Binary relation

Last updated

In mathematics, a binary relation over sets X and Y is a subset of the Cartesian product ; that is, it is a set of ordered pairs (x, y) consisting of elements x in X and y in Y. [1] It encodes the common concept of relation: an element x is related to an element y, if and only if the pair (x, y) belongs to the set of ordered pairs that defines the binary relation. A binary relation is the most studied special case n = 2 of an n-ary relation over sets X1, ..., Xn, which is a subset of the Cartesian product [1] [2]

Contents

An example of a binary relation is the "divides" relation over the set of prime numbers and the set of integers , in which each prime p is related to each integer z that is a multiple of p, but not to an integer that is not a multiple of p. In this relation, for instance, the prime number 2 is related to numbers such as −4, 0, 6, 10, but not to 1 or 9, just as the prime number 3 is related to 0, 6, and 9, but not to 4 or 13.

Binary relations are used in many branches of mathematics to model a wide variety of concepts. These include, among others:

A function may be defined as a special kind of binary relation. [3] Binary relations are also heavily used in computer science.

A binary relation over sets X and Y is an element of the power set of Since the latter set is ordered by inclusion (⊆), each relation has a place in the lattice of subsets of A binary relation is either a homogeneous relation or a heterogeneous relation depending on whether X = Y or not.

Since relations are sets, they can be manipulated using set operations, including union, intersection, and complementation, and satisfying the laws of an algebra of sets. Beyond that, operations like the converse of a relation and the composition of relations are available, satisfying the laws of a calculus of relations, for which there are textbooks by Ernst Schröder, [4] Clarence Lewis, [5] and Gunther Schmidt. [6] A deeper analysis of relations involves decomposing them into subsets called concepts, and placing them in a complete lattice.

In some systems of axiomatic set theory, relations are extended to classes, which are generalizations of sets. This extension is needed for, among other things, modeling the concepts of "is an element of" or "is a subset of" in set theory, without running into logical inconsistencies such as Russell's paradox.

The terms correspondence, [7] dyadic relation and two-place relation are synonyms for binary relation, though some authors use the term "binary relation" for any subset of a Cartesian product without reference to X and Y, and reserve the term "correspondence" for a binary relation with reference to X and Y.[ citation needed ]

Definition

Given sets X and Y, the Cartesian product is defined as and its elements are called ordered pairs.

A binary relationR over sets X and Y is a subset of [1] [8] The set X is called the domain [1] or set of departure of R, and the set Y the codomain or set of destination of R. In order to specify the choices of the sets X and Y, some authors define a binary relation or correspondence as an ordered triple (X, Y, G), where G is a subset of called the graph of the binary relation. The statement reads "x is R-related to y" and is denoted by xRy. [4] [5] [6] [note 1] The domain of definition or active domain [1] of R is the set of all x such that xRy for at least one y. The codomain of definition, active codomain, [1] image or range of R is the set of all y such that xRy for at least one x. The field of R is the union of its domain of definition and its codomain of definition. [10] [11] [12]

When a binary relation is called a homogeneous relation (or endorelation). Otherwise it is a heterogeneous relation . [13] [14] [15]

In a binary relation, the order of the elements is important; if then yRx can be true or false independently of xRy. For example, 3 divides 9, but 9 does not divide 3.

Examples

2nd example relation
A
B
ballcardollcup
John+
Mary+
Venus+
1st example relation
A
B
ballcardollcup
John+
Mary+
Ian
Venus+

1) The following example shows that the choice of codomain is important. Suppose there are four objects and four people A possible relation on A and B is the relation "is owned by", given by That is, John owns the ball, Mary owns the doll, and Venus owns the car. Nobody owns the cup and Ian owns nothing, see 1st example. As a set, R does not involve Ian, and therefore R could have been viewed as a subset of i.e. a relation over A and see 2nd example. While the 2nd example relation is surjective (see below), the 1st is not.

Oceans and continents (islands omitted) Oceans and continents coarse.png
Oceans and continents (islands omitted)
Ocean borders continent
NASAAFEUASAUAA
Indian0010111
Arctic1001100
Atlantic1111001
Pacific1100111

2) Let A = {Indian, Arctic, Atlantic, Pacific}, the oceans of the globe, and B = { NA, SA, AF, EU, AS, AU, AA }, the continents. Let aRb represent that ocean a borders continent b. Then the logical matrix for this relation is:

The connectivity of the planet Earth can be viewed through R RT and RTR, the former being a relation on A, which is the universal relation ( or a logical matrix of all ones). This universal relation reflects the fact that every ocean is separated from the others by at most one continent. On the other hand, RTR is a relation on which fails to be universal because at least two oceans must be traversed to voyage from Europe to Australia.

3) Visualization of relations leans on graph theory: For relations on a set (homogeneous relations), a directed graph illustrates a relation and a graph a symmetric relation. For heterogeneous relations a hypergraph has edges possibly with more than two nodes, and can be illustrated by a bipartite graph.

Just as the clique is integral to relations on a set, so bicliques are used to describe heterogeneous relations; indeed, they are the "concepts" that generate a lattice associated with a relation.

The various t axes represent time for observers in motion, the corresponding x axes are their lines of simultaneity Add velocity ark POV.svg
The various t axes represent time for observers in motion, the corresponding x axes are their lines of simultaneity

4) Hyperbolic orthogonality: Time and space are different categories, and temporal properties are separate from spatial properties. The idea of simultaneous events is simple in absolute time and space since each time t determines a simultaneous hyperplane in that cosmology. Herman Minkowski changed that when he articulated the notion of relative simultaneity, which exists when spatial events are "normal" to a time characterized by a velocity. He used an indefinite inner product, and specified that a time vector is normal to a space vector when that product is zero. The indefinite inner product in a composition algebra is given by

where the overbar denotes conjugation.

As a relation between some temporal events and some spatial events, hyperbolic orthogonality (as found in split-complex numbers) is a heterogeneous relation. [16]

5) A geometric configuration can be considered a relation between its points and its lines. The relation is expressed as incidence. Finite and infinite projective and affine planes are included. Jakob Steiner pioneered the cataloguing of configurations with the Steiner systems which have an n-element set S and a set of k-element subsets called blocks, such that a subset with t elements lies in just one block. These incidence structures have been generalized with block designs. The incidence matrix used in these geometrical contexts corresponds to the logical matrix used generally with binary relations.

An incidence structure is a triple D = (V, B, I) where V and B are any two disjoint sets and I is a binary relation between V and B, i.e. The elements of V will be called points, those of B blocks and those of I flags. [17]

Special types of binary relations

Examples of four types of binary relations over the real numbers: one-to-one (in green), one-to-many (in blue), many-to-one (in red), many-to-many (in black). The four types of binary relations.png
Examples of four types of binary relations over the real numbers: one-to-one (in green), one-to-many (in blue), many-to-one (in red), many-to-many (in black).

Some important types of binary relations R over sets X and Y are listed below.

Set-like[ citation needed ] (or local)
for all the class of all y such that yRx is a set. (This makes sense only if relations over proper classes are allowed.) For example, the usual ordering < over the class of ordinal numbers is a set-like relation, while its inverse > is not.

Uniqueness properties:

Totality properties (only definable if the domain X and codomain Y are specified):

Uniqueness and totality properties (only definable if the domain X and codomain Y are specified):

Operations on binary relations

Union

If R and S are binary relations over sets X and Y then is the union relation of R and S over X and Y.

The identity element is the empty relation. For example, is the union of < and =, and is the union of > and =.

Intersection

If R and S are binary relations over sets X and Y then is the intersection relation of R and S over X and Y.

The identity element is the universal relation. For example, the relation "is divisible by 6" is the intersection of the relations "is divisible by 3" and "is divisible by 2".

Composition

If R is a binary relation over sets X and Y, and S is a binary relation over sets Y and Z then (also denoted by R; S) is the composition relation of R and S over X and Z.

The identity element is the identity relation. The order of R and S in the notation used here agrees with the standard notational order for composition of functions. For example, the composition "is mother of" "is parent of" yields "is maternal grandparent of", while the composition "is parent of" "is mother of" yields "is grandmother of". For the former case, if x is the parent of y and y is the mother of z, then x is the maternal grandparent of z.

Converse

If R is a binary relation over sets X and Y then is the converse relation of R over Y and X.

For example, = is the converse of itself, as is and and are each other's converse, as are and A binary relation is equal to its converse if and only if it is symmetric.

Complement

If R is a binary relation over sets X and Y then (also denoted by R or ¬R) is the complementary relation of R over X and Y.

For example, and are each other's complement, as are and and and and and, for total orders, also < and and > and

The complement of the converse relation is the converse of the complement:

If the complement has the following properties:

Restriction

If R is a binary homogeneous relation over a set X and S is a subset of X then is the restriction relation of R to S over X.

If R is a binary relation over sets X and Y and if S is a subset of X then is the left-restriction relation of R to S over X and Y.

If R is a binary relation over sets X and Y and if S is a subset of Y then is the right-restriction relation of R to S over X and Y.

If a relation is reflexive, irreflexive, symmetric, antisymmetric, asymmetric, transitive, total, trichotomous, a partial order, total order, strict weak order, total preorder (weak order), or an equivalence relation, then so too are its restrictions.

However, the transitive closure of a restriction is a subset of the restriction of the transitive closure, i.e., in general not equal. For example, restricting the relation "x is parent of y" to females yields the relation "x is mother of the woman y"; its transitive closure doesn't relate a woman with her paternal grandmother. On the other hand, the transitive closure of "is parent of" is "is ancestor of"; its restriction to females does relate a woman with her paternal grandmother.

Also, the various concepts of completeness (not to be confused with being "total") do not carry over to restrictions. For example, over the real numbers a property of the relation is that every non-empty subset with an upper bound in has a least upper bound (also called supremum) in However, for the rational numbers this supremum is not necessarily rational, so the same property does not hold on the restriction of the relation to the rational numbers.

A binary relation R over sets X and Y is said to be contained in a relation S over X and Y, written if R is a subset of S, that is, for all and if xRy, then xSy. If R is contained in S and S is contained in R, then R and S are called equal written R = S. If R is contained in S but S is not contained in R, then R is said to be smaller than S, written For example, on the rational numbers, the relation is smaller than and equal to the composition

Matrix representation

Binary relations over sets X and Y can be represented algebraically by logical matrices indexed by X and Y with entries in the Boolean semiring (addition corresponds to OR and multiplication to AND) where matrix addition corresponds to union of relations, matrix multiplication corresponds to composition of relations (of a relation over X and Y and a relation over Y and Z), [21] the Hadamard product corresponds to intersection of relations, the zero matrix corresponds to the empty relation, and the matrix of ones corresponds to the universal relation. Homogeneous relations (when X = Y) form a matrix semiring (indeed, a matrix semialgebra over the Boolean semiring) where the identity matrix corresponds to the identity relation. [22]

Sets versus classes

Certain mathematical "relations", such as "equal to", "subset of", and "member of", cannot be understood to be binary relations as defined above, because their domains and codomains cannot be taken to be sets in the usual systems of axiomatic set theory. For example, to model the general concept of "equality" as a binary relation take the domain and codomain to be the "class of all sets", which is not a set in the usual set theory.

In most mathematical contexts, references to the relations of equality, membership and subset are harmless because they can be understood implicitly to be restricted to some set in the context. The usual work-around to this problem is to select a "large enough" set A, that contains all the objects of interest, and work with the restriction =A instead of =. Similarly, the "subset of" relation needs to be restricted to have domain and codomain P(A) (the power set of a specific set A): the resulting set relation can be denoted by Also, the "member of" relation needs to be restricted to have domain A and codomain P(A) to obtain a binary relation that is a set. Bertrand Russell has shown that assuming to be defined over all sets leads to a contradiction in naive set theory.

Another solution to this problem is to use a set theory with proper classes, such as NBG or Morse–Kelley set theory, and allow the domain and codomain (and so the graph) to be proper classes: in such a theory, equality, membership, and subset are binary relations without special comment. (A minor modification needs to be made to the concept of the ordered triple (X, Y, G), as normally a proper class cannot be a member of an ordered tuple; or of course one can identify the binary relation with its graph in this context.) [23] With this definition one can for instance define a binary relation over every set and its power set.

Homogeneous relation

A homogeneous relation over a set X is a binary relation over X and itself, i.e. it is a subset of the Cartesian product [15] [24] [25] It is also simply called a (binary) relation over X.

A homogeneous relation R over a set X may be identified with a directed simple graph permitting loops, where X is the vertex set and R is the edge set (there is an edge from a vertex x to a vertex y if and only if xRy). The set of all homogeneous relations over a set X is the power set which is a Boolean algebra augmented with the involution of mapping of a relation to its converse relation. Considering composition of relations as a binary operation on , it forms a semigroup with involution.

Some important properties that a homogeneous relation R over a set X may have are:

A partial order is a relation that is reflexive, antisymmetric, and transitive. A strict partial order is a relation that is irreflexive, antisymmetric, and transitive. A total order is a relation that is reflexive, antisymmetric, transitive and connected. [29] A strict total order is a relation that is irreflexive, antisymmetric, transitive and connected. An equivalence relation is a relation that is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive. For example, "x divides y" is a partial, but not a total order on natural numbers "x < y" is a strict total order on and "x is parallel to y" is an equivalence relation on the set of all lines in the Euclidean plane.

All operations defined in the section Operations on binary relations also apply to homogeneous relations. Beyond that, a homogeneous relation over a set X may be subjected to closure operations like:

Heterogeneous relation

In mathematics, a heterogeneous relation is a binary relation, a subset of a Cartesian product where A and B are distinct sets. [30] The prefix hetero is from the Greek ἕτερος (heteros, "other, another, different").

A heterogeneous relation has been called a rectangular relation, [15] suggesting that it does not have the square-symmetry of a homogeneous relation on a set where Commenting on the development of binary relations beyond homogeneous relations, researchers wrote, "...a variant of the theory has evolved that treats relations from the very beginning as heterogeneous or rectangular, i.e. as relations where the normal case is that they are relations between different sets." [31]

Calculus of relations

Developments in algebraic logic have facilitated usage of binary relations. The calculus of relations includes the algebra of sets, extended by composition of relations and the use of converse relations. The inclusion meaning that aRb implies aSb, sets the scene in a lattice of relations. But since the inclusion symbol is superfluous. Nevertheless, composition of relations and manipulation of the operators according to Schröder rules, provides a calculus to work in the power set of

In contrast to homogeneous relations, the composition of relations operation is only a partial function. The necessity of matching range to domain of composed relations has led to the suggestion that the study of heterogeneous relations is a chapter of category theory as in the category of sets, except that the morphisms of this category are relations. The objects of the category Rel are sets, and the relation-morphisms compose as required in a category.[ citation needed ]

Induced concept lattice

Binary relations have been described through their induced concept lattices: A conceptCR satisfies two properties: (1) The logical matrix of C is the outer product of logical vectors

logical vectors.[ clarification needed ] (2) C is maximal, not contained in any other outer product. Thus C is described as a non-enlargeable rectangle.

For a given relation the set of concepts, enlarged by their joins and meets, forms an "induced lattice of concepts", with inclusion forming a preorder.

The MacNeille completion theorem (1937) (that any partial order may be embedded in a complete lattice) is cited in a 2013 survey article "Decomposition of relations on concept lattices". [32] The decomposition is

where f and g are functions, called mappings or left-total, univalent relations in this context. The "induced concept lattice is isomorphic to the cut completion of the partial order E that belongs to the minimal decomposition (f, g, E) of the relation R."

Particular cases are considered below: E total order corresponds to Ferrers type, and E identity corresponds to difunctional, a generalization of equivalence relation on a set.

Relations may be ranked by the Schein rank which counts the number of concepts necessary to cover a relation. [33] Structural analysis of relations with concepts provides an approach for data mining. [34]

Particular relations

Difunctional

Among the homogeneous relations on a set, the equivalence relations are distinguished for their ability to partition the set. With binary relations in general the idea is to partition objects by distinguishing attributes. One way this can be done is with an intervening set of indicators. The partitioning relation is a composition of relations using univalent relations

The logical matrix of such a relation R can be re-arranged as a block matrix with blocks of ones along the diagonal. In terms of the calculus of relations, in 1950 Jacques Riguet showed that such relations satisfy the inclusion

[35]

He named these relations difunctional since the composition F GT involves univalent relations, commonly called functions.

Using the notation {y: xRy} = xR, a difunctional relation can also be characterized as a relation R such that wherever x1R and x2R have a non-empty intersection, then these two sets coincide; formally implies [36]

In 1997 researchers found "utility of binary decomposition based on difunctional dependencies in database management." [37] Furthermore, difunctional relations are fundamental in the study of bisimulations. [38]

In the context of homogeneous relations, a partial equivalence relation is difunctional.

In automata theory, the term rectangular relation has also been used to denote a difunctional relation. This terminology recalls the fact that, when represented as a logical matrix, the columns and rows of a difunctional relation can be arranged as a block diagonal matrix with rectangular blocks of true on the (asymmetric) main diagonal. [39]

Ferrers type

A strict order on a set is a homogeneous relation arising in order theory. In 1951 Jacques Riguet adopted the ordering of a partition of an integer, called a Ferrers diagram, to extend ordering to binary relations in general. [40]

The corresponding logical matrix of a general binary relation has rows which finish with a sequence of ones. Thus the dots of a Ferrer's diagram are changed to ones and aligned on the right in the matrix.

An algebraic statement required for a Ferrers type relation R is

If any one of the relations is of Ferrers type, then all of them are. [30]

Contact

Suppose B is the power set of A, the set of all subsets of A. Then a relation g is a contact relation if it satisfies three properties:

The set membership relation, ε = "is an element of", satisfies these properties so ε is a contact relation. The notion of a general contact relation was introduced by Georg Aumann in 1970. [41] [42]

In terms of the calculus of relations, sufficient conditions for a contact relation include

where is the converse of set membership (∈). [43] :280

Preorder R\R

Every relation R generates a preorder which is the left residual. [44] In terms of converse and complements, Forming the diagonal of , the corresponding row of and column of will be of opposite logical values, so the diagonal is all zeros. Then

so that is a reflexive relation.

To show transitivity, one requires that Recall that is the largest relation such that Then

(repeat)
(Schröder's rule)
(complementation)
(definition)

The inclusion relation Ω on the power set of U can be obtained in this way from the membership relation on subsets of U:

[43] :283

Fringe of a relation

Given a relation R, a sub-relation called its fringe is defined as

When R is a partial identity relation, difunctional, or a block diagonal relation, then fringe(R) = R. Otherwise the fringe operator selects a boundary sub-relation described in terms of its logical matrix: fringe(R) is the side diagonal if R is an upper right triangular linear order or strict order. Fringe(R) is the block fringe if R is irreflexive () or upper right block triangular. Fringe(R) is a sequence of boundary rectangles when R is of Ferrers type.

On the other hand, Fringe(R) = ∅ when R is a dense, linear, strict order. [43]

Mathematical heaps

Given two sets A and B, the set of binary relations between them can be equipped with a ternary operation where bT denotes the converse relation of b. In 1953 Viktor Wagner used properties of this ternary operation to define semiheaps, heaps, and generalized heaps. [45] [46] The contrast of heterogeneous and homogeneous relations is highlighted by these definitions:

There is a pleasant symmetry in Wagner's work between heaps, semiheaps, and generalised heaps on the one hand, and groups, semigroups, and generalised groups on the other. Essentially, the various types of semiheaps appear whenever we consider binary relations (and partial one-one mappings) between different sets A and B, while the various types of semigroups appear in the case where A = B.

Christopher Hollings, "Mathematics across the Iron Curtain: a history of the algebraic theory of semigroups" [47]

See also

Notes

  1. Authors who deal with binary relations only as a special case of n-ary relations for arbitrary n usually write Rxy as a special case of Rx1...xn (prefix notation). [9]

Related Research Articles

Equivalence relation Mathematical concept for comparing objects

In mathematics, an equivalence relation is a binary relation that is reflexive, symmetric and transitive. The relation "is equal to" is the canonical example of an equivalence relation.

In mathematics, a finitary relation over sets X1, …, Xn is a subset of the Cartesian product X1 × … × Xn; that is, it is a set of n-tuples (x1, …, xn) consisting of elements xi in Xi. Typically, the relation describes a possible connection between the elements of an n-tuple. For example, the relation "x is divisible by y and z" consists of the set of 3-tuples such that when substituted to x, y and z, respectively, make the sentence true.

Partially ordered set Set ordered by a transitive, antisymmetric, and reflexive binary relation

In mathematics, especially order theory, a partially ordered set formalizes and generalizes the intuitive concept of an ordering, sequencing, or arrangement of the elements of a set. A poset consists of a set together with a binary relation indicating that, for certain pairs of elements in the set, one of the elements precedes the other in the ordering. The relation itself is called a "partial order." The word partial in the names "partial order" and "partially ordered set" is used as an indication that not every pair of elements needs to be comparable. That is, there may be pairs of elements for which neither element precedes the other in the poset. Partial orders thus generalize total orders, in which every pair is comparable.

Complement (set theory) Subset of the elements that are not in a given subset

In set theory, the complement of a set A, often denoted by Ac, are the elements not in A.

In mathematics, a homogeneous binary relation R on a set X is reflexive if it relates every element of X to itself.

In mathematics, a relation R on a set X is transitive if, for all elements a, b, c in X, whenever R relates a to b and b to c, then R also relates a to c. Each partial order as well as each equivalence relation needs to be transitive.

In mathematics, the transitive closure of a binary relation R on a set X is the smallest relation on X that contains R and is transitive. For finite sets, "smallest" can be taken in its usual sense, of having the fewest related pairs; for infinite sets it is the unique minimal transitive superset of R.

In mathematics, a set is closed under an operation if performing that operation on members of the set always produces a member of that set. For example, the positive integers are closed under addition, but not under subtraction: 1 − 2 is not a positive integer even though both 1 and 2 are positive integers. Another example is the set containing only zero, which is closed under addition, subtraction and multiplication.

In mathematics, a principal homogeneous space, or torsor, for a group G is a homogeneous space X for G in which the stabilizer subgroup of every point is trivial. Equivalently, a principal homogeneous space for a group G is a non-empty set X on which G acts freely and transitively . An analogous definition holds in other categories, where, for example,

This is a glossary of some terms used in various branches of mathematics that are related to the fields of order, lattice, and domain theory. Note that there is a structured list of order topics available as well. Other helpful resources might be the following overview articles:

Image (mathematics) Set of all values of a function

In mathematics, the image of a function is the set of all output values it may produce.

Restriction (mathematics)

In mathematics, the restriction of a function is a new function, denoted or , obtained by choosing a smaller domain A for the original function .

In mathematics, a partial equivalence relation on a set is a binary relation that is symmetric and transitive. In other words, it holds for all that:

  1. if , then (symmetry)
  2. if and , then (transitivity)

In mathematics, the converse relation, or transpose, of a binary relation is the relation that occurs when the order of the elements is switched in the relation. For example, the converse of the relation 'child of' is the relation 'parent of'. In formal terms, if and are sets and is a relation from to then is the relation defined so that if and only if In set-builder notation,

In the mathematics of binary relations, the composition of relations is the forming of a new binary relation R ; S from two given binary relations R and S. In the calculus of relations, the composition of relations is called relative multiplication, and its result is called a relative product. Function composition is the special case of composition of relations where all relations involved are functions.

In set theory, a branch of mathematics, a serial relation, also called a total or more specifically left-total relation, is a binary relation R for which every element of the domain has a corresponding range element.

In mathematics, a homogeneous relation over a set X is a binary relation over X and itself, i.e. it is a subset of the Cartesian product X × X. It is also simply called a (binary) relation over X. An example of a homogeneous relation is the relation of kinship, where the relation is over people.

In the mathematical field of category theory, an allegory is a category that has some of the structure of the category Rel of sets and binary relations between them. Allegories can be used as an abstraction of categories of relations, and in this sense the theory of allegories is a generalization of relation algebra to relations between different sorts. Allegories are also useful in defining and investigating certain constructions in category theory, such as exact completions.

In mathematics, a binary relation over sets X and Y is a subset of the Cartesian product X × Y; that is, it is a set of ordered pairs (x, y) consisting of elements x in X and y in Y. It encodes the common concept of relation: an element x is related to an element y, if and only if the pair (x, y) belongs to the set of ordered pairs that defines the binary relation. A binary relation is the most studied special case n = 2 of an n-ary relation over sets X1, ..., Xn, which is a subset of the Cartesian product X1 × ... × Xn.

In order theory, the Szpilrajn extension theorem, proved by Edward Szpilrajn in 1930, states that every strict partial order is contained in a total order. Intuitively, the theorem says that any method of comparing elements that leaves some pairs incomparable can be extended in such a way that every pair becomes comparable. The theorem is one of many examples of the use of the axiom of choice in the form of Zorn's lemma to find a maximal set with certain properties.

References

  1. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 Codd, Edgar Frank (June 1970). "A Relational Model of Data for Large Shared Data Banks" (PDF). Communications of the ACM. 13 (6): 377–387. doi:10.1145/362384.362685. S2CID   207549016 . Retrieved 2020-04-29.
  2. "The Definitive Glossary of Higher Mathematical Jargon—Relation". Math Vault. 2019-08-01. Retrieved 2019-12-11.
  3. "Relation definition – Math Insight". mathinsight.org. Retrieved 2019-12-11.
  4. 1 2 Ernst Schröder (1895) Algebra und Logic der Relative, via Internet Archive
  5. 1 2 C. I. Lewis (1918) A Survey of Symbolic Logic , pages 269 to 279, via internet Archive
  6. 1 2 3 Gunther Schmidt, 2010. Relational Mathematics. Cambridge University Press, ISBN   978-0-521-76268-7, Chapt. 5
  7. Jacobson, Nathan (2009), Basic Algebra II (2nd ed.) § 2.1.
  8. Enderton 1977 , Ch 3. pg. 40
  9. Hans Hermes (1973). Introduction to Mathematical Logic. Hochschultext (Springer-Verlag). London: Springer. ISBN   3540058192. ISSN   1431-4657. Sect.II.§1.1.4
  10. Suppes, Patrick (1972) [originally published by D. van Nostrand Company in 1960]. Axiomatic Set Theory . Dover. ISBN   0-486-61630-4.
  11. Smullyan, Raymond M.; Fitting, Melvin (2010) [revised and corrected republication of the work originally published in 1996 by Oxford University Press, New York]. Set Theory and the Continuum Problem. Dover. ISBN   978-0-486-47484-7.
  12. Levy, Azriel (2002) [republication of the work published by Springer-Verlag, Berlin, Heidelberg and New York in 1979]. Basic Set Theory. Dover. ISBN   0-486-42079-5.
  13. Schmidt, Gunther; Ströhlein, Thomas (2012). Relations and Graphs: Discrete Mathematics for Computer Scientists. Springer Science & Business Media. Definition 4.1.1. ISBN   978-3-642-77968-8.
  14. Christodoulos A. Floudas; Panos M. Pardalos (2008). Encyclopedia of Optimization (2nd ed.). Springer Science & Business Media. pp. 299–300. ISBN   978-0-387-74758-3.
  15. 1 2 3 Michael Winter (2007). Goguen Categories: A Categorical Approach to L-fuzzy Relations. Springer. pp. x–xi. ISBN   978-1-4020-6164-6.
  16. Wikibooks-logo-en-noslogan.svg Relative simultaneity at Wikibooks
  17. Beth, Thomas; Jungnickel, Dieter; Lenz, Hanfried (1986). Design Theory. Cambridge University Press. p. 15.. 2nd ed. (1999) ISBN   978-0-521-44432-3
  18. 1 2 3 4 Kilp, Knauer and Mikhalev: p. 3. The same four definitions appear in the following:
    • Peter J. Pahl; Rudolf Damrath (2001). Mathematical Foundations of Computational Engineering: A Handbook. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 506. ISBN   978-3-540-67995-0.
    • Eike Best (1996). Semantics of Sequential and Parallel Programs. Prentice Hall. pp. 19–21. ISBN   978-0-13-460643-9.
    • Robert-Christoph Riemann (1999). Modelling of Concurrent Systems: Structural and Semantical Methods in the High Level Petri Net Calculus. Herbert Utz Verlag. pp. 21–22. ISBN   978-3-89675-629-9.
  19. Mäs, Stephan (2007), "Reasoning on Spatial Semantic Integrity Constraints", Spatial Information Theory: 8th International Conference, COSIT 2007, Melbourne, Australia, September 19–23, 2007, Proceedings, Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 4736, Springer, pp. 285–302, doi:10.1007/978-3-540-74788-8_18
  20. Yao, Y.Y.; Wong, S.K.M. (1995). "Generalization of rough sets using relationships between attribute values" (PDF). Proceedings of the 2nd Annual Joint Conference on Information Sciences: 30–33..
  21. John C. Baez (6 Nov 2001). "quantum mechanics over a commutative rig". Newsgroup:  sci.physics.research. Usenet:   9s87n0$iv5@gap.cco.caltech.edu . Retrieved November 25, 2018.
  22. Droste, M., & Kuich, W. (2009). Semirings and Formal Power Series. Handbook of Weighted Automata, 3–28. doi : 10.1007/978-3-642-01492-5_1, pp. 7-10
  23. Tarski, Alfred; Givant, Steven (1987). A formalization of set theory without variables. American Mathematical Society. p.  3. ISBN   0-8218-1041-3.
  24. M. E. Müller (2012). Relational Knowledge Discovery. Cambridge University Press. p. 22. ISBN   978-0-521-19021-3.
  25. Peter J. Pahl; Rudolf Damrath (2001). Mathematical Foundations of Computational Engineering: A Handbook. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 496. ISBN   978-3-540-67995-0.
  26. Smith, Douglas; Eggen, Maurice; St. Andre, Richard (2006), A Transition to Advanced Mathematics (6th ed.), Brooks/Cole, p. 160, ISBN   0-534-39900-2
  27. Nievergelt, Yves (2002), Foundations of Logic and Mathematics: Applications to Computer Science and Cryptography, Springer-Verlag, p.  158 .
  28. Flaška, V.; Ježek, J.; Kepka, T.; Kortelainen, J. (2007). Transitive Closures of Binary Relations I (PDF). Prague: School of Mathematics – Physics Charles University. p. 1. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2013-11-02. Lemma 1.1 (iv). This source refers to asymmetric relations as "strictly antisymmetric".
  29. Joseph G. Rosenstein, Linear orderings, Academic Press, 1982, ISBN   0-12-597680-1, p. 4
  30. 1 2 Schmidt, Gunther; Ströhlein, Thomas (2012). Relations and Graphs: Discrete Mathematics for Computer Scientists. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 77. ISBN   978-3-642-77968-8.
  31. G. Schmidt, Claudia Haltensperger, and Michael Winter (1997) "Heterogeneous relation algebra", chapter 3 (pages 37 to 53) in Relational Methods in Computer Science, Advances in Computer Science, Springer books ISBN   3-211-82971-7
  32. R. Berghammer & M. Winter (2013) "Decomposition of relations on concept lattices", Fundamenta Informaticae 126(1): 37–82 doi : 10.3233/FI-2013-871
  33. Ki Hang Kim (1982) Boolean Matrix Theory and Applications, page 37, Marcel Dekker ISBN   0-8247-1788-0
  34. Ali Jaoua, Rehab Duwairi, Samir Elloumi, and Sadok Ben Yahia (2009) "Data mining, reasoning and incremental information retrieval through non enlargeable rectangular relation coverage", pages 199 to 210 in Relations and Kleene algebras in computer science, Lecture Notes in Computer Science 5827, Springer MR 2781235
  35. Jacques Riguet (1950) "Quelques proprietes des relations difonctionelles", Comptes Rendus 230: 1999–2000
  36. Chris Brink; Wolfram Kahl; Gunther Schmidt (1997). Relational Methods in Computer Science. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 200. ISBN   978-3-211-82971-4.
  37. Ali Jaoua, Nadin Belkhiter, Habib Ounalli, and Theodore Moukam (1997) "Databases", pages 197–210 in Relational Methods in Computer Science, edited by Chris Brink, Wolfram Kahl, and Gunther Schmidt, Springer Science & Business Media ISBN   978-3-211-82971-4
  38. Gumm, H. P.; Zarrad, M. (2014). "Coalgebraic Simulations and Congruences". Coalgebraic Methods in Computer Science. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. 8446. p. 118. doi:10.1007/978-3-662-44124-4_7. ISBN   978-3-662-44123-7.
  39. Julius Richard Büchi (1989). Finite Automata, Their Algebras and Grammars: Towards a Theory of Formal Expressions. Springer Science & Business Media. pp. 35–37. ISBN   978-1-4613-8853-1.
  40. J. Riguet (1951) "Les relations de Ferrers", Comptes Rendus 232: 1729,30
  41. Georg Aumann (1971). "Kontakt-Relationen". Sitzungsberichte der mathematisch-physikalischen Klasse der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften München. 1970 (II): 67–77.
  42. Anne K. Steiner (1970) Review:Kontakt-Relationen from Mathematical Reviews
  43. 1 2 3 Gunther Schmidt (2011) Relational Mathematics, pages 211−15, Cambridge University Press ISBN   978-0-521-76268-7
  44. In this context, the symbol does not mean "set difference".
  45. Viktor Wagner (1953) "The theory of generalised heaps and generalised groups", Matematicheskii Sbornik 32(74): 545 to 632 MR 0059267
  46. C.D. Hollings & M.V. Lawson (2017) Wagner’s Theory of Generalised Heaps, Springer books ISBN   978-3-319-63620-7 MR 3729305
  47. Christopher Hollings (2014) Mathematics across the Iron Curtain: a history of the algebraic theory of semigroups, page 265, History of Mathematics 41, American Mathematical Society ISBN   978-1-4704-1493-1

Bibliography