Szpilrajn extension theorem

Last updated

In order theory, the Szpilrajn extension theorem (also called the order-extension principle), proved by Edward Szpilrajn in 1930, [1] states that every partial order is contained in a total order. Intuitively, the theorem says that any method of comparing elements that leaves some pairs incomparable can be extended in such a way that every pair becomes comparable. The theorem is one of many examples of the use of the axiom of choice in the form of Zorn's lemma to find a maximal set with certain properties.

Contents

Definitions and statement

A binary relation on a set is formally defined as a set of ordered pairs of elements of and is often abbreviated as

A relation is reflexive if holds for every element it is transitive if imply for all it is antisymmetric if imply for all and it is a connex relation if holds for all A partial order is, by definition, a reflexive, transitive and antisymmetric relation. A total order is a partial order that is connex.

A relation is contained in another relation when all ordered pairs in also appear in that is, implies for all The extension theorem states that every relation that is reflexive, transitive and antisymmetric (that is, a partial order) is contained in another relation which is reflexive, transitive, antisymmetric and connex (that is, a total order).

Proof

The theorem is proved in two steps. First, one shows that, if a partial order does not compare some two elements, it can be extended to an order with a superset of comparable pairs. A maximal partial order cannot be extended, by definition, so it follows from this step that a maximal partial order must be a total order. In the second step, Zorn's lemma is applied to find a maximal partial order that extends any given partial order.

For the first step, suppose that a given partial order does not compare and . Then the order is extended by first adding the pair to the relation, which may result in a non-transitive relation, and then restoring transitivity by adding all pairs such that This produces a relation that is still reflexive, antisymmetric and transitive and that strictly contains the original one. It follows that if the partial orders extending are themselves partially ordered by extension, then any maximal element of this extension order must be a total order.

Next it is shown that the poset of partial orders extending , ordered by extension, has a maximal element. The existence of such a maximal element is proved by applying Zorn's lemma to this poset. Zorn's lemma states that a partial order in which every chain has an upper bound has a maximal element. A chain in this poset is a set of relations in which, for every two relations, one extends the other. An upper bound for a chain can be found as the union of the relations in the chain, . This union is a relation that extends , since every element of is a partial order having as a subset. Next, it is shown that is a transitive relation. Suppose that and are in so that there exist such that and . Because is a chain, one of or must extend the other and contain both and , and by its transitivity it also contains , as does the union. Similarly, it can be shown that is antisymmetric. Thus, is an extension of , so it belongs to the poset of extensions of , and is an upper bound for .

This argument shows that Zorn's lemma may be applied to the poset of extensions of , producing a maximal element . By the first step this maximal element must be a total order, completing the proof.

Strength

Some form of the axiom of choice is necessary in proving the Szpilrajn extension theorem. The extension theorem implies the axiom of finite choice: if the union of a family of finite sets is given the empty partial order, and this is extended to a total order, the extension defines a choice from each finite set, its minimum element in the total order. Although finite choice is a weak version of the axiom of choice, it is independent of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory without choice. [2]

The Szpilrajn extension theorem together with another consequence of the axiom of choice, the principle that every total order has a cofinal well-order, can be combined to prove the full axiom of choice. With these assumptions, one can choose an element from any given set by extending its empty partial order, finding a cofinal well-order, and choosing the minimum element from that well-ordering. [3]

Other extension theorems

Arrow stated that every preorder (reflexive and transitive relation) can be extended to a total preorder (transitive and connex relation). [4] This claim was later proved by Hansson. [5] [6]

Suzumura proved that a binary relation can be extended to a total preorder if and only if it is Suzumura-consistent, which means that there is no cycle of elements such that for every pair of consecutive elements and there is some pair of consecutive elements in the cycle for which does not hold. [6]

Related Research Articles

In mathematics, a binary relation associates elements of one set, called the domain, with elements of another set, called the codomain. A binary relation over sets X and Y is a new set of ordered pairs (x, y) consisting of elements x from X and y from Y. It is a generalization of the more widely understood idea of a unary function. It encodes the common concept of relation: an element x is related to an element y, if and only if the pair (x, y) belongs to the set of ordered pairs that defines the binary relation. A binary relation is the most studied special case n = 2 of an n-ary relation over sets X1, ..., Xn, which is a subset of the Cartesian product

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Partially ordered set</span> Mathematical set with an ordering

In mathematics, especially order theory, a partial order on a set is an arrangement such that, for certain pairs of elements, one precedes the other. The word partial is used to indicate that not every pair of elements needs to be comparable; that is, there may be pairs for which neither element precedes the other. Partial orders thus generalize total orders, in which every pair is comparable.

In mathematics, a total order or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation on some set , which satisfies the following for all and in :

  1. (reflexive).
  2. If and then (transitive).
  3. If and then (antisymmetric).
  4. or .
<span class="mw-page-title-main">Ultrafilter</span> Maximal proper filter

In the mathematical field of order theory, an ultrafilter on a given partially ordered set is a certain subset of namely a maximal filter on that is, a proper filter on that cannot be enlarged to a bigger proper filter on

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Zorn's lemma</span> Mathematical proposition equivalent to the axiom of choice

Zorn's lemma, also known as the Kuratowski–Zorn lemma, is a proposition of set theory. It states that a partially ordered set containing upper bounds for every chain necessarily contains at least one maximal element.

In the mathematical discipline of set theory, forcing is a technique for proving consistency and independence results. Intuitively, forcing can be thought of as a technique to expand the set theoretical universe to a larger universe by introducing a new "generic" object .

In mathematics, a relation R on a set X is transitive if, for all elements a, b, c in X, whenever R relates a to b and b to c, then R also relates a to c. Each partial order as well as each equivalence relation needs to be transitive.

In mathematics, a subset of a given set is closed under an operation of the larger set if performing that operation on members of the subset always produces a member of that subset. For example, the natural numbers are closed under addition, but not under subtraction: 1 − 2 is not a natural number, although both 1 and 2 are.

Order theory is a branch of mathematics that investigates the intuitive notion of order using binary relations. It provides a formal framework for describing statements such as "this is less than that" or "this precedes that". This article introduces the field and provides basic definitions. A list of order-theoretic terms can be found in the order theory glossary.

This is a glossary of some terms used in various branches of mathematics that are related to the fields of order, lattice, and domain theory. Note that there is a structured list of order topics available as well. Other helpful resources might be the following overview articles:

In set theory, a branch of mathematics, a set is called transitive if either of the following equivalent conditions hold:

This article examines the implementation of mathematical concepts in set theory. The implementation of a number of basic mathematical concepts is carried out in parallel in ZFC and in NFU, the version of Quine's New Foundations shown to be consistent by R. B. Jensen in 1969.

In mathematics, Euclidean relations are a class of binary relations that formalize "Axiom 1" in Euclid's Elements: "Magnitudes which are equal to the same are equal to each other."

In order theory, a branch of mathematics, a linear extension of a partial order is a total order that is compatible with the partial order. As a classic example, the lexicographic order of totally ordered sets is a linear extension of their product order.

In mathematics, a homogeneous relation on a set X is a binary relation between X and itself, i.e. it is a subset of the Cartesian product X × X. This is commonly phrased as "a relation on X" or "a (binary) relation over X". An example of a homogeneous relation is the relation of kinship, where the relation is between people.

In constructive mathematics, pseudo-order is a name given to certain binary relations appropriate for modeling continuous orderings.

In mathematics, the Teichmüller–Tukey lemma, named after John Tukey and Oswald Teichmüller, is a lemma that states that every nonempty collection of finite character has a maximal element with respect to inclusion. Over Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, the Teichmüller–Tukey lemma is equivalent to the axiom of choice, and therefore to the well-ordering theorem, Zorn's lemma, and the Hausdorff maximal principle.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Relation (mathematics)</span> Relationship between two sets, defined by a set of ordered pairs

In mathematics, a relation on a set may, or may not, hold between two given members of the set. As an example, "is less than" is a relation on the set of natural numbers; it holds for instance between the values 1 and 3, and likewise between 3 and 4, but not between the values 3 and 1 nor between 4 and 4, that is, 3 < 1 evaluates to false, and so does 4 < 4. As another example, "is sister of" is a relation on the set of all people, it holds e.g. between Marie Curie and Bronisława Dłuska, and likewise vice versa. Set members may not be in relation "to a certain degree" – either they are in relation or they are not.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Semiorder</span> Numerical ordering with a margin of error

In order theory, a branch of mathematics, a semiorder is a type of ordering for items with numerical scores, where items with widely differing scores are compared by their scores and where scores within a given margin of error are deemed incomparable. Semiorders were introduced and applied in mathematical psychology by Duncan Luce (1956) as a model of human preference. They generalize strict weak orderings, in which items with equal scores may be tied but there is no margin of error. They are a special case of partial orders and of interval orders, and can be characterized among the partial orders by additional axioms, or by two forbidden four-item suborders.

This is a glossary of set theory.

References

  1. Szpilrajn, Edward (1930), "Sur l'extension de l'ordre partiel" (PDF), Fundamenta Mathematicae (in French), 16: 386–389, doi: 10.4064/fm-16-1-386-389
  2. Moore, Gregory H. (1982), Zermelo's Axiom of Choice: Its Origins, Development, and Influence, Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences, vol. 8, New York: Springer-Verlag, p. 222, doi:10.1007/978-1-4613-9478-5, ISBN   0-387-90670-3, MR   0679315
  3. Howard, Paul; Rubin, Jean E. (1998), "Note 121", Consequences of the Axiom of Choice, Mathematical Surveys and Monographs, vol. 59, Providence, Rhode Island: American Mathematical Society, p. 299, doi:10.1090/surv/059, ISBN   0-8218-0977-6, MR   1637107
  4. Arrow, Kenneth J. (2012), "IV.3: Quasi-orderings and compatible weak orderings", Social Choice and Individual Values (3rd ed.), Yale University Press, p. 64, ISBN   978-0-300-18698-7
  5. Hansson, Bengt (1968), "Choice structures and preference relations", Synthese, 18 (4): 443–458, doi:10.1007/BF00484979, JSTOR   20114617 ; see Lemma 3
  6. 1 2 Cato, Susumu (August 2011), "Szpilrajn, Arrow and Suzumura: concise proofs of extension theorems and an extension", Metroeconomica, 63 (2): 235–249, doi:10.1111/j.1467-999x.2011.04130.x