-19-255683-7.
  52. Georg Cantor (Nov 1895). "Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre (1)". Mathematische Annalen (in German). 46 (4): 481–512.
  53. Bertrand Russell (1903) The Principles of Mathematics , chapter VI: Classes
  54. Jose Ferreiros (1 November 2001). Labyrinth of Thought: A History of Set Theory and Its Role in Modern Mathematics. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN   978-3-7643-5749-8.
  55. Raatikainen, Panu (2022). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2024-06-03.

Related Research Articles

Naive set theory is any of several theories of sets used in the discussion of the foundations of mathematics. Unlike axiomatic set theories, which are defined using formal logic, naive set theory is defined informally, in natural language. It describes the aspects of mathematical sets familiar in discrete mathematics, and suffices for the everyday use of set theory concepts in contemporary mathematics.

In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is countable if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numbers; this means that each element in the set may be associated to a unique natural number, or that the elements of the set can be counted one at a time, although the counting may never finish due to an infinite number of elements.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Cardinality</span> Definition of the number of elements in a set

In mathematics, cardinality describes a relationship between sets which compares their relative size. For example, the sets and are the same size as they each contain 3 elements. Beginning in the late 19th century, this concept was generalized to infinite sets, which allows one to distinguish between different types of infinity, and to perform arithmetic on them. There are two notions often used when referring to cardinality: one which compares sets directly using bijections and injections, and another which uses cardinal numbers. The cardinality of a set may also be called its size, when no confusion with other notions of size is possible.

In mathematics, any vector space has a corresponding dual vector space consisting of all linear forms on together with the vector space structure of pointwise addition and scalar multiplication by constants.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Basis (linear algebra)</span> Set of vectors used to define coordinates

In mathematics, a set B of vectors in a vector space V is called a basis if every element of V may be written in a unique way as a finite linear combination of elements of B. The coefficients of this linear combination are referred to as components or coordinates of the vector with respect to B. The elements of a basis are called basis vectors.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Natural number</span> Number used for counting

In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers0, 1, 2, 3, ..., while others start with 1, defining them as the positive integers1, 2, 3, .... Some authors acknowledge both definitions whenever convenient. Sometimes, the whole numbers are the natural numbers plus zero. In other cases, the whole numbers refer to all of the integers, including negative integers. The counting numbers are another term for the natural numbers, particularly in primary school education, and are ambiguous as well although typically start at 1.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Number</span> Used to count, measure, and label

A number is a mathematical object used to count, measure, and label. The most basic examples are the natural numbers 1, 2, 3, 4, and so forth. Numbers can be represented in language with number words. More universally, individual numbers can be represented by symbols, called numerals; for example, "5" is a numeral that represents the number five. As only a relatively small number of symbols can be memorized, basic numerals are commonly organized in a numeral system, which is an organized way to represent any number. The most common numeral system is the Hindu–Arabic numeral system, which allows for the representation of any non-negative integer using a combination of ten fundamental numeric symbols, called digits. In addition to their use in counting and measuring, numerals are often used for labels, for ordering, and for codes. In common usage, a numeral is not clearly distinguished from the number that it represents.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Nonstandard analysis</span> Calculus using a logically rigorous notion of infinitesimal numbers

The history of calculus is fraught with philosophical debates about the meaning and logical validity of fluxions or infinitesimal numbers. The standard way to resolve these debates is to define the operations of calculus using limits rather than infinitesimals. Nonstandard analysis instead reformulates the calculus using a logically rigorous notion of infinitesimal numbers.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Power set</span> Mathematical set of all subsets of a set

In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set S is the set of all subsets of S, including the empty set and S itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is postulated by the axiom of power set. The powerset of S is variously denoted as P(S), 𝒫(S), P(S), , or 2S. Any subset of P(S) is called a family of sets over S.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Subset</span> Set whose elements all belong to another set

In mathematics, a set A is a subset of a set B if all elements of A are also elements of B; B is then a superset of A. It is possible for A and B to be equal; if they are unequal, then A is a proper subset of B. The relationship of one set being a subset of another is called inclusion. A is a subset of B may also be expressed as B includes A or A is included in B. A k-subset is a subset with k elements.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Union (set theory)</span> Set of elements in any of some sets

In set theory, the union of a collection of sets is the set of all elements in the collection. It is one of the fundamental operations through which sets can be combined and related to each other. A nullary union refers to a union of zero sets and it is by definition equal to the empty set.

In mathematics, rings are algebraic structures that generalize fields: multiplication need not be commutative and multiplicative inverses need not exist. Informally, a ring is a set equipped with two binary operations satisfying properties analogous to those of addition and multiplication of integers. Ring elements may be numbers such as integers or complex numbers, but they may also be non-numerical objects such as polynomials, square matrices, functions, and power series.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Cantor's diagonal argument</span> Proof in set theory

Cantor's diagonal argument is a mathematical proof that there are infinite sets which cannot be put into one-to-one correspondence with the infinite set of natural numbers – informally, that there are sets which in some sense contain more elements than there are positive integers. Such sets are now called uncountable sets, and the size of infinite sets is treated by the theory of cardinal numbers, which Cantor began.

A mathematical symbol is a figure or a combination of figures that is used to represent a mathematical object, an action on mathematical objects, a relation between mathematical objects, or for structuring the other symbols that occur in a formula. As formulas are entirely constituted with symbols of various types, many symbols are needed for expressing all mathematics.

In mathematics, a free abelian group is an abelian group with a basis. Being an abelian group means that it is a set with an addition operation that is associative, commutative, and invertible. A basis, also called an integral basis, is a subset such that every element of the group can be uniquely expressed as an integer combination of finitely many basis elements. For instance the two-dimensional integer lattice forms a free abelian group, with coordinatewise addition as its operation, and with the two points (1,0) and (0,1) as its basis. Free abelian groups have properties which make them similar to vector spaces, and may equivalently be called free-modules, the free modules over the integers. Lattice theory studies free abelian subgroups of real vector spaces. In algebraic topology, free abelian groups are used to define chain groups, and in algebraic geometry they are used to define divisors.

In mathematics, a multiset is a modification of the concept of a set that, unlike a set, allows for multiple instances for each of its elements. The number of instances given for each element is called the multiplicity of that element in the multiset. As a consequence, an infinite number of multisets exist that contain only elements a and b, but vary in the multiplicities of their elements:

In mathematics, an element of a set is any one of the distinct objects that belong to that set. For example, given a set called A containing the first four positive integers, one could say that "3 is an element of A", expressed notationally as .

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Real number</span> Number representing a continuous quantity

In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one-dimensional quantity such as a distance, duration or temperature. Here, continuous means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every real number can be almost uniquely represented by an infinite decimal expansion.

In mathematics, a family, or indexed family, is informally a collection of objects, each associated with an index from some index set. For example, a family of real numbers, indexed by the set of integers, is a collection of real numbers, where a given function selects one real number for each integer as indexing.

In mathematics, an algebraic number field is an extension field of the field of rational numbers such that the field extension has finite degree . Thus is a field that contains and has finite dimension when considered as a vector space over .

References