Free energy principle

Last updated

The free energy principle is a theoretical framework suggesting that the brain reduces surprise or uncertainty by making predictions based on internal models and updating them using sensory input. It highlights the brain's objective of aligning its internal model and the external world to enhance prediction accuracy. This principle integrates Bayesian inference with active inference, where actions are guided by predictions and sensory feedback refines them. It has wide-ranging implications for comprehending brain function, perception, and action. [1]

Contents

Overview

In biophysics and cognitive science, the free energy principle is a mathematical principle describing a formal account of the representational capacities of physical systems: that is, why things that exist look as if they track properties of the systems to which they are coupled. [2]

It establishes that the dynamics of physical systems minimise a quantity known as surprisal (which is the negative log probability of some outcome); or equivalently, its variational upper bound, called free energy . The principle is used especially in Bayesian approaches to brain function, but also some approaches to artificial intelligence; it is formally related to variational Bayesian methods and was originally introduced by Karl Friston as an explanation for embodied perception-action loops in neuroscience. [3]

The free energy principle models the behaviour of systems that are distinct from, but coupled to, another system (e.g., an embedding environment), where the degrees of freedom that implement the interface between the two systems is known as a Markov blanket. More formally, the free energy principle says that if a system has a "particular partition" (i.e., into particles, with their Markov blankets), then subsets of that system will track the statistical structure of other subsets (which are known as internal and external states or paths of a system).

The free energy principle is based on the Bayesian idea of the brain as an “inference engine.” Under the free energy principle, systems pursue paths of least surprise, or equivalently, minimize the difference between predictions based on their model of the world and their sense and associated perception. This difference is quantified by variational free energy and is minimized by continuous correction of the world model of the system, or by making the world more like the predictions of the system. By actively changing the world to make it closer to the expected state, systems can also minimize the free energy of the system. Friston assumes this to be the principle of all biological reaction. [4] Friston also believes his principle applies to mental disorders as well as to artificial intelligence. AI implementations based on the active inference principle have shown advantages over other methods. [4]

The free energy principle is a mathematical principle of information physics: much like the principle of maximum entropy or the principle of least action, it is true on mathematical grounds. To attempt to falsify the free energy principle is a category mistake, akin to trying to falsify calculus by making empirical observations. (One cannot invalidate a mathematical theory in this way; instead, one would need to derive a formal contradiction from the theory.) In a 2018 interview, Friston explained what it entails for the free energy principle to not be subject to falsification: "I think it is useful to make a fundamental distinction at this point—that we can appeal to later. The distinction is between a state and process theory; i.e., the difference between a normative principle that things may or may not conform to, and a process theory or hypothesis about how that principle is realized. Under this distinction, the free energy principle stands in stark distinction to things like predictive coding and the Bayesian brain hypothesis. This is because the free energy principle is what it is — a principle. Like Hamilton's principle of stationary action, it cannot be falsified. It cannot be disproven. In fact, there’s not much you can do with it, unless you ask whether measurable systems conform to the principle. On the other hand, hypotheses that the brain performs some form of Bayesian inference or predictive coding are what they are—hypotheses. These hypotheses may or may not be supported by empirical evidence." [5] There are many examples of these hypotheses being supported by empirical evidence. [6]

Background

The notion that self-organising biological systems – like a cell or brain – can be understood as minimising variational free energy is based upon Helmholtz’s work on unconscious inference [7] and subsequent treatments in psychology [8] and machine learning. [9] Variational free energy is a function of observations and a probability density over their hidden causes. This variational density is defined in relation to a probabilistic model that generates predicted observations from hypothesized causes. In this setting, free energy provides an approximation to Bayesian model evidence. [10] Therefore, its minimisation can be seen as a Bayesian inference process. When a system actively makes observations to minimise free energy, it implicitly performs active inference and maximises the evidence for its model of the world.

However, free energy is also an upper bound on the self-information of outcomes, where the long-term average of surprise is entropy. This means that if a system acts to minimise free energy, it will implicitly place an upper bound on the entropy of the outcomes – or sensory states – it samples. [11] [12]

Relationship to other theories

Active inference is closely related to the good regulator theorem [13] and related accounts of self-organisation, [14] [15] such as self-assembly, pattern formation, autopoiesis [16] and practopoiesis. [17] It addresses the themes considered in cybernetics, synergetics [18] and embodied cognition. Because free energy can be expressed as the expected energy of observations under the variational density minus its entropy, it is also related to the maximum entropy principle. [19] Finally, because the time average of energy is action, the principle of minimum variational free energy is a principle of least action. Active inference allowing for scale invariance has also been applied to other theories and domains. For instance, it has been applied to sociology, [20] [21] [22] [23] linguistics and communication, [24] [25] [26] semiotics, [27] [28] and epidemiology [29] among others.

Negative free energy is formally equivalent to the evidence lower bound, which is commonly used in machine learning to train generative models, such as variational autoencoders.

Action and perception

Figure 1: These schematics illustrate the partition of states into the internal states
m
(
t
)
{\displaystyle \mu (t)}
and external (hidden, latent) states
ps
(
t
)
{\displaystyle \psi (t)}
that are separated by a Markov blanket - comprising sensory states
s
(
t
)
{\displaystyle s(t)}
and active states
a
(
t
)
{\displaystyle a(t)}
. The upper panel shows exactly the same dependencies but rearranged so that the internal states are associated with the intracellular states of a cell, while the sensory states become the surface states of the cell membrane overlying active states (e.g., the actin filaments of the cytoskeleton). The lower panel shows this partition as it would be applied to action and perception in the brain; where active and internal states minimise a free energy functional of sensory states. The ensuing self-organisation of internal states then correspond to perception, while action couples brain states back to external states. MarokovBlanketFreeEnergyFigure.jpg
Figure 1: These schematics illustrate the partition of states into the internal states and external (hidden, latent) states that are separated by a Markov blanket – comprising sensory states and active states . The upper panel shows exactly the same dependencies but rearranged so that the internal states are associated with the intracellular states of a cell, while the sensory states become the surface states of the cell membrane overlying active states (e.g., the actin filaments of the cytoskeleton). The lower panel shows this partition as it would be applied to action and perception in the brain; where active and internal states minimise a free energy functional of sensory states. The ensuing self-organisation of internal states then correspond to perception, while action couples brain states back to external states.

Active inference applies the techniques of approximate Bayesian inference to infer the causes of sensory data from a 'generative' model of how that data is caused and then uses these inferences to guide action. Bayes' rule characterizes the probabilistically optimal inversion of such a causal model, but applying it is typically computationally intractable, leading to the use of approximate methods. In active inference, the leading class of such approximate methods are variational methods, for both practical and theoretical reasons: practical, as they often lead to simple inference procedures; and theoretical, because they are related to fundamental physical principles, as discussed above.

These variational methods proceed by minimizing an upper bound on the divergence between the Bayes-optimal inference (or 'posterior') and its approximation according to the method. This upper bound is known as the free energy, and we can accordingly characterize perception as the minimization of the free energy with respect to inbound sensory information, and action as the minimization of the same free energy with respect to outbound action information. This holistic dual optimization is characteristic of active inference, and the free energy principle is the hypothesis that all systems which perceive and act can be characterized in this way.

In order to exemplify the mechanics of active inference via the free energy principle, a generative model must be specified, and this typically involves a collection of probability density functions which together characterize the causal model. One such specification is as follows. The system is modelled as inhabiting a state space , in the sense that its states form the points of this space. The state space is then factorized according to , where is the space of 'external' states that are 'hidden' from the agent (in the sense of not being directly perceived or accessible), is the space of sensory states that are directly perceived by the agent, is the space of the agent's possible actions, and is a space of 'internal' states that are private to the agent.

Keeping with the Figure 1, note that in the following the and are functions of (continuous) time . The generative model is the specification of the following density functions:

These density functions determine the factors of a "joint model", which represents the complete specification of the generative model, and which can be written as

.

Bayes' rule then determines the "posterior density" , which expresses a probabilistically optimal belief about the external state given the preceding state and the agent's actions, sensory signals, and internal states. Since computing is computationally intractable, the free energy principle asserts the existence of a "variational density" , where is an approximation to . One then defines the free energy as

and defines action and perception as the joint optimization problem

where the internal states are typically taken to encode the parameters of the 'variational' density and hence the agent's "best guess" about the posterior belief over . Note that the free energy is also an upper bound on a measure of the agent's (marginal, or average) sensory surprise, and hence free energy minimization is often motivated by the minimization of surprise.

Free energy minimisation

Free energy minimisation and self-organisation

Free energy minimisation has been proposed as a hallmark of self-organising systems when cast as random dynamical systems. [30] This formulation rests on a Markov blanket (comprising action and sensory states) that separates internal and external states. If internal states and action minimise free energy, then they place an upper bound on the entropy of sensory states:

This is because – under ergodic assumptions – the long-term average of surprise is entropy. This bound resists a natural tendency to disorder – of the sort associated with the second law of thermodynamics and the fluctuation theorem. However, formulating a unifying principle for the life sciences in terms of concepts from statistical physics, such as random dynamical system, non-equilibrium steady state and ergodicity, places substantial constraints on the theoretical and empirical study of biological systems with the risk of obscuring all features that make biological systems interesting kinds of self-organizing systems. [31]

Free energy minimisation and Bayesian inference

All Bayesian inference can be cast in terms of free energy minimisation [32] [ failed verification ]. When free energy is minimised with respect to internal states, the Kullback–Leibler divergence between the variational and posterior density over hidden states is minimised. This corresponds to approximate Bayesian inference – when the form of the variational density is fixed – and exact Bayesian inference otherwise. Free energy minimisation therefore provides a generic description of Bayesian inference and filtering (e.g., Kalman filtering). It is also used in Bayesian model selection, where free energy can be usefully decomposed into complexity and accuracy:

Models with minimum free energy provide an accurate explanation of data, under complexity costs (c.f., Occam's razor and more formal treatments of computational costs [33] ). Here, complexity is the divergence between the variational density and prior beliefs about hidden states (i.e., the effective degrees of freedom used to explain the data).

Free energy minimisation and thermodynamics

Variational free energy is an information-theoretic functional and is distinct from thermodynamic (Helmholtz) free energy. [34] However, the complexity term of variational free energy shares the same fixed point as Helmholtz free energy (under the assumption the system is thermodynamically closed but not isolated). This is because if sensory perturbations are suspended (for a suitably long period of time), complexity is minimised (because accuracy can be neglected). At this point, the system is at equilibrium and internal states minimise Helmholtz free energy, by the principle of minimum energy. [35]

Free energy minimisation and information theory

Free energy minimisation is equivalent to maximising the mutual information between sensory states and internal states that parameterise the variational density (for a fixed entropy variational density). This relates free energy minimization to the principle of minimum redundancy. [36] [12]

Free energy minimisation in neuroscience

Free energy minimisation provides a useful way to formulate normative (Bayes optimal) models of neuronal inference and learning under uncertainty [37] and therefore subscribes to the Bayesian brain hypothesis. [38] The neuronal processes described by free energy minimisation depend on the nature of hidden states: that can comprise time-dependent variables, time-invariant parameters and the precision (inverse variance or temperature) of random fluctuations. Minimising variables, parameters, and precision correspond to inference, learning, and the encoding of uncertainty, respectively.

Perceptual inference and categorisation

Free energy minimisation formalises the notion of unconscious inference in perception [7] [9] and provides a normative (Bayesian) theory of neuronal processing. The associated process theory of neuronal dynamics is based on minimising free energy through gradient descent. This corresponds to generalised Bayesian filtering (where ~ denotes a variable in generalised coordinates of motion and is a derivative matrix operator): [39]

Usually, the generative models that define free energy are non-linear and hierarchical (like cortical hierarchies in the brain). Special cases of generalised filtering include Kalman filtering, which is formally equivalent to predictive coding [40] – a popular metaphor for message passing in the brain. Under hierarchical models, predictive coding involves the recurrent exchange of ascending (bottom-up) prediction errors and descending (top-down) predictions [41] that is consistent with the anatomy and physiology of sensory [42] and motor systems. [43]

Perceptual learning and memory

In predictive coding, optimising model parameters through a gradient descent on the time integral of free energy (free action) reduces to associative or Hebbian plasticity and is associated with synaptic plasticity in the brain.

Perceptual precision, attention and salience

Optimizing the precision parameters corresponds to optimizing the gain of prediction errors (c.f., Kalman gain). In neuronally plausible implementations of predictive coding, [41] this corresponds to optimizing the excitability of superficial pyramidal cells and has been interpreted in terms of attentional gain. [44]

Simulation of the results achieved from a selective attention task carried out by the Bayesian reformulation of the SAIM entitled PE-SAIM in multiple objects environment. The graphs show the time course of the activation for the FOA and the two template units in the Knowledge Network. PESAIM.jpg
Simulation of the results achieved from a selective attention task carried out by the Bayesian reformulation of the SAIM entitled PE-SAIM in multiple objects environment. The graphs show the time course of the activation for the FOA and the two template units in the Knowledge Network.

With regard to the top-down vs. bottom-up controversy, which has been addressed as a major open problem of attention, a computational model has succeeded in illustrating the circular nature of the interplay between top-down and bottom-up mechanisms. Using an established emergent model of attention, namely SAIM, the authors proposed a model called PE-SAIM, which, in contrast to the standard version, approaches selective attention from a top-down position. The model takes into account the transmission of prediction errors to the same level or a level above, in order to minimise the energy function that indicates the difference between the data and its cause, or, in other words, between the generative model and the posterior. To increase validity, they also incorporated neural competition between stimuli into their model. A notable feature of this model is the reformulation of the free energy function only in terms of prediction errors during task performance:

where is the total energy function of the neural networks entail, and is the prediction error between the generative model (prior) and posterior changing over time. [45] Comparing the two models reveals a notable similarity between their respective results while also highlighting a remarkable discrepancy, whereby – in the standard version of the SAIM – the model's focus is mainly upon the excitatory connections, whereas in the PE-SAIM, the inhibitory connections are leveraged to make an inference. The model has also proved to be fit to predict the EEG and fMRI data drawn from human experiments with high precision. In the same vein, Yahya et al. also applied the free energy principle to propose a computational model for template matching in covert selective visual attention that mostly relies on SAIM. [46] According to this study, the total free energy of the whole state-space is reached by inserting top-down signals in the original neural networks, whereby we derive a dynamical system comprising both feed-forward and backward prediction error.

Active inference

When gradient descent is applied to action , motor control can be understood in terms of classical reflex arcs that are engaged by descending (corticospinal) predictions. This provides a formalism that generalizes the equilibrium point solution – to the degrees of freedom problem [47] – to movement trajectories.

Active inference and optimal control

Active inference is related to optimal control by replacing value or cost-to-go functions with prior beliefs about state transitions or flow. [48] This exploits the close connection between Bayesian filtering and the solution to the Bellman equation. However, active inference starts with (priors over) flow that are specified with scalar and vector value functions of state space (c.f., the Helmholtz decomposition). Here, is the amplitude of random fluctuations and cost is . The priors over flow induce a prior over states that is the solution to the appropriate forward Kolmogorov equations. [49] In contrast, optimal control optimises the flow, given a cost function, under the assumption that (i.e., the flow is curl free or has detailed balance). Usually, this entails solving backward Kolmogorov equations. [50]

Active inference and optimal decision (game) theory

Optimal decision problems (usually formulated as partially observable Markov decision processes) are treated within active inference by absorbing utility functions into prior beliefs. In this setting, states that have a high utility (low cost) are states an agent expects to occupy. By equipping the generative model with hidden states that model control, policies (control sequences) that minimise variational free energy lead to high utility states. [51]

Neurobiologically, neuromodulators such as dopamine are considered to report the precision of prediction errors by modulating the gain of principal cells encoding prediction error. [52] This is closely related to – but formally distinct from – the role of dopamine in reporting prediction errors per se [53] and related computational accounts. [54]

Active inference and cognitive neuroscience

Active inference has been used to address a range of issues in cognitive neuroscience, brain function and neuropsychiatry, including action observation, [55] mirror neurons, [56] saccades and visual search, [57] [58] eye movements, [59] sleep, [60] illusions, [61] attention, [44] action selection, [52] consciousness, [62] [63] hysteria [64] and psychosis. [65] Explanations of action in active inference often depend on the idea that the brain has 'stubborn predictions' that it cannot update, leading to actions that cause these predictions to come true. [66]

See also

Related Research Articles

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Scanning tunneling microscope</span> Instrument able to image surfaces at the atomic level by exploiting quantum tunneling effects

A scanning tunneling microscope (STM) is a type of scanning probe microscope used for imaging surfaces at the atomic level. Its development in 1981 earned its inventors, Gerd Binnig and Heinrich Rohrer, then at IBM Zürich, the Nobel Prize in Physics in 1986. STM senses the surface by using an extremely sharp conducting tip that can distinguish features smaller than 0.1 nm with a 0.01 nm (10 pm) depth resolution. This means that individual atoms can routinely be imaged and manipulated. Most scanning tunneling microscopes are built for use in ultra-high vacuum at temperatures approaching absolute zero, but variants exist for studies in air, water and other environments, and for temperatures over 1000 °C.

In particle physics, the Dirac equation is a relativistic wave equation derived by British physicist Paul Dirac in 1928. In its free form, or including electromagnetic interactions, it describes all spin-1/2 massive particles, called "Dirac particles", such as electrons and quarks for which parity is a symmetry. It is consistent with both the principles of quantum mechanics and the theory of special relativity, and was the first theory to account fully for special relativity in the context of quantum mechanics. It was validated by accounting for the fine structure of the hydrogen spectrum in a completely rigorous way. It has become vital in the building of the Standard Model.

The Klein–Gordon equation is a relativistic wave equation, related to the Schrödinger equation. It is second-order in space and time and manifestly Lorentz-covariant. It is a differential equation version of the relativistic energy–momentum relation .

Belief propagation, also known as sum–product message passing, is a message-passing algorithm for performing inference on graphical models, such as Bayesian networks and Markov random fields. It calculates the marginal distribution for each unobserved node, conditional on any observed nodes. Belief propagation is commonly used in artificial intelligence and information theory, and has demonstrated empirical success in numerous applications, including low-density parity-check codes, turbo codes, free energy approximation, and satisfiability.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Franck–Condon principle</span> Quantum chemistry rule regarding vibronic transitions

The Franck-Condon Principle describes the intensities of vibronic transitions, or the absorption or emission of a photon. It states that when a molecule is undergoing an electronic transition, such as ionization, the nuclear configuration of the molecule experiences no significant change.

The Thirring model is an exactly solvable quantum field theory which describes the self-interactions of a Dirac field in (1+1) dimensions.

The Gross–Pitaevskii equation describes the ground state of a quantum system of identical bosons using the Hartree–Fock approximation and the pseudopotential interaction model.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Bethe–Salpeter equation</span> Equation for two-body bound states

The Bethe–Salpeter equation is an integral equation, the solution of which describes the structure of a relativistic two-body (particles) bound state in a covariant formalism quantum field theory (QFT). The equation was first published in 1950 at the end of a paper by Yoichiro Nambu, but without derivation.

Frequentist inference is a type of statistical inference based in frequentist probability, which treats “probability” in equivalent terms to “frequency” and draws conclusions from sample-data by means of emphasizing the frequency or proportion of findings in the data. Frequentist inference underlies frequentist statistics, in which the well-established methodologies of statistical hypothesis testing and confidence intervals are founded.

Newton–Cartan theory is a geometrical re-formulation, as well as a generalization, of Newtonian gravity first introduced by Élie Cartan and Kurt Friedrichs and later developed by G. Dautcourt, W. G. Dixon, P. Havas, H. Künzle, Andrzej Trautman, and others. In this re-formulation, the structural similarities between Newton's theory and Albert Einstein's general theory of relativity are readily seen, and it has been used by Cartan and Friedrichs to give a rigorous formulation of the way in which Newtonian gravity can be seen as a specific limit of general relativity, and by Jürgen Ehlers to extend this correspondence to specific solutions of general relativity.

In physics, relativistic quantum mechanics (RQM) is any Poincaré covariant formulation of quantum mechanics (QM). This theory is applicable to massive particles propagating at all velocities up to those comparable to the speed of light c, and can accommodate massless particles. The theory has application in high energy physics, particle physics and accelerator physics, as well as atomic physics, chemistry and condensed matter physics. Non-relativistic quantum mechanics refers to the mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics applied in the context of Galilean relativity, more specifically quantizing the equations of classical mechanics by replacing dynamical variables by operators. Relativistic quantum mechanics (RQM) is quantum mechanics applied with special relativity. Although the earlier formulations, like the Schrödinger picture and Heisenberg picture were originally formulated in a non-relativistic background, a few of them also work with special relativity.

Bayesian approaches to brain function investigate the capacity of the nervous system to operate in situations of uncertainty in a fashion that is close to the optimal prescribed by Bayesian statistics. This term is used in behavioural sciences and neuroscience and studies associated with this term often strive to explain the brain's cognitive abilities based on statistical principles. It is frequently assumed that the nervous system maintains internal probabilistic models that are updated by neural processing of sensory information using methods approximating those of Bayesian probability.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Bivariate von Mises distribution</span> Probability distribution on a torus

In probability theory and statistics, the bivariate von Mises distribution is a probability distribution describing values on a torus. It may be thought of as an analogue on the torus of the bivariate normal distribution. The distribution belongs to the field of directional statistics. The general bivariate von Mises distribution was first proposed by Kanti Mardia in 1975. One of its variants is today used in the field of bioinformatics to formulate a probabilistic model of protein structure in atomic detail, such as backbone-dependent rotamer libraries.

Karl John Friston FRS FMedSci FRSB is a British neuroscientist and theoretician at University College London. He is an authority on brain imaging and theoretical neuroscience, especially the use of physics-inspired statistical methods to model neuroimaging data and other random dynamical systems. Friston is a key architect of the free energy principle and active inference. In imaging neuroscience he is best known for statistical parametric mapping and dynamic causal modelling. Friston also acts as a scientific advisor to numerous groups in industry.

In probability theory and statistics, the normal-inverse-Wishart distribution is a multivariate four-parameter family of continuous probability distributions. It is the conjugate prior of a multivariate normal distribution with unknown mean and covariance matrix.

Generalized filtering is a generic Bayesian filtering scheme for nonlinear state-space models. It is based on a variational principle of least action, formulated in generalized coordinates of motion. Note that "generalized coordinates of motion" are related to—but distinct from—generalized coordinates as used in (multibody) dynamical systems analysis. Generalized filtering furnishes posterior densities over hidden states generating observed data using a generalized gradient descent on variational free energy, under the Laplace assumption. Unlike classical filtering, generalized filtering eschews Markovian assumptions about random fluctuations. Furthermore, it operates online, assimilating data to approximate the posterior density over unknown quantities, without the need for a backward pass. Special cases include variational filtering, dynamic expectation maximization and generalized predictive coding.

In neuroscience, predictive coding is a theory of brain function which postulates that the brain is constantly generating and updating a "mental model" of the environment. According to the theory, such a mental model is used to predict input signals from the senses that are then compared with the actual input signals from those senses. Predictive coding is member of a wider set of theories that follow the Bayesian brain hypothesis.

Dynamic causal modeling (DCM) is a framework for specifying models, fitting them to data and comparing their evidence using Bayesian model comparison. It uses nonlinear state-space models in continuous time, specified using stochastic or ordinary differential equations. DCM was initially developed for testing hypotheses about neural dynamics. In this setting, differential equations describe the interaction of neural populations, which directly or indirectly give rise to functional neuroimaging data e.g., functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI), magnetoencephalography (MEG) or electroencephalography (EEG). Parameters in these models quantify the directed influences or effective connectivity among neuronal populations, which are estimated from the data using Bayesian statistical methods.

Bayesian model reduction is a method for computing the evidence and posterior over the parameters of Bayesian models that differ in their priors. A full model is fitted to data using standard approaches. Hypotheses are then tested by defining one or more 'reduced' models with alternative priors, which usually – in the limit – switch off certain parameters. The evidence and parameters of the reduced models can then be computed from the evidence and estimated (posterior) parameters of the full model using Bayesian model reduction. If the priors and posteriors are normally distributed, then there is an analytic solution which can be computed rapidly. This has multiple scientific and engineering applications: these include scoring the evidence for large numbers of models very quickly and facilitating the estimation of hierarchical models.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Rosalyn Moran</span> Irish and British neuroscientist and computational psychiatrist

Rosalyn J. Moran is an Irish and British neuroscientist and computational psychiatrist. She is deputy director of the King's College London Institute for Artificial Intelligence. Her research looks to understand neural algorithms through brain connectivity.

References

  1. Bruineberg, Jelle; Kiverstein, Julian; Rietveld, Erik (2018). "The anticipating brain is not a scientist: the free-energy principle from an ecological-enactive perspective". Synthese. 195 (6): 2417–2444. doi:10.1007/s11229-016-1239-1. PMC   6438652 . PMID   30996493.
  2. Friston, Karl (2010). "The free-energy principle: a unified brain theory?". Nature Reviews Neuroscience. 11 (2): 127–138. doi:10.1038/nrn2787. PMID   20068583. S2CID   5053247 . Retrieved July 9, 2023.
  3. Friston, Karl; Kilner, James; Harrison, Lee (2006). "A free energy principle for the brain" (PDF). Journal of Physiology-Paris. 100 (1–3): 70–87. doi:10.1016/j.jphysparis.2006.10.001. PMID   17097864. S2CID   637885.
  4. 1 2 Shaun Raviv: The Genius Neuroscientist Who Might Hold the Key to True AI. In: Wired, 13. November 2018
  5. Friston, Karl (2018). "Of woodlice and men: A Bayesian account of cognition, life and consciousness. An interview with Karl Friston (by Martin Fortier & Daniel Friedman)". ALIUS Bulletin. 2: 17–43.
  6. Friston, Karl (2022). Active Inference: The Free Energy Principle in Mind, Brain, and Behavior. MIT Press. ISBN   9780262045353.
  7. 1 2 Helmholtz, H. (1866/1962). Concerning the perceptions in general. In Treatise on physiological optics (J. Southall, Trans., 3rd ed., Vol. III). New York: Dover. Available at https://web.archive.org/web/20180320133752/http://poseidon.sunyopt.edu/BackusLab/Helmholtz/
  8. Gregory, R. L. (1980-07-08). "Perceptions as hypotheses". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. B, Biological Sciences. 290 (1038): 181–197. Bibcode:1980RSPTB.290..181G. doi:10.1098/rstb.1980.0090. JSTOR   2395424. PMID   6106237.
  9. 1 2 Dayan, Peter; Hinton, Geoffrey E.; Neal, Radford M.; Zemel, Richard S. (1995). "The Helmholtz Machine" (PDF). Neural Computation. 7 (5): 889–904. doi:10.1162/neco.1995.7.5.889. hdl: 21.11116/0000-0002-D6D3-E . PMID   7584891. S2CID   1890561.
  10. Beal, M. J. (2003). Variational Algorithms for Approximate Bayesian Inference. Ph.D. Thesis, University College London.
  11. Sakthivadivel, Dalton (2022). "Towards a Geometry and Analysis for Bayesian Mechanics". arXiv: 2204.11900 [math-ph].
  12. 1 2 Ramstead, Maxwell; Sakthivadivel, Dalton; Heins, Conor; Koudahl, Magnus; Millidge, Beren; Da Costa, Lancelot; Klein, Brennan; Friston, Karl (2023). "On Bayesian mechanics: A physics of and by beliefs". Interface Focus. 13 (3). arXiv: 2205.11543 . doi:10.1098/rsfs.2022.0029. PMC   10198254 . PMID   37213925. S2CID   249017997.
  13. Conant, Roger C.; Ross Ashby, W. (1970). "Every good regulator of a system must be a model of that system". International Journal of Systems Science. 1 (2): 89–97. doi:10.1080/00207727008920220.
  14. Kauffman, S. (1993). The Origins of Order: Self-Organization and Selection in Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  15. Nicolis, G., & Prigogine, I. (1977). Self-organization in non-equilibrium systems. New York: John Wiley.
  16. Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F. (1980). Autopoiesis: the organization of the living. In V. F. Maturana HR (Ed.), Autopoiesis and Cognition. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Reidel.
  17. Nikolić, Danko (2015). "Practopoiesis: Or how life fosters a mind". Journal of Theoretical Biology. 373: 40–61. arXiv: 1402.5332 . Bibcode:2015JThBi.373...40N. doi:10.1016/j.jtbi.2015.03.003. PMID   25791287. S2CID   12680941.
  18. Haken, H. (1983). Synergetics: An introduction. Non-equilibrium phase transition and self-organisation in physics, chemistry and biology (3rd ed.). Berlin: Springer Verlag.
  19. Jaynes, E. T. (1957). "Information Theory and Statistical Mechanics" (PDF). Physical Review. 106 (4): 620–630. Bibcode:1957PhRv..106..620J. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.106.620. S2CID   17870175.
  20. Veissière, Samuel P. L.; Constant, Axel; Ramstead, Maxwell J. D.; Friston, Karl J.; Kirmayer, Laurence J. (2020). "Thinking through other minds: A variational approach to cognition and culture". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 43: e90. doi:10.1017/S0140525X19001213. ISSN   0140-525X. PMID   31142395. S2CID   169038428.
  21. Ramstead, Maxwell J. D.; Constant, Axel; Badcock, Paul B.; Friston, Karl J. (2019-12-01). "Variational ecology and the physics of sentient systems". Physics of Life Reviews. Physics of Mind. 31: 188–205. Bibcode:2019PhLRv..31..188R. doi:10.1016/j.plrev.2018.12.002. ISSN   1571-0645. PMC   6941227 . PMID   30655223.
  22. Albarracin, Mahault; Demekas, Daphne; Ramstead, Maxwell J. D.; Heins, Conor (April 2022). "Epistemic Communities under Active Inference". Entropy. 24 (4): 476. Bibcode:2022Entrp..24..476A. doi: 10.3390/e24040476 . ISSN   1099-4300. PMC   9027706 . PMID   35455140.
  23. Albarracin, Mahault; Constant, Axel; Friston, Karl J.; Ramstead, Maxwell James D. (2021). "A Variational Approach to Scripts". Frontiers in Psychology. 12: 585493. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2021.585493 . ISSN   1664-1078. PMC   8329037 . PMID   34354621.
  24. Friston, Karl J.; Parr, Thomas; Yufik, Yan; Sajid, Noor; Price, Catherine J.; Holmes, Emma (2020-11-01). "Generative models, linguistic communication and active inference". Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews. 118: 42–64. doi:10.1016/j.neubiorev.2020.07.005. ISSN   0149-7634. PMC   7758713 . PMID   32687883.
  25. Tison, Remi; Poirier, Pierre (2021-10-02). "Communication as Socially Extended Active Inference: An Ecological Approach to Communicative Behavior". Ecological Psychology. 33 (3–4): 197–235. doi:10.1080/10407413.2021.1965480. ISSN   1040-7413. S2CID   238703201.
  26. Friston, Karl J.; Frith, Christopher D. (2015-07-01). "Active inference, communication and hermeneutics". Cortex. Special issue: Prediction in speech and language processing. 68: 129–143. doi:10.1016/j.cortex.2015.03.025. ISSN   0010-9452. PMC   4502445 . PMID   25957007.
  27. Kerusauskaite, Skaiste (2023-06-01). "Role of Culture in Meaning Making: Bridging Semiotic Cultural Psychology and Active Inference". Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science. 57 (2): 432–443. doi:10.1007/s12124-022-09744-x. ISSN   1936-3567. PMID   36585542. S2CID   255366405.
  28. García, Adolfo M.; Ibáñez, Agustín (2022-11-14). The Routledge Handbook of Semiosis and the Brain. Taylor & Francis. ISBN   978-1-000-72877-4.
  29. Bottemanne, Hugo; Friston, Karl J. (2021-12-01). "An active inference account of protective behaviours during the COVID-19 pandemic". Cognitive, Affective, & Behavioral Neuroscience. 21 (6): 1117–1129. doi:10.3758/s13415-021-00947-0. ISSN   1531-135X. PMC   8518276 . PMID   34652601.
  30. Crauel, Hans; Flandoli, Franco (1994). "Attractors for random dynamical systems". Probability Theory and Related Fields. 100 (3): 365–393. doi: 10.1007/BF01193705 . S2CID   122609512.
  31. Colombo, Matteo; Palacios, Patricia (2021). "Non-equilibrium thermodynamics and the free energy principle in biology". Biology & Philosophy. 36 (5). doi: 10.1007/s10539-021-09818-x . S2CID   235803361.
  32. Roweis, Sam; Ghahramani, Zoubin (1999). "A Unifying Review of Linear Gaussian Models" (PDF). Neural Computation. 11 (2): 305–345. doi:10.1162/089976699300016674. PMID   9950734. S2CID   2590898.
  33. Ortega, Pedro A.; Braun, Daniel A. (2013). "Thermodynamics as a theory of decision-making with information-processing costs". Proceedings of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences. 469 (2153). arXiv: 1204.6481 . Bibcode:2013RSPSA.46920683O. doi:10.1098/rspa.2012.0683. S2CID   28080508.
  34. Evans, Denis J. (2003). "A non-equilibrium free energy theorem for deterministic systems" (PDF). Molecular Physics. 101 (10): 1551–1554. Bibcode:2003MolPh.101.1551E. doi:10.1080/0026897031000085173. S2CID   15129000.
  35. Jarzynski, C. (1997). "Nonequilibrium Equality for Free Energy Differences". Physical Review Letters. 78 (14): 2690–2693. arXiv: cond-mat/9610209 . Bibcode:1997PhRvL..78.2690J. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.78.2690. S2CID   16112025.
  36. Sakthivadivel, Dalton (2022). "Towards a Geometry and Analysis for Bayesian Mechanics". arXiv: 2204.11900 [math-ph].
  37. Friston, Karl (2010). "The free-energy principle: A unified brain theory?" (PDF). Nature Reviews Neuroscience. 11 (2): 127–138. doi:10.1038/nrn2787. PMID   20068583. S2CID   5053247.
  38. Knill, David C.; Pouget, Alexandre (2004). "The Bayesian brain: The role of uncertainty in neural coding and computation" (PDF). Trends in Neurosciences. 27 (12): 712–719. doi:10.1016/j.tins.2004.10.007. PMID   15541511. S2CID   9870936. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2016-03-04. Retrieved 2013-05-31.
  39. Friston, Karl; Stephan, Klaas; Li, Baojuan; Daunizeau, Jean (2010). "Generalised Filtering". Mathematical Problems in Engineering. 2010: 1–34. doi: 10.1155/2010/621670 .
  40. Knill, David C.; Pouget, Alexandre (2004). "The Bayesian brain: The role of uncertainty in neural coding and computation" (PDF). Trends in Neurosciences. 27 (12): 712–719. doi:10.1016/j.tins.2004.10.007. PMID   15541511. S2CID   9870936.
  41. 1 2 Mumford, D. (1992). "On the computational architecture of the neocortex" (PDF). Biological Cybernetics. 66 (3): 241–251. doi:10.1007/BF00198477. PMID   1540675. S2CID   14303625.
  42. Bastos, Andre M.; Usrey, W. Martin; Adams, Rick A.; Mangun, George R.; Fries, Pascal; Friston, Karl J. (2012). "Canonical Microcircuits for Predictive Coding". Neuron. 76 (4): 695–711. doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2012.10.038. PMC   3777738 . PMID   23177956.
  43. Adams, Rick A.; Shipp, Stewart; Friston, Karl J. (2013). "Predictions not commands: Active inference in the motor system". Brain Structure and Function. 218 (3): 611–643. doi:10.1007/s00429-012-0475-5. PMC   3637647 . PMID   23129312.
  44. 1 2 Friston, Karl J.; Feldman, Harriet (2010). "Attention, Uncertainty, and Free-Energy". Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. 4: 215. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2010.00215 . PMC   3001758 . PMID   21160551.
  45. Abadi, Alireza Khatoon; Yahya, Keyvan; Amini, Massoud; Friston, Karl; Heinke, Dietmar (2019). "Excitatory versus inhibitory feedback in Bayesian formulations of scene construction". Journal of the Royal Society Interface. 16 (154). doi:10.1098/rsif.2018.0344. PMC   6544897 . PMID   31039693.
  46. "12th Biannual Conference of the German Cognitive Science Society (KogWis 2014)". Cognitive Processing. 15: 107. 2014. doi: 10.1007/s10339-013-0597-6 . S2CID   10121398.
  47. Feldman, Anatol G.; Levin, Mindy F. (1995). "The origin and use of positional frames of reference in motor control" (PDF). Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 18 (4): 723–744. doi:10.1017/S0140525X0004070X. S2CID   145164477. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2014-03-29. Retrieved 2013-05-31.
  48. Friston, Karl (2011). "What is Optimal about Motor Control?" (PDF). Neuron. 72 (3): 488–498. doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2011.10.018. PMID   22078508. S2CID   13912462.
  49. Friston, Karl; Ao, Ping (2012). "Free Energy, Value, and Attractors". Computational and Mathematical Methods in Medicine. 2012: 1–27. doi: 10.1155/2012/937860 . PMC   3249597 . PMID   22229042.
  50. Kappen, H. J. (2005). "Path integrals and symmetry breaking for optimal control theory". Journal of Statistical Mechanics: Theory and Experiment. 2005 (11): P11011. arXiv: physics/0505066 . Bibcode:2005JSMTE..11..011K. doi:10.1088/1742-5468/2005/11/P11011. S2CID   87027.
  51. Friston, Karl; Samothrakis, Spyridon; Montague, Read (2012). "Active inference and agency: Optimal control without cost functions". Biological Cybernetics. 106 (8–9): 523–541. doi: 10.1007/s00422-012-0512-8 . hdl: 10919/78836 . PMID   22864468.
  52. 1 2 Friston, Karl J.; Shiner, Tamara; Fitzgerald, Thomas; Galea, Joseph M.; Adams, Rick; Brown, Harriet; Dolan, Raymond J.; Moran, Rosalyn; Stephan, Klaas Enno; Bestmann, Sven (2012). "Dopamine, Affordance and Active Inference". PLOS Computational Biology. 8 (1): e1002327. Bibcode:2012PLSCB...8E2327F. doi: 10.1371/journal.pcbi.1002327 . PMC   3252266 . PMID   22241972.
  53. Fiorillo, Christopher D.; Tobler, Philippe N.; Schultz, Wolfram (2003). "Discrete Coding of Reward Probability and Uncertainty by Dopamine Neurons" (PDF). Science. 299 (5614): 1898–1902. Bibcode:2003Sci...299.1898F. doi:10.1126/science.1077349. PMID   12649484. S2CID   2363255. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2016-03-04. Retrieved 2013-05-31.
  54. Frank, Michael J. (2005). "Dynamic Dopamine Modulation in the Basal Ganglia: A Neurocomputational Account of Cognitive Deficits in Medicated and Nonmedicated Parkinsonism" (PDF). Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience. 17 (1): 51–72. doi:10.1162/0898929052880093. PMID   15701239. S2CID   7414727.
  55. Friston, Karl; Mattout, Jérémie; Kilner, James (2011). "Action understanding and active inference" (PDF). Biological Cybernetics. 104 (1–2): 137–160. doi:10.1007/s00422-011-0424-z. PMC   3491875 . PMID   21327826.
  56. Kilner, James M.; Friston, Karl J.; Frith, Chris D. (2007). "Predictive coding: An account of the mirror neuron system" (PDF). Cognitive Processing. 8 (3): 159–166. doi:10.1007/s10339-007-0170-2. PMC   2649419 . PMID   17429704.
  57. Friston, Karl; Adams, Rick A.; Perrinet, Laurent; Breakspear, Michael (2012). "Perceptions as Hypotheses: Saccades as Experiments". Frontiers in Psychology. 3: 151. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00151 . PMC   3361132 . PMID   22654776.
  58. Mirza, M. Berk; Adams, Rick A.; Mathys, Christoph; Friston, Karl J. (2018). "Human visual exploration reduces uncertainty about the sensed world". PLOS ONE. 13 (1): e0190429. Bibcode:2018PLoSO..1390429M. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0190429 . PMC   5755757 . PMID   29304087.
  59. Perrinet, Laurent U.; Adams, Rick A.; Friston, Karl J. (2014). "Active inference, eye movements and oculomotor delays". Biological Cybernetics. 108 (6): 777–801. doi:10.1007/s00422-014-0620-8. PMC   4250571 . PMID   25128318.
  60. Hobson, J.A.; Friston, K.J. (2012). "Waking and dreaming consciousness: Neurobiological and functional considerations". Progress in Neurobiology. 98 (1): 82–98. doi: 10.1016/j.pneurobio.2012.05.003 . PMC   3389346 . PMID   22609044.
  61. Brown, Harriet; Friston, Karl J. (2012). "Free-Energy and Illusions: The Cornsweet Effect". Frontiers in Psychology. 3: 43. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00043 . PMC   3289982 . PMID   22393327.
  62. Rudrauf, David; Bennequin, Daniel; Granic, Isabela; Landini, Gregory; Friston, Karl; Williford, Kenneth (2017-09-07). "A mathematical model of embodied consciousness" (PDF). Journal of Theoretical Biology. 428: 106–131. Bibcode:2017JThBi.428..106R. doi:10.1016/j.jtbi.2017.05.032. PMID   28554611.
  63. K, Williford; D, Bennequin; K, Friston; D, Rudrauf (2018-12-17). "The Projective Consciousness Model and Phenomenal Selfhood". Frontiers in Psychology. 9: 2571. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.02571 . PMC   6304424 . PMID   30618988.
  64. Edwards, M. J.; Adams, R. A.; Brown, H.; Parees, I.; Friston, K. J. (2012). "A Bayesian account of 'hysteria'" (PDF). Brain. 135 (11): 3495–3512. doi:10.1093/brain/aws129. PMC   3501967 . PMID   22641838.
  65. Adams, Rick A.; Perrinet, Laurent U.; Friston, Karl (2012). "Smooth Pursuit and Visual Occlusion: Active Inference and Oculomotor Control in Schizophrenia". PLOS ONE. 7 (10): e47502. Bibcode:2012PLoSO...747502A. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0047502 . PMC   3482214 . PMID   23110076.
  66. Yon, Daniel; Lange, Floris P. de; Press, Clare (2019-01-01). "The Predictive Brain as a Stubborn Scientist". Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 23 (1): 6–8. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2018.10.003. PMID   30429054. S2CID   53280000.