In mathematics, a set A is a subset of a set B if all elements of A are also elements of B; B is then a superset of A. It is possible for A and B to be equal; if they are unequal, then A is a proper subset of B. The relationship of one set being a subset of another is called inclusion (or sometimes containment). A is a subset of B may also be expressed as B includes (or contains) A or A is included (or contained) in B. A k-subset is a subset with k elements.
When quantified, is represented as [1]
One can prove the statement by applying a proof technique known as the element argument [2] :
Let sets A and B be given. To prove that
- suppose that a is a particular but arbitrarily chosen element of A
- show that a is an element of B.
The validity of this technique can be seen as a consequence of universal generalization: the technique shows for an arbitrarily chosen element c. Universal generalisation then implies which is equivalent to as stated above.
If A and B are sets and every element of A is also an element of B, then:
If A is a subset of B, but A is not equal to B (i.e. there exists at least one element of B which is not an element of A), then:
The empty set, written or has no elements, and therefore is vacuously a subset of any set X.
Some authors use the symbols and to indicate subset and superset respectively; that is, with the same meaning as and instead of the symbols and [4] For example, for these authors, it is true of every set A that (a reflexive relation).
Other authors prefer to use the symbols and to indicate proper (also called strict) subset and proper superset respectively; that is, with the same meaning as and instead of the symbols and [5] This usage makes and analogous to the inequality symbols and For example, if then x may or may not equal y, but if then x definitely does not equal y, and is less than y (an irreflexive relation). Similarly, using the convention that is proper subset, if then A may or may not equal B, but if then A definitely does not equal B.
Another example in an Euler diagram:
The set of all subsets of is called its power set, and is denoted by . [6]
The inclusion relation is a partial order on the set defined by . We may also partially order by reverse set inclusion by defining
For the power set of a set S, the inclusion partial order is—up to an order isomorphism—the Cartesian product of (the cardinality of S) copies of the partial order on for which This can be illustrated by enumerating , and associating with each subset (i.e., each element of ) the k-tuple from of which the ith coordinate is 1 if and only if is a member of T.
The set of all -subsets of is denoted by , in analogue with the notation for binomial coefficients, which count the number of -subsets of an -element set. In set theory, the notation is also common, especially when is a transfinite cardinal number.
In mathematics, a binary relation associates elements of one set, called the domain, with elements of another set, called the codomain. Precisely, a binary relation over sets and is a set of ordered pairs consisting of elements from and from . It encodes the common concept of relation: an element is related to an element , if and only if the pair belongs to the set of ordered pairs that defines the binary relation.
In mathematics, especially order theory, a partial order on a set is an arrangement such that, for certain pairs of elements, one precedes the other. The word partial is used to indicate that not every pair of elements needs to be comparable; that is, there may be pairs for which neither element precedes the other. Partial orders thus generalize total orders, in which every pair is comparable.
In the mathematical field of order theory, an ultrafilter on a given partially ordered set is a certain subset of namely a maximal filter on that is, a proper filter on that cannot be enlarged to a bigger proper filter on
Distributions, also known as Schwartz distributions or generalized functions, are objects that generalize the classical notion of functions in mathematical analysis. Distributions make it possible to differentiate functions whose derivatives do not exist in the classical sense. In particular, any locally integrable function has a distributional derivative.
In mathematics, the symmetric difference of two sets, also known as the disjunctive union and set sum, is the set of elements which are in either of the sets, but not in their intersection. For example, the symmetric difference of the sets and is .
In mathematics, a subset of a given set is closed under an operation of the larger set if performing that operation on members of the subset always produces a member of that subset. For example, the natural numbers are closed under addition, but not under subtraction: 1 − 2 is not a natural number, although both 1 and 2 are.
In combinatorics, a branch of mathematics, the inclusion–exclusion principle is a counting technique which generalizes the familiar method of obtaining the number of elements in the union of two finite sets; symbolically expressed as
In mathematics, in the area of order theory, an antichain is a subset of a partially ordered set such that any two distinct elements in the subset are incomparable.
In mathematics, a subset of a preordered set is said to be cofinal or frequent in if for every it is possible to find an element in that is "larger than ".
In set theory, a prewellordering on a set is a preorder on that is strongly connected and well-founded in the sense that the induced relation defined by is a well-founded relation.
In mathematics, an upper set of a partially ordered set is a subset with the following property: if s is in S and if x in X is larger than s, then x is in S. In other words, this means that any x element of X that is to some element of S is necessarily also an element of S. The term lower set is defined similarly as being a subset S of X with the property that any element x of X that is to some element of S is necessarily also an element of S.
In mathematics, set-theoretic topology is a subject that combines set theory and general topology. It focuses on topological questions that are independent of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZFC).
In mathematics, specifically order theory, the join of a subset of a partially ordered set is the supremum of denoted and similarly, the meet of is the infimum, denoted In general, the join and meet of a subset of a partially ordered set need not exist. Join and meet are dual to one another with respect to order inversion.
In mathematics, an ordered vector space or partially ordered vector space is a vector space equipped with a partial order that is compatible with the vector space operations.
In the mathematical field of set theory, an ideal is a partially ordered collection of sets that are considered to be "small" or "negligible". Every subset of an element of the ideal must also be in the ideal, and the union of any two elements of the ideal must also be in the ideal.
In mathematics, a filter on a set is a family of subsets such that:
In mathematics, a cardinal function is a function that returns cardinal numbers.
In functional analysis, a branch of mathematics, a strictly singular operator is a bounded linear operator between normed spaces which is not bounded below on any infinite-dimensional subspace.
Filters in topology, a subfield of mathematics, can be used to study topological spaces and define all basic topological notions such as convergence, continuity, compactness, and more. Filters, which are special families of subsets of some given set, also provide a common framework for defining various types of limits of functions such as limits from the left/right, to infinity, to a point or a set, and many others. Special types of filters called ultrafilters have many useful technical properties and they may often be used in place of arbitrary filters.
In the mathematical field of set theory, an ultrafilter on a set is a maximal filter on the set In other words, it is a collection of subsets of that satisfies the definition of a filter on and that is maximal with respect to inclusion, in the sense that there does not exist a strictly larger collection of subsets of that is also a filter. Equivalently, an ultrafilter on the set can also be characterized as a filter on with the property that for every subset of either or its complement belongs to the ultrafilter.