A verbum dicendi (Latin for "word of speaking" or "verb of speaking"), also called verb of utterance, is a word that expresses speech or introduces a quotation. English examples of verbs of speaking include say, utter, ask and rumble. Because a verbum dicendi often introduces a quotation, it may grammaticalize into a quotative.
The plural of verbum dicendi is verba dicendi.
A complement of a verbum dicendi can be direct or indirect speech. Direct speech is a single unit of linguistic object that is '"mentioned" rather than used.' [1] In contrast, indirect speech is a proposition whose parts make semantic and syntactic contribution to the whole sentence just like parts of the matrix clause (i.e. the main clause/sentence, as opposed to an embedded clause).
Cross-linguistically, there are syntactic differences between direct and indirect speech, which include verbatimness, interpretations of deictic expressions, tense, presence or absence of complementizers, and syntactic opacity. [1]
If a complement of a verbum dicendi is direct speech, it is presented as a faithful report of what the original speaker exactly said. In the following examples, the first means that "I will go to Tokyo" was the exact sentence that John uttered. In the second, on the other hand, John might have uttered a different sentence, for example, "I'll spend my vacation in Tokyo." [1]
a. John said (to me): "I will go to Tokyo"
b. John said (to me) that he would go to Tokyo. [1]
If a complement of a verbum dicendi is direct speech, deictic expressions in the complement are interpreted with respect to the context in which the original sentence was uttered. [1] In (2)a, the embedded clause is direct speech; the first person pronoun I and the second person pronoun you in "Ii will give youj a hand" respectively refer to the utterer and the addressee in the context in which this quoted speech was uttered. In contrast, if the embedded clause is indirect speech, all deictic expressions in the sentence are interpreted in the context in which the matrix clause is uttered. In (2)b, the embedded clause is indirect speech, so all the occurrences of the first person pronoun me and the second person pronoun you in the sentence respectively refer to the utterer and the addressee in the immediate context in which 2(b) is uttered.
(2)a. Youi said to mej: "Ii will give youj a hand."
(2)b. Youi said to mej that youi would give mej a hand. [1]
Some languages, including English, show difference in tense between direct and indirect quotes. This phenomenon is formalized as "the sequence of tense rules." [1]
In some languages, the distinction between direct and indirect speech can be diagnosed by presence of an overt complementizer. Many languages, including English, have an overt complementizer (e.g. that in English) when the complement of a verbum dicendi is indirect speech, as seen in (1)b and 2(b) above. Some languages, such as Tikar, on the other hand, use an overt complementizer to introduce indirect speech. [1]
If a complement of a verbum dicendi is direct speech, it is "syntactically opaque," [1] meaning that syntactic elements inside this embedded clause cannot interact with elements in the matrix clause.
For example, Negative Polarity Items (NPI) inside an embedded direct quote cannot be licensed by a syntactic element in the matrix clause.
(3)a. ?Nobody said "we saw anything."
(3)b. Nobody said that they had seen anything. [2]
Note that (3)a is still syntactically well-formed but cannot communicate the same meaning as (3)b, in which the NPI anything inside the embedded indirect quote [they had seen anything] is licensed by nobody in the matrix clause. Another example is that wh-movement out of an embedded direct quote is prohibited, as seen in (4)a below.
(4)a. *What did John say: "I read _"?
(4)b. What did John say that he had read _? [1]
In English, verba dicendi such as say and think are used to report speech and thought processes. [3]
(1)a. If you touched a one they would say ‘wey you’re on’. (UK) b. And I thought ‘Well we need some more popcorn’. (US) [3]
Such examples are prototypical, but many variants exist within an open class of manner-of-speaking verbs, such as ask, shout, scream, wonder, yell, holler, bellow, grunt, mumble, mutter, etc. These may be considered semantically more specific, implying a clause type (as in ask) or indicating the intensity or prosody of the reported material (e.g. shout, mutter).
Quotation indicates to a listener that a message originated from a different voice, and/or at a different time than the present. An utterance like “Jim said ‘I love you’” reports at the present moment that Jim said “I love you” at some time in the past. Thus, there are two distinct active voices: that of the narrator and that of the reportee. [3] Written English often employs manner-of-speaking verbs or verba dicendi in conjunction with quotation marks to demarcate the quoted content. Speakers use more subtle phonetic and prosodic cues like intonation, rhythm, and mimesis to indicate reported speech.
There are numerous syntactically and semantically relevant properties of verba dicendi and manner-of-speaking verbs, several of which are highlighted below:
i. They are so-called Activity Verbs. They may occur in progressive and imperative forms, among other tests:
(2)a. He was shouting obscenities. b. Yell to George about the new quota. c. What John did was lisp French to Mary. [4]
ii. The subject of verba dicendi is normally sentient:
(3)a. My father howled for me to pick up the chair. b. *My desk howled for me to pick up the chair. [4]
However, it is possible, at least colloquially, to assign the subject role of some verba dicendi to abstracta. An expression like "When you're late, it says you don't care" could be one such example.
iii. Verba dicendi may have an indirect object, which may be marked by to and which is also normally sentient:
(4)a. Scream ‘Up the Queen’ (to the first person who passes) b. *She will howl 'O my stars and garters' to the essence of friendship [4]
iv. Manner-of-speaking verbs may have a direct object, which may be a noun describing the speech act itself, a desentential complement (that-clause, indirect question or infinitive), or a direct quotation:
(5)a. Hoffman will probably mutter a foul oath. b. Martin shrieked that there were cockroaches in the caviar. c. Regrettably, someone mumbled, “I suspect poison.” [4]
Further, the direct object of some manner-of-speaking verbs may be deleted, resulting in a sentence that does not indicate an act of communication, but rather a description of the sound made:
d. My companion shrieked. [4]
Other verba dicendi do not permit this, however. Say, ask, tell, for instance, cannot occur freely without an object:
e. *Said John [5]
Speak may occur without an object. In fact, its occurrence with an object is restricted. A that-clause, for example, is ungrammatical:
f. Margaret spoke (to me) g. *Margaret spoke that there were cockroaches in the caviar [4]
v. Some manner-of-speaking verbs may occur with directional adverbials, which cannot co-occur with indirect objects:
(6)a. He bellowed at us (*to Sam) [4]
Other verba dicendi cannot occur in at constructions:
b. *She {said/remarked/declared} (something) at me [4]
vi. Some manner-of-speaking verbs may have a nominal (noun) counterpart which sounds the same, but which has no communicative content, such as mutter, bellow, shriek, whine and whisper. Notice that other verba dicendi do not have these homophonous nouns (e.g. speak/speech, tell/tale, declare/declaration). [4] There are many such observations. Another property of verbs of speaking is the lack of so-called factivity effect; in other words, the speaker is not required to actually believe what they are saying. [6] This has implications for the truth conditions of quotative constructions:
(7) Mary says that Paul is her friend.
Mary's statement may be false, though it may be true that she actually said it. In fact, she may even believe it to be false. However, whether or not believing is part of speaking has been debated for some time. [6]
The syntax of quotation and verba dicendi appears at first glance to be a straightforward case of transitivity, in which the quoted material is interpreted as a direct object. In a case like
(8) Jim said “I love you” [3]
the traditionally held analysis takes the reported clause “I love you” to be the complement of say. Thus the quote is termed an NP (noun phrase) and introduced as a direct object.
This analysis is supported by some of the typical syntactic tools for testing direct objects, such as moving into the focus of a question and clefting. [3] However, constituency, movement and replacement tests show that the quotative clause does not behave like a normal transitive construction. For example, clefting and passivization of these forms give marked (ungrammatical, or strange at least) results:
(9)a. ?“I’ll call you” was said by Pat cf. The cat was held by Pat b. ?What Pat did with “I’ll call you” was say it cf. What Pat did with the cat was hold it [7]
Quotation may also be less restricted than ordinary transitive verbs. They may occur parenthetically, unlike other verbs:
(10)a. “I’ll call you” Pat said “and I hope you answer” cf. ?The cat Pat held and a book b. “I” Pat said “will call you and I hope you answer” cf. *The Pat held cat and a book [7] [ dubious ]
Another issue is that manner-of-speaking verbs are not always obligatorily transitive. Verbs like think, laugh, scream, yell, whisper may be intransitive. [7] A different model has been proposed, which does not rely on transitivity, but rather an asymmetrical construction containing a reporting clause (head) and an independent reported clause. [7] Note that the asymmetry arises from the fact that the reporting clause is dependent on the quoted content for grammaticality, while the reverse is not true.
(11)a.*I said b.“I love you”
In this model, the dependent clause has a site of elaboration (e-site) which is filled by the independent clause:
HEAD[Pat said e-site] COMPLEMENT[“I’ll call you”] HEAD[Pat thought e-site] COMPLEMENT[“I’ll call you”] HEAD[Pat was like e-site] COMPLEMENT[“I’ll call you”] [7]
Direct quotation is reported from the perspective of the experiencer:
(12) He said “I am leaving now” [3]
However, indirect quotation is often paraphrased, and reported by a narrator from the perspective of the reportee. Verbs like ask and tell are frequently associated with indirect speech. English indirect quotation also shows a sequence-of-tense effect: a past tense reporting verb requires a "back-shift" in verb tense within the indirect quote itself [3]
(13)a. He said "I am leaving now" b. He said (that) he was leaving immediately [3]
Indirect quotation is, in theory, syntactically constrained and requires that the quoted content form a subordinate clause under the CP node. [3] However, what is heard in speech does not necessarily conform to theory. The complementizer that, though considered to be a marker of indirect quotation, is not obligatory and is often omitted. Further, it can (and does) occur with direct quotes in some dialects of English (e.g. Hong Kong, Indian). [7] Verbs of speaking often employ the Conversational Historical Present tense, whereby actions in the past are referred to with present-tense morphology. This is considered to add immediacy or authority to the discourse. [3] However, it also illustrates the difficulty in differentiating direct and indirect quotation. [3]
(14) So uh ... this lady says ... uh this uh Bert (‘)His son’ll make them. He’s an electrician(‘) [3]
Sentences with verba dicendi for direct quotation may use the somewhat antiquated verb-first (V2) order of English syntax. Inversion of this type with verbs of speaking or thinking frequently occurs in written English, though rarely in spoken English. It is also possible to invert the clause without changing subject-verb order. This is not possible with regular English transitives:
(15)a. “No no no” said Harry b. “You’re not drunk” she says cf. *The cat held Pat (where Pat did the holding) [7]
There are several restrictions, however. For example, quantifiers may occur to the right of the subject in a non-inverted quotative sentence, but not in an inverted sentence. They can, however, occur to the immediate left of the subject in an inverted sentence:
(16)a.”We must do this again”, the guests all declared to Tony b.”We must do this again”, declared all the guests to Tony c.*”We must do this again”, declared the guests all to Tony [5]
Inversion and negation with verba dicendi may co-occur only if the reporting clause itself is not inverted:
(17)a.“Let’s eat”, said John just once b.“Let’s eat”, John didn't just say once c.*”Let’s eat”, said not John just once d.*”Let’s eat”, not said John just once [5]
Other constraints involve subject position, DP direct objects, and movement, among others.
Grammaticalization is the attribution of grammatical character to a previously independent, autonomous word. [7] There is significant cross-linguistic evidence of verba dicendi grammaticalizing into functional syntactic categories. For instance, in some African and Asian languages, these verbs may grammaticalize into a complementizer. [7] In other East African languages, they may become markers of Tense-Aspect-Mood (TAM). [7] In English, the verb say in particular has also developed the function of a comment clause:
(18)a. Say there actually were vultures on his tail b. What say he does answer? c. Buy a big bottle – say about 250 mils d. If we ran out of flour or sugar, say, we would gather up a few eggs and take them to Mr. Nichols's general store e.“Say, isn’t that–” Lance started, but Buck answered before the question was even asked f.“Say, that’s our City,” bubbles Dolores g. Jump, I say, and be done with it [8]
In these examples, the verb say fulfils many roles. In the first two examples (a & b), it means ‘suppose', or 'assume.’ In the third and fourth examples (c & d) the meaning of say could be paraphrased as 'for example', or 'approximately.' Example (e) uses say as an imperative introducing a question and connotes 'tell me/us.' Say may also function as an interjection to either focus attention on the speaker or to convey some emotional state such as surprise, regret, disbelief, etc. [8] Finally, example (f) uses say in an emphatic, often imperative way. This function dates from the (early) Middle English period [7]
In addition to basic verba dicendi and manner of speaking verbs, other forms are frequently used in spoken English. What sets these apart is that they are not, semantically speaking, reporting verbs at all. Such forms include be like, be all, and go.
(19)a. Pat was like “I’ll call you.” [7] b. [...]and then my sister’s all “excuse me would you mind if I gave you, if I want your autograph” and she’s like “oh sure, no problem.” c. And he goes “yeah” and looks and you can tell maybe he thinks he's got the wrong address[...] [9]
These forms, particularly be like, have captured the attention of much linguistic study and documentation. Some research has addressed the syntax of these forms in quotation, which is highly problematic. For example, a verbum dicendi like say may refer to a previously quoted clause with it. However, this is not possible with these innovative forms:
(20)a. “I don’t know if he heard it, but I know I definitely said it b. *I’m like it c. *She was all it d. *I went it [10]
Notice that these forms also don’t behave as basic verba dicendi in many other ways. Clefting, for example, produces ungrammatical forms like
(21)a. *That’s nice was gone by me b. *Um, yah, I know, but there’s going to be wine there was been all by her [10]
They also can’t participate in inverted constructions like other manner-of-speaking verbs:
(22)a. *“Go home”, he was like b. *“I’m leaving”, was all John
Several other issues concerning these forms are the topic of much current study, including their diachrony, or change in use over time. Go, for example, dates as far back as the eighteenth century, in contexts like go bang, go crack, go crash, etc. [3] Research on these forms has also shown that be like in particular is associated with young people. However, this assumption is questioned on the basis of more recent findings which suggest that it is used by older speakers as well. [9] It has also been largely attributed to female speakers, especially white females in California (Valley Girls). However, it is regularly used by speakers of both sexes, and in dialects of English outside of the US, including Canada and the UK. [10] This is a topic of a great deal of research in current syntax and sociolinguistics.
In Japanese, verba dicendi (発話行為動詞 hatsuwa kōi dōshi [11] 'speech act verb'), also referred to as verbs of communication [12] or verbs of saying, [13] include 言う iu/yuu 'say', 聞く kiku 'ask', 語る kataru 'relate', 話す hanasu 'talk', and 述べる noberu 'state'. [12] [11]
Verba dicendi occur in the following construction: [_________] {と -to, って -tte} Verbum dicendi. [12]
と -to has been described as a complementizer and a quotative particle. [12] [13] Historically, use of と -to was restricted to reporting a statement by another speaker, but it has a much wider distribution in modern Japanese. [12] In conversational Japanese, って -tte [14] is more frequently used, and it has been described as a quotative particle, a hearsay particle, a quotation marker, and a quotative complementizer. [15] [16] In the above construction, the underlined phrase headed by {と -to, って -tte} can be a word, a clause, a sentence, or an onomatopoetic expression. [12]
Like in English, verba dicendi in Japanese can introduce both direct and indirect speech as their complement. [13] This is contrasted with verbs of thinking, which only introduce indirect speech. An exception to this is a verb of thinking 思う omou 'think', which can introduce a speech that is not uttered but takes place in one's mind as direct speech in the simple past tense; this use of 思う omou 'think' is called a "quasi-communicative act". [13]
In Japanese, a complement of a verbum dicendi can be ambiguous between direct and indirect readings, meaning that the distinction can only be inferred from the discourse context. [13] For example, in (1), [boku ga Tookyoo e iku], which is in the complement of the verb 言う iu (past tense: itta), can be interpreted as either direct speech (2)a or indirect speech (2)b.
(1) 太郎は僕が東京へ行くと言った。
Taroo wa [boku ga Tookyoo e ik-u] to it-ta [13]
Taro TOP I(MALE) NOM Tokyo to go-PRS QUOT say-PST.
(2)a. Taroi said, "Ii will go to Tokyo."
(2)b. Taroi said that Ij would go to Tokyo.
One reason for this direct-indirect ambiguity in Japanese is that Japanese indirect speech does not involve "backshifting of tense" [13] observed in other languages including English. In the English translations, the direct speech in (2)a has will in the tense of the embedded clause, but in (2)b, it has been "backshifted" to would so that it matches the past tense of the matrix clause. Tense does not serve as a diagnostics of direct-indirect distinctions in Japanese. [17] [12]
Another reason for the ambiguity is that both direct and indirect quotes are introduced by {と -to, って -tte} in Japanese. Hence, presence of an overt complementizer cannot disambiguate direct and indirect speech either. [13]
Disambiguation of direct and indirect speech in Japanese depends on switches in deictic expressions and expressions of "speaker-addressee relationship". [12] One language-specific diagnostics of direct speech is so-called "addressee-oriented expressions," [16] which trigger a presupposition that there is an addressee in the discourse context. Some examples are listed below:
sentence final particles: さ -sa 'let me tell you'; ね -ne 'you know'; よ -yo 'I tell you'; わ -wa 'I want you to know'
imperative forms: 「走れ!」hashire 'Run!’
polite verbs/polite auxiliary verbs: です desu; ございます gozaimasu; ますmasu [16] [12]
For example, in (3), [Ame da yo] in the complement of the verb 言う iu (past tense: itta) is unambiguously interpreted as direct speech because of the sentence final particle よ -yo 'I tell you'.
(3) 太郎は花子に「雨だよ」と言った。
Taro wa Hanako ni [Ame da yo] to it-ta [13]
Taro TOP Hanako DAT rain COP yo QUOT say-PST
'Taro said to Hanako, "It is raining, I tell you."
Similarly, in (4), [Ame desu] in the complement of the verb 言う iu (past tense: itta) is unambiguously interpreted as direct speech because of the polite verb です desu.
(4) 太郎は花子に「雨です」と言った。
Taro wa Hanako ni [Ame desu] to it-ta [13]
Taro TOP Hanako DAT rain desu QUOT say-PST
'Taro said to Hanako politely, "It is raining."
One diagnostics of indirect speech in Japanese is presence of the reflexive pronoun 自分 zibun 'self'. It is a gender-neutral pronoun that uniformly refers to "the private self," [13] or an agent of thinking, as opposed to "the public self," an agent of communicating, expressed by various personal pronouns (e.g. 僕 boku 'I(MALE)'), occupational roles (e.g. 先生 sensei 'teacher'), and kinship terms (e.g. お母さん okaasan 'mother'). [13]
For example, in (5), [zibun ga Tookyoo e iku] in the complement of the verb 言う iu (past tense: itta) is unambiguously interpreted as indirect speech because of the presence of 自分 zibun 'self', which is co-referential with 太郎 Taro.
(5) 太郎は自分が東京へ行くと言った。
Tarooi wa [zibuni ga Tookyoo e iku] to it-ta [13]
Taro TOP self NOM Tokyo to go QUOT say-PST.
'Taro said that he would go to Tokyo.'
Note that (5) only differs from (1) in the subject of the embedded clause; (5) has 自分 zibun 'self' and (1) has 僕 boku 'I(MALE)'.
It has been reported that some sentences in Japanese have characteristics of both direct and indirect modes simultaneously. [1] This phenomenon is called "semi-indirect mode" or "quasi-direct mode". It is also observed in a reported speech, and Kuno (1988) has termed it "blended discourse". [18] [1] (6) is an example of blended discourse.
(6) 太郎は奴のうちに何時に来いと言ったのか。
Taroi wa [yatui-no uti-ni nanzi-ni ko-i] to it-ta no ka? [1]
Taro TOP [he-GEN house-DAT what.time-DAT come-IMP] QUOT say-PST Q Q
'What time did Taroi say, [come to hisi house ______]?'
[yatu-no uti-ni nanzi-ni ko-i] in the complement of the verb 言う iu (past tense: itta) appears to be direct speech because it has an imperative verb form 来い ko-i 'Come!'.
On the other hand, the third person pronoun 奴 yatu 'he' inside the embedded clause is co-referential with the matrix subject 太郎 Taro. [1] This means that this deictic expression inside the embedded clause is interpreted in the context in which the whole sentence (6) is uttered; cross-linguistically, this is considered to be a property of indirect speech.
Moreover, the wh-phrase 何時 nanzi 'what time' inside the embedded clause is taking matrix scope, meaning that it interacts with the matrix clause to influence the meaning of the whole sentence. [1] This sentence means that, for example, 太郎 Taro had said "Come to my house at ten o'clock!," and the utterer of (6), not knowing the content of "ten o'clock," is requesting for this information. Availability of this meaning is an indication of indirect speech because if the embedded clause was direct speech, it would be syntactically opaque.
A quotation is the repetition of a sentence, phrase, or passage from speech or text that someone has said or written. In oral speech, it is the representation of an utterance that is introduced by a quotative marker, such as a verb of saying. For example: John said: "I saw Mary today". Quotations in oral speech are also signaled by special prosody in addition to quotative markers. In written text, quotations are signaled by quotation marks. Quotations are also used to present well-known statement parts that are explicitly attributed by citation to their original source; such statements are marked with quotation marks.
English grammar is the set of structural rules of the English language. This includes the structure of words, phrases, clauses, sentences, and whole texts.
In language, a clause is a constituent that comprises a semantic predicand and a semantic predicate. A typical clause consists of a subject and a syntactic predicate, the latter typically a verb phrase composed of a verb with any objects and other modifiers. However, the subject is sometimes unexpressed if it is retrievable from context, especially in null-subject language but also in other languages, including English instances of the imperative mood.
In syntax, verb-second (V2) word order is a sentence structure in which the finite verb of a sentence or a clause is placed in the clause's second position, so that the verb is preceded by a single word or group of words.
Irish syntax is rather different from that of most Indo-European languages, especially because of its VSO word order.
In linguistics, wh-movement is the formation of syntactic dependencies involving interrogative words. An example in English is the dependency formed between what and the object position of doing in "What are you doing?" Interrogative forms are sometimes known within English linguistics as wh-words, such as what, when, where, who, and why, but also include other interrogative words, such as how. This dependency has been used as a diagnostic tool in syntactic studies as it can be observed to interact with other grammatical constraints.
In English, the passive voice is marked by a subject that is followed by a stative verb complemented by a past participle. For example:
The enemy was defeated. Caesar was stabbed.
The sequence of tenses is a set of grammatical rules of a particular language, governing the agreement between the tenses of verbs in related clauses or sentences.
In grammar, accusative and infinitive is the name for a syntactic construction first described in Latin and Greek, also found in various forms in other languages such as English and Dutch. In this construction, the subject of a subordinate clause is put in the accusative or objective case and the verb appears in the infinitive form.
Indirect speech, also known as reported speech, indirect discourse (US), or ōrātiō oblīqua, is the practice, common in all Latin historical writers, of reporting spoken or written words indirectly, using different grammatical forms. Passages of indirect speech can extend from a single phrase to an entire paragraph, and this style was generally preferred by Roman historians to the direct speech commonly found in Greek authors.
In linguistics, a complementizer or complementiser is a functional category that includes those words that can be used to turn a clause into the subject or object of a sentence. For example, the word that may be called a complementizer in English sentences like Mary believes that it is raining. The concept of complementizers is specific to certain modern grammatical theories. In traditional grammar, such words are normally considered conjunctions. The standard abbreviation for complementizer is C.
A quotative is a grammatical device to mark quoted speech. When a quotation is used, the grammatical person and tense of the original utterance is maintained, rather than adjusting it as would be the case with reported speech. It can be equated with "spoken quotation marks."
In grammar, a content clause is a dependent clause that provides content implied or commented upon by an independent clause. The term was coined by Danish linguist Otto Jespersen. Content clauses are also known as noun clauses.
The term linguistic performance was used by Noam Chomsky in 1960 to describe "the actual use of language in concrete situations". It is used to describe both the production, sometimes called parole, as well as the comprehension of language. Performance is defined in opposition to "competence"; the latter describes the mental knowledge that a speaker or listener has of language.
In linguistics, an empty category, which may also be referred to as a covert category, is an element in the study of syntax that does not have any phonological content and is therefore unpronounced. Empty categories exist in contrast to overt categories which are pronounced. When representing empty categories in tree structures, linguists use a null symbol (∅) to depict the idea that there is a mental category at the level being represented, even if the word(s) are being left out of overt speech. The phenomenon was named and outlined by Noam Chomsky in his 1981 LGB framework, and serves to address apparent violations of locality of selection — there are different types of empty categories that each appear to account for locality violations in different environments. Empty categories are present in most of the world's languages, although different languages allow for different categories to be empty.
In linguistics, speech or indirect discourse is a grammatical mechanism for reporting the content of another utterance without directly quoting it. For example, the English sentence Jill said she was coming is indirect discourse while Jill said "I'm coming" would be direct discourse. In fiction, the "utterance" might amount to an unvoiced thought that passes through a stream of consciousness, as reported by an omniscient narrator.
Logophoricity is a phenomenon of binding relation that may employ a morphologically different set of anaphoric forms, in the context where the referent is an entity whose speech, thoughts, or feelings are being reported. This entity may or may not be distant from the discourse, but the referent must reside in a clause external to the one in which the logophor resides. The specially-formed anaphors that are morphologically distinct from the typical pronouns of a language are known as logophoric pronouns, originally coined by the linguist Claude Hagège. The linguistic importance of logophoricity is its capability to do away with ambiguity as to who is being referred to. A crucial element of logophoricity is the logophoric context, defined as the environment where use of logophoric pronouns is possible. Several syntactic and semantic accounts have been suggested. While some languages may not be purely logophoric, logophoric context may still be found in those languages; in those cases, it is common to find that in the place where logophoric pronouns would typically occur, non-clause-bounded reflexive pronouns appear instead.
This article describes the uses of various verb forms in modern standard English language. This includes:
This article describes the syntax of clauses in the English language, chiefly in Modern English. A clause is often said to be the smallest grammatical unit that can express a complete proposition. But this semantic idea of a clause leaves out much of English clause syntax. For example, clauses can be questions, but questions are not propositions. A syntactic description of an English clause is that it is a subject and a verb. But this too fails, as a clause need not have a subject, as with the imperative, and, in many theories, an English clause may be verbless. The idea of what qualifies varies between theories and has changed over time.
The Ancient Greek infinitive is a non-finite verb form, sometimes called a verb mood, with no endings for person or number, but it is inflected for tense and voice.
{{cite journal}}
: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)