In mathematics, the Hausdorff maximal principle is an alternate and earlier formulation of Zorn's lemma proved by Felix Hausdorff in 1914 (Moore 1982:168). It states that in any partially ordered set, every totally ordered subset is contained in a maximal totally ordered subset, where "maximal" is with respect to set inclusion.
In a partially ordered set, a totally ordered subset is also called a chain. Thus, the maximal principle says every chain in the set extends to a maximal chain.
The Hausdorff maximal principle is one of many statements equivalent to the axiom of choice over ZF (Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice). The principle is also called the Hausdorff maximality theorem or the Kuratowski lemma (Kelley 1955:33).
The Hausdorff maximal principle states that, in any partially ordered set , every chain (i.e., a totally ordered subset) is contained in a maximal chain (i.e., a chain that is not contained in a strictly larger chain in ). In general, there may be several maximal chains containing a given chain.
An equivalent form of the Hausdorff maximal principle is that in every partially ordered set, there exists a maximal chain. (Note if the set is empty, the empty subset is a maximal chain.)
This form follows from the original form since the empty set is a chain. Conversely, to deduce the original form from this form, consider the set of all chains in containing a given chain in . Then is partially ordered by set inclusion. Thus, by the maximal principle in the above form, contains a maximal chain . Let be the union of , which is a chain in since a union of a totally ordered set of chains is a chain. Since contains , it is an element of . Also, since any chain containing is contained in as is a union, is in fact a maximal element of ; i.e., a maximal chain in .
The proof that the Hausdorff maximal principle is equivalent to Zorn's lemma is somehow similar to this proof. Indeed, first assume Zorn's lemma. Since a union of a totally ordered set of chains is a chain, the hypothesis of Zorn's lemma (every chain has an upper bound) is satisfied for and thus contains a maximal element or a maximal chain in .
Conversely, if the maximal principle holds, then contains a maximal chain . By the hypothesis of Zorn's lemma, has an upper bound in . If , then is a chain containing and so by maximality, ; i.e., and so .
If A is any collection of sets, the relation "is a proper subset of" is a strict partial order on A. Suppose that A is the collection of all circular regions (interiors of circles) in the plane. One maximal totally ordered sub-collection of A consists of all circular regions with centers at the origin. Another maximal totally ordered sub-collection consists of all circular regions bounded by circles tangent from the right to the y-axis at the origin.
If (x0, y0) and (x1, y1) are two points of the plane , define (x0, y0) < (x1, y1) if y0 = y1 and x0 < x1. This is a partial ordering of under which two points are comparable only if they lie on the same horizontal line. The maximal totally ordered sets are horizontal lines in .
By the Hausdorff maximal principle, we can show every Hilbert space contains a maximal orthonormal subset as follows. [1] (This fact can be stated as saying that as Hilbert spaces.)
Let be the set of all orthonormal subsets of the given Hilbert space , which is partially ordered by set inclusion. It is nonempty as it contains the empty set and thus by the maximal principle, it contains a maximal chain . Let be the union of . We shall show it is a maximal orthonormal subset. First, if are in , then either or . That is, any given two distinct elements in are contained in some in and so they are orthogonal to each other (and of course, is a subset of the unit sphere in ). Second, if for some in , then cannot be in and so is a chain strictly larger than , a contradiction.
For the purpose of comparison, here is a proof of the same fact by Zorn's lemma. As above, let be the set of all orthonormal subsets of . If is a chain in , then the union of is also orthonormal by the same argument as above and so is an upper bound of . Thus, by Zorn's lemma, contains a maximal element . (So, the difference is that the maximal principle gives a maximal chain while Zorn's lemma gives a maximal element directly.)
The idea of the proof is essentially due to Zermelo and is to prove the following weak form of Zorn's lemma, from the axiom of choice. [2] [3]
(Zorn's lemma itself also follows from this weak form.) The maximal principle follows from the above since the set of all chains in satisfies the above conditions.
By the axiom of choice, we have a function such that for the power set of .
For each , let be the set of all such that is in . If , then let . Otherwise, let
Note is a maximal element if and only if . Thus, we are done if we can find a such that .
Fix a in . We call a subset a tower (over ) if
There exists at least one tower; indeed, the set of all sets in containing is a tower. Let be the intersection of all towers, which is again a tower.
Now, we shall show is totally ordered. We say a set is comparable in if for each in , either or . Let be the set of all sets in that are comparable in . We claim is a tower. The conditions 1. and 2. are straightforward to check. For 3., let in be given and then let be the set of all in such that either or .
We claim is a tower. The conditions 1. and 2. are again straightforward to check. For 3., let be in . If , then since is comparable in , either or . In the first case, is in . In the second case, we have , which implies either or . (This is the moment we needed to collapse a set to an element by the axiom of choice to define .) Either way, we have is in . Similarly, if , we see is in . Hence, is a tower. Now, since and is the intersection of all towers, , which implies is comparable in ; i.e., is in . This completes the proof of the claim that is a tower.
Finally, since is a tower contained in , we have , which means is totally ordered.
Let be the union of . By 2., is in and then by 3., is in . Since is the union of , and thus .
Here we are going to use the following application of the Bourbaki–Witt theorem to prove the Hausdorff maximal principle:
Every partially ordered set , such that every chain has a least upper bound in , has maximal element. A partially ordered set satisfiying this property is also called chain complete.
Now to the proof: First, let be the set of all chains in . We want to show that has a maximal element. By inclusion of sets is a partially ordered set. It is left to show, that a chain in has a least upper bound. is clearly an upper bound for , since it forms again a chain. It is the least upper bound, because each upper bound for contains .
By the statement above, we conclude that has a maximal element. That is exactly the maximal chain we were looking for.
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of sets, each containing at least one element, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from each set, even if the collection is infinite. Formally, it states that for every indexed family of nonempty sets, there exists an indexed set such that for every . The axiom of choice was formulated in 1904 by Ernst Zermelo in order to formalize his proof of the well-ordering theorem.
The Hahn–Banach theorem is a central tool in functional analysis. It allows the extension of bounded linear functionals defined on a vector subspace of some vector space to the whole space, and it also shows that there are "enough" continuous linear functionals defined on every normed vector space to make the study of the dual space "interesting". Another version of the Hahn–Banach theorem is known as the Hahn–Banach separation theorem or the hyperplane separation theorem, and has numerous uses in convex geometry.
In algebra, a prime ideal is a subset of a ring that shares many important properties of a prime number in the ring of integers. The prime ideals for the integers are the sets that contain all the multiples of a given prime number, together with the zero ideal.
In the mathematical field of order theory, an ultrafilter on a given partially ordered set is a certain subset of namely a maximal filter on that is, a proper filter on that cannot be enlarged to a bigger proper filter on
In mathematics, the well-ordering theorem, also known as Zermelo's theorem, states that every set can be well-ordered. A set X is well-ordered by a strict total order if every non-empty subset of X has a least element under the ordering. The well-ordering theorem together with Zorn's lemma are the most important mathematical statements that are equivalent to the axiom of choice. Ernst Zermelo introduced the axiom of choice as an "unobjectionable logical principle" to prove the well-ordering theorem. One can conclude from the well-ordering theorem that every set is susceptible to transfinite induction, which is considered by mathematicians to be a powerful technique. One famous consequence of the theorem is the Banach–Tarski paradox.
Zorn's lemma, also known as the Kuratowski–Zorn lemma, is a proposition of set theory. It states that a partially ordered set containing upper bounds for every chain necessarily contains at least one maximal element.
In mathematics, a transcendental extension is a field extension such that there exists an element in the field that is transcendental over the field ; that is, an element that is not a root of any univariate polynomial with coefficients in . In other words, a transcendental extension is a field extension that is not algebraic. For example, and are both transcendental extensions of
In mathematics, especially in order theory, a maximal element of a subset of some preordered set is an element of that is not smaller than any other element in . A minimal element of a subset of some preordered set is defined dually as an element of that is not greater than any other element in .
In mathematics, the Gelfand representation in functional analysis is either of two things:
In abstract algebra, a valuation ring is an integral domain D such that for every non-zero element x of its field of fractions F, at least one of x or x−1 belongs to D.
In mathematics, the Bourbaki–Witt theorem in order theory, named after Nicolas Bourbaki and Ernst Witt, is a basic fixed-point theorem for partially ordered sets. It states that if X is a non-empty chain complete poset, and such that for all then f has a fixed point. Such a function f is called inflationary or progressive.
In mathematics, a subset of a preordered set is said to be cofinal or frequent in if for every it is possible to find an element in that is "larger than ".
In mathematics, a family of sets is of finite character if for each , belongs to if and only if every finite subset of belongs to . That is,
In mathematics, the Vitali covering lemma is a combinatorial and geometric result commonly used in measure theory of Euclidean spaces. This lemma is an intermediate step, of independent interest, in the proof of the Vitali covering theorem. The covering theorem is credited to the Italian mathematician Giuseppe Vitali. The theorem states that it is possible to cover, up to a Lebesgue-negligible set, a given subset E of Rd by a disjoint family extracted from a Vitali covering of E.
In mathematics, an approximately finite-dimensional (AF) C*-algebra is a C*-algebra that is the inductive limit of a sequence of finite-dimensional C*-algebras. Approximate finite-dimensionality was first defined and described combinatorially by Ola Bratteli. Later, George A. Elliott gave a complete classification of AF algebras using the K0 functor whose range consists of ordered abelian groups with sufficiently nice order structure.
In mathematics, the Teichmüller–Tukey lemma, named after John Tukey and Oswald Teichmüller, is a lemma that states that every nonempty collection of finite character has a maximal element with respect to inclusion. Over Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, the Teichmüller–Tukey lemma is equivalent to the axiom of choice, and therefore to the well-ordering theorem, Zorn's lemma, and the Hausdorff maximal principle.
In order theory, the Szpilrajn extension theorem, proved by Edward Szpilrajn in 1930, states that every partial order is contained in a total order. Intuitively, the theorem says that any method of comparing elements that leaves some pairs incomparable can be extended in such a way that every pair becomes comparable. The theorem is one of many examples of the use of the axiom of choice in the form of Zorn's lemma to find a maximal set with certain properties.
In algebra, Zariski's lemma, proved by Oscar Zariski, states that, if a field K is finitely generated as an associative algebra over another field k, then K is a finite field extension of k.
In abstract algebra, Kaplansky's theorem on projective modules, first proven by Irving Kaplansky, states that a projective module over a local ring is free; where a not-necessarily-commutative ring is called local if for each element x, either x or 1 − x is a unit element. The theorem can also be formulated so to characterize a local ring.
In the mathematical field of set theory, an ultrafilter on a set is a maximal filter on the set In other words, it is a collection of subsets of that satisfies the definition of a filter on and that is maximal with respect to inclusion, in the sense that there does not exist a strictly larger collection of subsets of that is also a filter. Equivalently, an ultrafilter on the set can also be characterized as a filter on with the property that for every subset of either or its complement belongs to the ultrafilter.