List of logic symbols

Last updated

In logic, a set of symbols is commonly used to express logical representation. The following table lists many common symbols, together with their name, how they should be read out loud, and the related field of mathematics. Additionally, the subsequent columns contains an informal explanation, a short example, the Unicode location, the name for use in HTML documents, [1] and the LaTeX symbol.

Contents

Basic logic symbols

SymbolUnicode
value
(hexadecimal)
HTML
codes
LaTeX
symbol
Logic NameRead asCategoryExplanationExamples


U+21D2

U+2192

U+2283
⇒
→
⊃

⇒
→
⊃

\Rightarrow
\implies
\to or \rightarrow
\supset
material conditional (material implication) implies,
if P then Q,
it is not the case that P and not Q
propositional logic, Boolean algebra, Heyting algebra is false when A is true and B is false but true otherwise.

may mean the same as
(the symbol may also indicate the domain and codomain of a function; see table of mathematical symbols).

may mean the same as (the symbol may also mean superset).
is true, but is in general false
(since x could be −2).


U+21D4

U+2194

U+2261
⇔
↔
≡

⇔
↔
≡

\Leftrightarrow
\iff
\leftrightarrow
\equiv
material biconditional (material equivalence) if and only if, iff, xnor propositional logic, Boolean algebra is true only if both A and B are false, or both A and B are true. Whether a symbol means a material biconditional or a logical equivalence, depends on the author’s style.
¬
~
!
U+00AC

U+007E

U+0021
¬
˜
!

¬
˜
!

\lnot or \neg

\sim


negation not propositional logic, Boolean algebra The statement is true if and only if A is false.

A slash placed through another operator is the same as placed in front.


·
&
U+2227

U+00B7

U+0026
∧
·
&

∧
·
&

\wedge or \land
\cdot

\& [2]
logical conjunction and propositional logic, Boolean algebra The statement A  B is true if A and B are both true; otherwise, it is false.
n < 4   n >2   n = 3 when n is a natural number.

+
U+2228

U+002B

U+2225
&#8744;
&#43;
&#8741;

&or;
&plus;
&parallel;

\lor or \vee



\parallel
logical (inclusive) disjunction or propositional logic, Boolean algebra The statement A  B is true if A or B (or both) are true; if both are false, the statement is false.
n ≥ 4   n ≤ 2  n ≠ 3 when n is a natural number.




U+2295

U+22BB

U+21AE

U+2262
&#8853;
&#8891;
&#8622;
&#8802;

&oplus;
&veebar;

&nequiv;

\oplus

\veebar



\not\equiv
exclusive disjunction xor,
either ... or ... (but not both)
propositional logic, Boolean algebra The statement is true when either A or B, but not both, are true. This is equivalent to
¬(A ↔ B), hence the symbols and .
is always true and is always false (if vacuous truth is excluded).


T
1


U+22A4





&#8868;


&top;

\top



true (tautology) top, truth, tautology, verum, full clause propositional logic, Boolean algebra, first-order logic denotes a proposition that is always true.
The proposition is always true since at least one of the two is unconditionally true.


F
0


U+22A5





&#8869;

&perp;



\bot



false (contradiction) bottom, falsity, contradiction, falsum, empty clause propositional logic, Boolean algebra, first-order logic denotes a proposition that is always false.
The symbol ⊥ may also refer to perpendicular  lines.
The proposition is always false since at least one of the two is unconditionally false.

()
U+2200


&#8704;

&forall;


\forall


universal quantification given any, for all, for every, for each, for any first-order logic   or
  says “given any , has property .”
U+2203&#8707;

&exist;

\exists existential quantification there exists, for some first-order logic   says “there exists an (at least one) such that has property .”
n is even.
∃!
U+2203 U+0021&#8707; &#33;

&exist;!

\exists ! uniqueness quantification there exists exactly one first-order logic (abbreviation) says “there exists exactly one such that has property .” Only and are part of formal logic.
is an abbreviation for
( )
U+0028 U+0029&#40; &#41;

&lpar;
&rpar;

( ) precedence grouping parentheses; bracketsalmost all logic syntaxes, as well as metalanguagePerform the operations inside the parentheses first.
(8 ÷ 4) ÷ 2 = 2 ÷ 2 = 1, but 8 ÷ (4 ÷ 2) = 8 ÷ 2 = 4.
U+1D53B&#120123;

&Dopf;

\mathbb{D} domain of discourse domain of discourse metalanguage (first-order logic semantics)
U+22A2&#8866;

&vdash;

\vdash turnstile syntactically entails (proves) metalanguage (metalogic) says “ is
a theorem of ”.
In other words,
proves via a deductive system.

(eg. by using natural deduction)
U+22A8&#8872;

&vDash;

\vDash, \models double turnstile semantically entails metalanguage (metalogic) says
“in every model,
it is not the case that is true and is false”.

(eg. by using truth tables)


U+2261

U+27DA

U+21D4
&#8801;


&#8660; &equiv; — &hArr;

\equiv



\Leftrightarrow
logical equivalence is logically equivalent to metalanguage (metalogic) It’s when and . Whether a symbol means a material biconditional or a logical equivalence, depends on the author’s style.
U+22AC⊬\nvdashdoes not syntactically entail (does not prove) metalanguage (metalogic) says “ is
not a theorem of ”.
In other words,
is not derivable from via a deductive system.
U+22AD⊭\nvDashdoes not semantically entail metalanguage (metalogic) says “ does not guarantee the truth of  ”.
In other words,
does not make true.
U+25A1\Box necessity (in a model) box; it is necessary that modal logic modal operator for “it is necessary that”
in alethic logic, “it is provable that”
in provability logic, “it is obligatory that”
in deontic logic, “it is believed that”
in doxastic logic.
says “it is necessary that everything has property
U+25C7\Diamond possibility (in a model) diamond;
it is possible that
modal logic modal operator for “it is possible that”, (in most modal logics it is defined as “¬□¬”, “it is not necessarily not”).
says “it is possible that something has property
U+2234∴\therefore therefore therefore metalanguage abbreviation for “therefore”.
U+2235∵\because because because metalanguage abbreviation for “because”.


U+2254

U+225C

U+225D
&#8788;

&coloneq;






:=

\triangleq


\stackrel{

\scriptscriptstyle \mathrm{def}}{=}

definition is defined as metalanguage means "from now on, is defined to be another name for ." This is a statement in the metalanguage, not the object language. The notation may occasionally be seen in physics, meaning the same as .

Advanced or rarely used logical symbols

The following symbols are either advanced and context-sensitive or very rarely used:

SymbolUnicode
value
(hexadecimal)
HTML
value
(decimal)
HTML
entity
(named)
LaTeX
symbol
Logic NameRead asCategoryExplanation
U+297D\strictifright fish tailSometimes used for “relation”, also used for denoting various ad hoc relations (for example, for denoting “witnessing” in the context of Rosser's trick). The fish hook is also used as strict implication by C.I.Lewis .
̅
U+0305 combining overline Used format for denoting Gödel numbers. Using HTML style “4̅” is an abbreviation for the standard numeral “SSSS0”.

It may also denote a negation (used primarily in electronics).


U+231C
U+231D
\ulcorner

\urcorner

top left corner
top right corner
Corner quotes, also called “Quine quotes”; for quasi-quotation, i.e. quoting specific context of unspecified (“variable”) expressions; [3] also used for denoting Gödel number; [4] for example “⌜G⌝” denotes the Gödel number of G. (Typographical note: although the quotes appears as a “pair” in unicode (231C and 231D), they are not symmetrical in some fonts. In some fonts (for example Arial) they are only symmetrical in certain sizes. Alternatively the quotes can be rendered as ⌈ and ⌉ (U+2308 and U+2309) or by using a negation symbol and a reversed negation symbol ⌐ ¬ in superscript mode.)
U+2204\nexiststhere does not existStrike out existential quantifier. “¬∃” is recommended instead. [ by whom? ]

|
U+2191
U+007C
upwards arrow
vertical line
Sheffer stroke,
the sign for the NAND operator (negation of conjunction).
U+2193downwards arrow Peirce Arrow,
a sign for the NOR operator (negation of disjunction).
U+22BCNANDA new symbol made specifically for the NAND operator.
U+22BDNORA new symbol made specifically for the NOR operator.
U+2299\odotcircled dot operatorA sign for the XNOR operator (material biconditional and XNOR are the same operation).
U+27DBleft and right tack“Proves and is proved by”.
U+22A7models“Is a model of” or “is a valuation satisfying”.
U+22A9forcesOne of this symbol’s uses is to mean “truthmakes” in the truthmaker theory of truth. It is also used to mean “forces” in the set theory method of forcing.
U+27E1white concave-sided diamondnevermodal operator
U+27E2white concave-sided diamond with leftwards tickwas nevermodal operator
U+27E3white concave-sided diamond with rightwards tickwill never bemodal operator
U+25A4white square with leftwards tickwas alwaysmodal operator
U+25A5white square with rightwards tickwill always bemodal operator
U+22C6star operatorMay sometimes be used for ad-hoc operators.
U+2310reversed not sign
U+2A07two logical AND operator

See also

Related Research Articles

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Logical disjunction</span> Logical connective OR

In logic, disjunction, also known as logical disjunction or logical or or logical addition or inclusive disjunction, is a logical connective typically notated as and read aloud as "or". For instance, the English language sentence "it is sunny or it is warm" can be represented in logic using the disjunctive formula , assuming that abbreviates "it is sunny" and abbreviates "it is warm".

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Empty set</span> Mathematical set containing no elements

In mathematics, the empty set or void set is the unique set having no elements; its size or cardinality is zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exists by including an axiom of empty set, while in other theories, its existence can be deduced. Many possible properties of sets are vacuously true for the empty set.

In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" is paraphrased by the biconditional, a logical connective between statements. The biconditional is true in two cases, where either both statements are true or both are false. The connective is biconditional, and can be likened to the standard material conditional combined with its reverse ("if"); hence the name. The result is that the truth of either one of the connected statements requires the truth of the other, though it is controversial whether the connective thus defined is properly rendered by the English "if and only if"—with its pre-existing meaning. For example, P if and only if Q means that P is true whenever Q is true, and the only case in which P is true is if Q is also true, whereas in the case of P if Q, there could be other scenarios where P is true and Q is false.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Logical conjunction</span> Logical connective AND

In logic, mathematics and linguistics, and is the truth-functional operator of conjunction or logical conjunction. The logical connective of this operator is typically represented as or or (prefix) or or in which is the most modern and widely used.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Logical connective</span> Symbol connecting sentential formulas in logic

In logic, a logical connective is a logical constant. Connectives can be used to connect logical formulas. For instance in the syntax of propositional logic, the binary connective can be used to join the two atomic formulas and , rendering the complex formula .

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Sheffer stroke</span> Logical operation

In Boolean functions and propositional calculus, the Sheffer stroke denotes a logical operation that is equivalent to the negation of the conjunction operation, expressed in ordinary language as "not both". It is also called non-conjunction, or alternative denial, or NAND. In digital electronics, it corresponds to the NAND gate. It is named after Henry Maurice Sheffer and written as or as or as or as in Polish notation by Łukasiewicz.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Blackboard bold</span> Typeface style

Blackboard bold is a style of writing bold symbols on a blackboard by doubling certain strokes, commonly used in mathematical lectures, and the derived style of typeface used in printed mathematical texts. The style is most commonly used to represent the number sets , (integers), , , and .

In typography, a bullet or bullet point, , is a typographical symbol or glyph used to introduce items in a list. For example:
 Item 1
 Item 2
 Item 3

A mathematical symbol is a figure or a combination of figures that is used to represent a mathematical object, an action on mathematical objects, a relation between mathematical objects, or for structuring the other symbols that occur in a formula. As formulas are entirely constituted with symbols of various types, many symbols are needed for expressing all mathematics.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Exclusive or</span> True when either but not both inputs are true

Exclusive or, exclusive disjunction, exclusive alternation, logical non-equivalence, or logical inequality is a logical operator whose negation is the logical biconditional. With two inputs, XOR is true if and only if the inputs differ. With multiple inputs, XOR is true if and only if the number of true inputs is odd.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Logical NOR</span> Binary operation that is true if and only if both operands are false

In Boolean logic, logical NOR, non-disjunction, or joint denial is a truth-functional operator which produces a result that is the negation of logical or. That is, a sentence of the form (p NOR q) is true precisely when neither p nor q is true—i.e. when both p and q are false. It is logically equivalent to and , where the symbol signifies logical negation, signifies OR, and signifies AND.

The equals sign or equal sign, also known as the equality sign, is the mathematical symbol =, which is used to indicate equality in some well-defined sense. In an equation, it is placed between two expressions that have the same value, or for which one studies the conditions under which they have the same value.

In logic, a truth function is a function that accepts truth values as input and produces a unique truth value as output. In other words: the input and output of a truth function are all truth values; a truth function will always output exactly one truth value, and inputting the same truth value(s) will always output the same truth value. The typical example is in propositional logic, wherein a compound statement is constructed using individual statements connected by logical connectives; if the truth value of the compound statement is entirely determined by the truth value(s) of the constituent statement(s), the compound statement is called a truth function, and any logical connectives used are said to be truth functional.

The vertical bar, |, is a glyph with various uses in mathematics, computing, and typography. It has many names, often related to particular meanings: Sheffer stroke, pipe, bar, or, vbar, and others.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Józef Maria Bocheński</span> Philosopher

Józef Maria Bocheński or Innocentius Bochenski was a Polish Dominican, logician and philosopher.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Mathematical operators and symbols in Unicode</span>

The Unicode Standard encodes almost all standard characters used in mathematics. Unicode Technical Report #25 provides comprehensive information about the character repertoire, their properties, and guidelines for implementation. Mathematical operators and symbols are in multiple Unicode blocks. Some of these blocks are dedicated to, or primarily contain, mathematical characters while others are a mix of mathematical and non-mathematical characters. This article covers all Unicode characters with a derived property of "Math".

In mathematics, the radical symbol, radical sign, root symbol, radix, or surd is a symbol for the square root or higher-order root of a number. The square root of a number x is written as

The up tack or falsum is a constant symbol used to represent:

A truth table is a mathematical table used in logic—specifically in connection with Boolean algebra, Boolean functions, and propositional calculus—which sets out the functional values of logical expressions on each of their functional arguments, that is, for each combination of values taken by their logical variables. In particular, truth tables can be used to show whether a propositional expression is true for all legitimate input values, that is, logically valid.

References

  1. "Named character references". HTML 5.1 Nightly. W3C. Retrieved 9 September 2015.
  2. Although this character is available in LaTeX, the MediaWiki TeX system does not support it.
  3. Quine, W.V. (1981): Mathematical Logic, §6
  4. Hintikka, Jaakko (1998), The Principles of Mathematics Revisited, Cambridge University Press, p. 113, ISBN   9780521624985 .

Further reading