Tolerance relation

Last updated

In universal algebra and lattice theory, a tolerance relation on an algebraic structure is a reflexive symmetric relation that is compatible with all operations of the structure. Thus a tolerance is like a congruence, except that the assumption of transitivity is dropped. [1] On a set, an algebraic structure with empty family of operations, tolerance relations are simply reflexive symmetric relations. A set that possesses a tolerance relation can be described as a tolerance space. [2] Tolerance relations provide a convenient general tool for studying indiscernibility/indistinguishability phenomena. The importance of those for mathematics had been first recognized by Poincaré. [3]

Contents

Definitions

A tolerance relation on an algebraic structure is usually defined to be a reflexive symmetric relation on that is compatible with every operation in . A tolerance relation can also be seen as a cover of that satisfies certain conditions. The two definitions are equivalent, since for a fixed algebraic structure, the tolerance relations in the two definitions are in one-to-one correspondence. The tolerance relations on an algebraic structure form an algebraic lattice under inclusion. Since every congruence relation is a tolerance relation, the congruence lattice is a subset of the tolerance lattice , but is not necessarily a sublattice of . [4]

As binary relations

A tolerance relation on an algebraic structure is a binary relation on that satisfies the following conditions.

A congruence relation is a tolerance relation that is also transitive.

As covers

A tolerance relation on an algebraic structure is a cover of that satisfies the following three conditions. [5] :307,Theorem 3

Every partition of satisfies the first two conditions, but not conversely. A congruence relation is a tolerance relation that also forms a set partition.

Equivalence of the two definitions

Let be a tolerance binary relation on an algebraic structure . Let be the family of maximal subsets such that for every . Using graph theoretical terms, is the set of all maximal cliques of the graph . If is a congruence relation, is just the quotient set of equivalence classes. Then is a cover of and satisfies all the three conditions in the cover definition. (The last condition is shown using Zorn's lemma.) Conversely, let be a cover of and suppose that forms a tolerance on . Consider a binary relation on for which if and only if for some . Then is a tolerance on as a binary relation. The map is a one-to-one correspondence between the tolerances as binary relations and as covers whose inverse is . Therefore, the two definitions are equivalent. A tolerance is transitive as a binary relation if and only if it is a partition as a cover. Thus the two characterizations of congruence relations also agree.

Quotient algebras over tolerance relations

Let be an algebraic structure and let be a tolerance relation on . Suppose that, for each -ary operation and , there is a unique such that

Then this provides a natural definition of the quotient algebra

of over . In the case of congruence relations, the uniqueness condition always holds true and the quotient algebra defined here coincides with the usual one.

A main difference from congruence relations is that for a tolerance relation the uniqueness condition may fail, and even if it does not, the quotient algebra may not inherit the identities defining the variety that belongs to, so that the quotient algebra may fail to be a member of the variety again. Therefore, for a variety of algebraic structures, we may consider the following two conditions. [4]

Every strongly tolerance factorable variety is tolerance factorable, but not vice versa.

Examples

Sets

A set is an algebraic structure with no operations at all. In this case, tolerance relations are simply reflexive symmetric relations and it is trivial that the variety of sets is strongly tolerance factorable.

Groups

On a group, every tolerance relation is a congruence relation. In particular, this is true for all algebraic structures that are groups when some of their operations are forgot, e.g. rings, vector spaces, modules, Boolean algebras, etc. [6] :261–262 Therefore, the varieties of groups, rings, vector spaces, modules and Boolean algebras are also strongly tolerance factorable trivially.

Lattices

For a tolerance relation on a lattice , every set in is a convex sublattice of . Thus, for all , we have

In particular, the following results hold.

The variety of lattices is strongly tolerance factorable. That is, given any lattice and any tolerance relation on , for each there exist unique such that

and the quotient algebra

is a lattice again. [7] [8] [9] :44,Theorem 22

In particular, we can form quotient lattices of distributive lattices and modular lattices over tolerance relations. However, unlike in the case of congruence relations, the quotient lattices need not be distributive or modular again. In other words, the varieties of distributive lattices and modular lattices are tolerance factorable, but not strongly tolerance factorable. [7] :40 [4] Actually, every subvariety of the variety of lattices is tolerance factorable, and the only strongly tolerance factorable subvariety other than itself is the trivial subvariety (consisting of one-element lattices). [7] :40 This is because every lattice is isomorphic to a sublattice of the quotient lattice over a tolerance relation of a sublattice of a direct product of two-element lattices. [7] :40,Theorem 3

See also

References

  1. Kearnes, Keith; Kiss, Emil W. (2013). The Shape of Congruence Lattices. American Mathematical Soc. p. 20. ISBN   978-0-8218-8323-5.
  2. Sossinsky, Alexey (1986-02-01). "Tolerance space theory and some applications". Acta Applicandae Mathematicae . 5 (2): 137–167. doi:10.1007/BF00046585. S2CID   119731847.
  3. Poincare, H. (1905). Science and Hypothesis (with a preface by J.Larmor ed.). New York: 3 East 14th Street: The Walter Scott Publishing Co., Ltd. pp.  22-23.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location (link)
  4. 1 2 3 Chajda, Ivan; Radeleczki, Sándor (2014). "Notes on tolerance factorable classes of algebras". Acta Scientiarum Mathematicarum. 80 (3–4): 389–397. doi:10.14232/actasm-012-861-x. ISSN   0001-6969. MR   3307031. S2CID   85560830. Zbl   1321.08002.
  5. Chajda, Ivan; Niederle, Josef; Zelinka, Bohdan (1976). "On existence conditions for compatible tolerances". Czechoslovak Mathematical Journal. 26 (101): 304–311. doi: 10.21136/CMJ.1976.101403 . ISSN   0011-4642. MR   0401561. Zbl   0333.08006. EuDML   12943 .
  6. Schein, Boris M. (1987). "Semigroups of tolerance relations". Discrete Mathematics. 64: 253–262. doi: 10.1016/0012-365X(87)90194-4 . ISSN   0012-365X. MR   0887364. Zbl   0615.20045.
  7. 1 2 3 4 Czédli, Gábor (1982). "Factor lattices by tolerances". Acta Scientiarum Mathematicarum. 44: 35–42. ISSN   0001-6969. MR   0660510. Zbl   0484.06010.
  8. Grätzer, George; Wenzel, G. H. (1990). "Notes on tolerance relations of lattices". Acta Scientiarum Mathematicarum. 54 (3–4): 229–240. ISSN   0001-6969. MR   1096802. Zbl   0727.06011.
  9. Grätzer, George (2011). Lattice Theory: Foundation. Basel: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-0348-0018-1. ISBN   978-3-0348-0017-4. LCCN   2011921250. MR   2768581. Zbl   1233.06001.

Further reading