Preference

Last updated

In psychology, economics and philosophy, preference is a technical term usually used in relation to choosing between alternatives. For example, someone prefers A over B if they would rather choose A than B. Preferences are central to decision theory because of this relation to behavior. Some methods such as Ordinal Priority Approach use preference relation for decision-making. As connative states, they are closely related to desires. The difference between the two is that desires are directed at one object while preferences concern a comparison between two alternatives, of which one is preferred to the other.

Contents

In insolvency, the term is used to determine which outstanding obligation the insolvent party has to settle first.

Psychology

In psychology, preferences refer to an individual's attitude towards a set of objects, typically reflected in an explicit decision-making process (Lichtenstein & Slovic, 2006). The term is also used to mean evaluative judgment in the sense of liking or disliking an object (e.g., Scherer, 2005) which is the most typical definition employed in psychology. However, it does not mean that a preference is necessarily stable over time. Preference can be notably modified by decision-making processes, such as choices (Brehm, 1956; Sharot, De Martino, & Dolan, 2009), even unconsciously (see Coppin, Delplanque, Cayeux, Porcherot, & Sander, 2010). Consequently, preference can be affected by a person's surroundings and upbringing in terms of geographical location, cultural background, religious beliefs, and education. These factors are found to affect preference as repeated exposure to a certain idea or concept correlates with a positive preference. [1]

Economics

In economics and other social sciences, preference refers to the set of assumptions related to ordering some alternatives, based on the degree of happiness, satisfaction, gratification, morality, enjoyment, or utility they provide. The concept of preferences is used in post-World War II neoclassical economics to provide observable evidence in relation to people's actions. [2] These actions can be described by Rational Choice Theory, where individuals make decisions based on rational preferences which are aligned with their self-interests in order to achieve an optimal outcome. [3]

Consumer preference, or consumers' preference for particular brands over identical products and services, is an important notion in the psychological influence of consumption. Consumer preferences have three properties: completeness, transitivity and non-satiation. For a preference to be rational, it must satisfy the axioms of transitivity and Completeness (statistics). The first axiom of transitivity refers to consistency between preferences, such that if x is preferred to y and y is preferred to z, then x has to be preferred to z. [4] [5] The second axiom of completeness describes that a relationship must exist between two options, such that x must be preferred to y or y must be preferred to x, or is indifferent between them. [4] [5] For example, if I prefer sugar to honey and honey to sweetener then I must prefer sugar to sweetener to satisfy transitivity and I must have a preference between the items to satisfy completeness. Under the axiom of completeness, an individual cannot lack a preference between any two options. [6]

An example of transitive and complete preferences. 279124338 2213 4894807220743277869 n.jpg
An example of transitive and complete preferences.

If preferences are both transitive and complete, the relationship between preference can be described by a utility function. [7] This is because the axioms allow for preferences to be ordered into one equivalent ordering with no preference cycles. [8] Maximising utility does not imply maximise happiness, rather it is an optimisation of the available options based on an individual's preferences. [9] The so-called Expected Utility Theory (EUT), which was introduced by John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern in 1944, explains that so long as an agent's preferences over risky options follow a set of axioms, then he is maximizing the expected value of a utility function. [10] In utility theory, preference relates to decision makers' attitudes towards rewards and hazards. The specific varieties are classified into three categories: 1) risk-averse, that is, equal gains and losses, with investors participating when the loss probability is less than 50%; 2) the risk-taking kind, which is the polar opposite of type 1); 3) Relatively risk-neutral, in the sense that the introduction of risk has no clear association with the decision maker's choice. [11]

The mathematical foundations of most common types of preferences — that are representable by quadratic or additive functions — laid down by Gérard Debreu [12] [13] enabled Andranik Tangian to develop methods for their elicitation. In particular, additive and quadratic preference functions in variables can be constructed from interviews, where questions are aimed at tracing totally 2D-indifference curves in coordinate planes without referring to cardinal utility estimates. [14] [15]

Empirical evidence has shown that the usage of rational preferences (and Rational Choice Theory) does not always accurately predict human behaviour because it makes unrealistic assumptions. [16] [17] [18] In response to this, neoclassical economists argue that it provides a normative model for people to adjust and optimise their actions. [19] Behavioural economics describes an alternative approach to predicting human behaviour by using psychological theory which explores deviations from rational preferences and the standard economic model. [20] It also recognises that rational preferences and choices are limited by heuristics and biases. Heuristics are rules of thumb such as elimination by aspects which are used to make decisions rather than maximising the utility function. [21] Economic biases such as reference points and loss aversion also violate the assumption of rational preferences by causing individuals to act irrationally. [22]

Individual preferences can be represented as an indifference curve given the underlying assumptions. Indifference curves graphically depict all product combinations that yield the same amount of usefulness. Indifference curves allow us to graphically define and rank all possible combinations of two commodities. [23]

The graph's three main points are:

1. If more is better, the indifference curve dips downward.

2. Greater transitivity indicates that the indifference curves do not overlap.

3. A propensity for diversity causes indifference curves to curve inward.

Risk preference

Risk preference is defined as how much risk a person is prepared to accept based on the expected utility or pleasure of the outcome.

Risk tolerance is a critical component of personal financial planning, that is, risk preference.

In psychology, risk preference is occasionally characterised as the proclivity to engage in a behaviour or activity that is advantageous but may involve some potential loss, such as substance abuse or criminal action that may bring significant bodily and mental harm to the individual. [24]

In economics, risk preference refers to a proclivity to engage in behaviours or activities that entail greater variance returns, regardless of whether they be gains or losses, and are frequently associated with monetary rewards involving lotteries. [25]

There are two different traditions of measuring preference for risk, the revealed and stated preference traditions, which Coexist in psychology, and to some extent in economics as well. [26] [27] [28]

Risk preference evaluated from stated preferences emerges as a concept with significant temporal stability, but revealed preference measures do not. [29]

Relation to desires

Preferences and desires are two closely related notions: they are both conative states that determine our behavior. [30] The difference between the two is that desires are directed at one object while preferences concern a comparison between two alternatives, of which one is preferred to the other. [31] [30] The focus on preferences instead of desires is very common in the field of decision theory. It has been argued that desire is the more fundamental notion and that preferences are to be defined in terms of desires. [32] [31] [30] For this to work, desire has to be understood as involving a degree or intensity. Given this assumption, a preference can be defined as a comparison of two desires. [32] That Nadia prefers tea over coffee, for example, just means that her desire for tea is stronger than her desire for coffee. One argument for this approach is due to considerations of parsimony: a great number of preferences can be derived from a very small number of desires. [32] [30] One objection to this theory is that our introspective access is much more immediate in cases of preferences than in cases of desires. So it is usually much easier for us to know which of two options we prefer than to know the degree with which we desire a particular object. This consideration has been used to suggest that maybe preference, and not desire, is the more fundamental notion. [32]

Insolvency

In Insolvency, the term can be used to describe when a company pays a specific creditor or group of creditors. From doing this, that creditor(s) is made better off, than other creditors. After paying the 'preferred creditor', the company seeks to go into formal insolvency like an administration or liquidation. There must be a desire to make the creditor better off, for them to be a preference. If the preference is proven, legal action can occur. It is a wrongful act of trading. Disqualification is a risk. [33] Preference arises within the context of the principle maintaining that one of the main objectives in the winding up of an insolvent company is to ensure the equal treatment of creditors. [34] The rules on preferences allow paying up their creditors as insolvency looms, but that it must prove that the transaction is a result of ordinary commercial considerations. [34] Also, under the English Insolvency Act 1986, if a creditor was proven to have forced the company to pay, the resulting payment would not be considered a preference since it would not constitute unfairness. [35] It is the decision to give a preference, rather than the giving of the preference pursuant to that decision, which must be influenced by the desire to produce the effect of the preference. For these purposes, therefore, the relevant time is the date of the decision, not the date of giving the preference. [36]

See also

Related Research Articles

Rational choice theory refers to a set of guidelines that help understand economic and social behaviour. The theory originated in the eighteenth century and can be traced back to the political economist and philosopher Adam Smith. The theory postulates that an individual will perform a cost–benefit analysis to determine whether an option is right for them. It also suggests that an individual's self-driven rational actions will help better the overall economy. Rational choice theory looks at three concepts: rational actors, self interest and the invisible hand.

In economics, utility is a measure of the satisfaction that a certain person has from a certain state of the world. Over time, the term has been used in two different meanings.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Indifference curve</span> Concept in economics

In economics, an indifference curve connects points on a graph representing different quantities of two goods, points between which a consumer is indifferent. That is, any combinations of two products indicated by the curve will provide the consumer with equal levels of utility, and the consumer has no preference for one combination or bundle of goods over a different combination on the same curve. One can also refer to each point on the indifference curve as rendering the same level of utility (satisfaction) for the consumer. In other words, an indifference curve is the locus of various points showing different combinations of two goods providing equal utility to the consumer. Utility is then a device to represent preferences rather than something from which preferences come. The main use of indifference curves is in the representation of potentially observable demand patterns for individual consumers over commodity bundles.

Bounded rationality is the idea that rationality is limited when individuals make decisions, and under these limitations, rational individuals will select a decision that is satisfactory rather than optimal.

Behavioral economics is the study of the psychological, cognitive, emotional, cultural and social factors involved in the decisions of individuals or institutions, and how these decisions deviate from those implied by classical economic theory.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Prospect theory</span> Theory of behavioral economics and behavioral finance

Prospect theory is a theory of behavioral economics, judgment and decision making that was developed by Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky in 1979. The theory was cited in the decision to award Kahneman the 2002 Nobel Memorial Prize in Economics.

The theory of consumer choice is the branch of microeconomics that relates preferences to consumption expenditures and to consumer demand curves. It analyzes how consumers maximize the desirability of their consumption, by maximizing utility subject to a consumer budget constraint. Factors influencing consumers' evaluation of the utility of goods include: income level, cultural factors, product information and physio-psychological factors.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Decision theory</span> Branch of applied probability theory

Decision theory is a branch of applied probability theory and analytic philosophy concerned with the theory of making decisions based on assigning probabilities to various factors and assigning numerical consequences to the outcome.

The expected utility hypothesis is a foundational assumption in mathematical economics concerning decision making under uncertainty. It postulates that rational agents maximize utility, meaning the subjective desirability of their actions. Rational choice theory, a cornerstone of microeconomics, builds this postulate to model aggregate social behaviour.

In gambling, economics, and the philosophy of probability, a Dutch book or lock is a set of odds and bets that ensures a guaranteed profit. It is generally used as a thought experiment to motivate Von Neumann–Morgenstern axioms or the axioms of probability by showing they are equivalent to philosophical coherence or Pareto efficiency.

Utility maximization was first developed by utilitarian philosophers Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill. In microeconomics, the utility maximization problem is the problem consumers face: "How should I spend my money in order to maximize my utility?" It is a type of optimal decision problem. It consists of choosing how much of each available good or service to consume, taking into account a constraint on total spending (income), the prices of the goods and their preferences.

In decision theory, the Ellsberg paradox is a paradox in which people's decisions are inconsistent with subjective expected utility theory. John Maynard Keynes published a version of the paradox in 1921. Daniel Ellsberg popularized the paradox in his 1961 paper, "Risk, Ambiguity, and the Savage Axioms". It is generally taken to be evidence of ambiguity aversion, in which a person tends to prefer choices with quantifiable risks over those with unknown, incalculable risks.

Revealed preference theory, pioneered by economist Paul Anthony Samuelson in 1938, is a method of analyzing choices made by individuals, mostly used for comparing the influence of policies on consumer behavior. Revealed preference models assume that the preferences of consumers can be revealed by their purchasing habits.

The Allais paradox is a choice problem designed by Maurice Allais to show an inconsistency of actual observed choices with the predictions of expected utility theory. Rather than adhering to rationality, the Allais paradox proves that individuals rarely make rational decisions consistently when required to do so immediately. The independence axiom of expected utility theory, which requires that the preferences of an individual should not change when altering two lotteries by equal proportions, was proven to be violated by the paradox.

Pairwise comparison generally is any process of comparing entities in pairs to judge which of each entity is preferred, or has a greater amount of some quantitative property, or whether or not the two entities are identical. The method of pairwise comparison is used in the scientific study of preferences, attitudes, voting systems, social choice, public choice, requirements engineering and multiagent AI systems. In psychology literature, it is often referred to as paired comparison.

In decision theory, the von Neumann–Morgenstern (VNM) utility theorem shows that, under certain axioms of rational behavior, a decision-maker faced with risky (probabilistic) outcomes of different choices will behave as if they are maximizing the expected value of some function defined over the potential outcomes at some specified point in the future. This function is known as the von Neumann–Morgenstern utility function. The theorem is the basis for expected utility theory.

In economics, and in other social sciences, preference refers to an order by which an agent, while in search of an "optimal choice", ranks alternatives based on their respective utility. Preferences are evaluations that concern matters of value, in relation to practical reasoning. Individual preferences are determined by taste, need, ..., as opposed to price, availability or personal income. Classical economics assumes that people act in their best (rational) interest. In this context, rationality would dictate that, when given a choice, an individual will select an option that maximizes their self-interest. But preferences are not always transitive, both because real humans are far from always being rational and because in some situations preferences can form cycles, in which case there exists no well-defined optimal choice. An example of this is Efron dice.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Semiorder</span> Numerical ordering with a margin of error

In order theory, a branch of mathematics, a semiorder is a type of ordering for items with numerical scores, where items with widely differing scores are compared by their scores and where scores within a given margin of error are deemed incomparable. Semiorders were introduced and applied in mathematical psychology by Duncan Luce as a model of human preference. They generalize strict weak orderings, in which items with equal scores may be tied but there is no margin of error. They are a special case of partial orders and of interval orders, and can be characterized among the partial orders by additional axioms, or by two forbidden four-item suborders.

In expected utility theory, a lottery is a discrete distribution of probability on a set of states of nature. The elements of a lottery correspond to the probabilities that each of the states of nature will occur, e.g.. Much of the theoretical analysis of choice under uncertainty involves characterizing the available choices in terms of lotteries.

Stochastic transitivity models are stochastic versions of the transitivity property of binary relations studied in mathematics. Several models of stochastic transitivity exist and have been used to describe the probabilities involved in experiments of paired comparisons, specifically in scenarios where transitivity is expected, however, empirical observations of the binary relation is probabilistic. For example, players' skills in a sport might be expected to be transitive, i.e. "if player A is better than B and B is better than C, then player A must be better than C"; however, in any given match, a weaker player might still end up winning with a positive probability. Tightly matched players might have a higher chance of observing this inversion while players with large differences in their skills might only see these inversions happen seldom. Stochastic transitivity models formalize such relations between the probabilities and the underlying transitive relation.

References

  1. Zajonc, Robert B.; Markus, Hazel (1982-09-01). "Affective and Cognitive Factors in Preferences". Journal of Consumer Research. 9 (2): 123–131. doi:10.1086/208905. ISSN   0093-5301.
  2. Allan, Bentley B. (2019). "Paradigm and nexus: neoclassical economics and the growth imperative in the World Bank, 1948-2000". Review of International Political Economy. 26 (1): 183–206. doi:10.1080/09692290.2018.1543719. S2CID   158564367.
  3. Zey, Mary (1998). Rational Choice Theory and Organizational Theory: A Critique. SAGE Publications, Inc. pp. 1–13.
  4. 1 2 Bossert, Walter; Kotaro, Suzumura (2009). "External Norms and Rationality of Choice". Economics and Philosophy. 25 (2): 139–152. doi:10.1017/S0266267109990010. S2CID   15220288.
  5. 1 2 Schotter, Andrew (2006). "Strong and Wrong: The Use of Rational Choice Theory in Experimental Economics". Journal of Theoretical Politics. 18 (4): 498–511. doi:10.1177/0951629806067455. S2CID   29003374.
  6. Eliaz, Kfir (2006). "Indifference or indecisiveness? Choice-theoretic foundations of incomplete preferences". Games and Economic Behavior. 56: 61–86. doi:10.1016/j.geb.2005.06.007.
  7. Aleskerov, Fuad (2007). Utility Maximization, Choice and Preferences (2 ed.). Springer. pp. 17–52.
  8. List, Christian (2012). "The theory of judgment aggregation: an introductory review" (PDF). Synthese. 187 (1): 179–207. doi:10.1007/s11229-011-0025-3. S2CID   6430197.
  9. Kirsh, Yoram (2017). "Utility and Happiness in a Prosperous Society". OUI – Institute for Policy Analysis Working Paper Series. 37.
  10. Teraji, Shinji (2018). The Cognitive Basis of Institutions: A Synthesis of Behavioral and Institutional Economics. London: Academic Press. p. 137. ISBN   9780128120231.
  11. Nagaya, Kazuhisa (2021-10-15). "Why and Under What Conditions Does Loss Aversion Emerge?". Japanese Psychological Research. 65 (4): 379–398. doi:10.1111/jpr.12385. ISSN   0021-5368. S2CID   244976714.
  12. Debreu, Gérard (1952). "Definite and semidefinite quadratic forms". Econometrica. 20 (2): 295–300. doi:10.2307/1907852. JSTOR   1907852.
  13. Debreu, Gérard (1960). "Topological methods in cardinal utility theory". In Arrow, Kenneth (ed.). Mathematical Methods in the Social Sciences,1959. Stanford: Stanford University Press. pp. 16–26. doi:10.1016/S0377-2217(03)00413-2.
  14. Tangian, Andranik (2002). "Constructing a quasi-concave quadratic objective function from interviewing a decision maker". European Journal of Operational Research. 141 (3): 608–640. doi:10.1016/S0377-2217(01)00185-0.
  15. Tangian, Andranik (2004). "A model for ordinally constructing additive objective functions". European Journal of Operational Research. 159 (2): 476–512. doi:10.1016/S0377-2217(03)00413-2.
  16. Kalter, Frank; Kroneberg, Clemens (2012). "Rational Choice Theory and Empirical Research: Methodological and Theoretical Contributions in Europe". Annual Review of Sociology. 38 (1): 73–92. doi:10.1146/annurev-soc-071811-145441.
  17. England, Paula (1989). "A feminist critique of rational-choice theories: Implications for sociology". The American Sociologist. 20 (1): 14–28. doi:10.1007/BF02697784. S2CID   143743641.
  18. Herfeld, Catherine (2021). "Revisiting the criticisms of rational choice theories". Philosophy Compass. 17 (1).
  19. Case, Karl (2008). "A Response to Guerrien and Benicourt". The Review of Radical Political Economics. 40 (3): 331–335. doi:10.1177/0486613408320324. S2CID   154665809.
  20. Angner, Erik (2021). A Course in Behavioural Economics (3 ed.). United Kingdom: Macmillan Education Limited. pp. 25–37. ISBN   978-1-352-01080-0.
  21. Grandori, Anna (2010). "A rational heuristic model of economic decision making". Rationality and Society. 22 (4): 477–504. doi:10.1177/1043463110383972. S2CID   146886098.
  22. Bouteska, Ahmed; Regaieg, Boutheina (2020). "Loss aversion, overconfidence of investors and their impact on market performance evidence from the US stock markets". Journal of Economics, Finance and Administrative Science. 25 (50): 451–478. doi: 10.1108/JEFAS-07-2017-0081 . hdl: 10419/253806 . S2CID   158379317.
  23. Aguirre Sotelo, Jose Antonio Manuel; Block, Walter E. (2014-12-31). "Indifference Curve Analysis: The Correct and the Incorrect". Oeconomia Copernicana. 5 (4): 7–43. doi: 10.12775/OeC.2014.025 . ISSN   2353-1827.
  24. Steinberg, Laurence (July 2013). "The influence of neuroscience on US Supreme Court decisions about adolescents' criminal culpability". Nature Reviews Neuroscience. 14 (7): 513–518. doi:10.1038/nrn3509. ISSN   1471-003X. PMID   23756633. S2CID   12544303.
  25. Harrison, Glenn W.; Rutström, E. Elisabet (2008), "Risk Aversion in the Laboratory", Research in Experimental Economics, Bingley: Emerald (MCB UP ), vol. 12, pp. 41–196, doi:10.1016/s0193-2306(08)00003-3, ISBN   978-0-7623-1384-6 , retrieved 2023-04-23
  26. Appelt, Kirstin C.; Milch, Kerry F.; Handgraaf, Michel J. J.; Weber, Elke U. (April 2011). "The Decision Making Individual Differences Inventory and guidelines for the study of individual differences in judgment and decision-making research". Judgment and Decision Making. 6 (3): 252–262. doi: 10.1017/S1930297500001455 . ISSN   1930-2975. S2CID   2468108.
  27. Beshears, John; Choi, James; Laibson, David; Madrian, Brigitte (May 2008). "How are Preferences Revealed?" (PDF). Journal of Public Economics. Cambridge, MA. 92 (8–9): 1787–1794. doi:10.3386/w13976. PMC   3993927 . PMID   24761048.
  28. Charness, Gary; Gneezy, Uri; Imas, Alex (March 2013). "Experimental methods: Eliciting risk preferences". Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization. 87: 43–51. doi:10.1016/j.jebo.2012.12.023.
  29. Mata, Rui; Frey, Renato; Richter, David; Schupp, Jürgen; Hertwig, Ralph (2018-05-01). "Risk Preference: A View from Psychology". Journal of Economic Perspectives. 32 (2): 155–172. doi:10.1257/jep.32.2.155. hdl: 21.11116/0000-0001-5038-6 . ISSN   0895-3309. PMID   30203934.
  30. 1 2 3 4 Schulz, Armin W. (2015). "Preferences Vs. Desires: Debating the Fundamental Structure of Conative States". Economics and Philosophy. 31 (2): 239–257. doi:10.1017/S0266267115000115. S2CID   155414997.
  31. 1 2 Pettit, Philip. "Desire - Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy". www.rep.routledge.com. Retrieved 4 May 2021.
  32. 1 2 3 4 Schroeder, Tim (2020). "Desire". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 3 May 2021.
  33. Steven, Keith. "What Is A Preference Under The Insolvency Act 1986" . Retrieved October 1, 2018.
  34. 1 2 Hannigan, Brenda (2015). Company Law, Fourth Edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 368. ISBN   9780198722861.
  35. Gullifer, Louise; Payne, Jennifer (2015). Corporate Finance Law: Principles and Policy, Second Edition. Oxford: Bloomsbury Publishing. p. 111. ISBN   9781782259602.
  36. Green, Elliot. "Green v Ireland [2011] EWHC 1305 (Ch)" . Retrieved December 1, 2022.

General

  • Brehm, J.W. (1956). Post-decision changes in desirability of choice alternatives. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 52, 384–389.
  • Coppin, G., Delplanque, S., Cayeux, I., Porcherot, C., & Sander, D. (2010). I'm no longer torn after choice: How explicit choices can implicitly shape preferences for odors. Psychological Science, 21, 489–493.
  • Lichtenstein, S., & Slovic, P. (2006). The construction of preference. New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Scherer, K.R. (2005). What are emotions? And how can they be measured? Social Science Information, 44, 695–729.
  • Sharot, T., De Martino, B., & Dolan, R.J. (2009). How choice reveals and shapes expected hedonic outcome. Journal of Neuroscience, 29, 3760–3765.