Integrated information theory

Last updated

Phi; the symbol used for integrated information Phi-iit-symbol.svg
Phi; the symbol used for integrated information

Integrated information theory (IIT) proposes a mathematical model for the consciousness of a system. It comprises a framework ultimately intended to explain why some physical systems (such as human brains) are conscious, [1] and to be capable of providing a concrete inference about whether any physical system is conscious, to what degree, and what particular experience it is having; why they feel the particular way they do in particular states (e.g. why our visual field appears extended when we gaze out at the night sky), [2] and what it would take for other physical systems to be conscious (Are other animals conscious? Might the whole universe be?). [3]

Contents

According to IIT, a system's consciousness (what it is like subjectively) is conjectured to be identical to its causal properties (what it is like objectively). Therefore it should be possible to account for the conscious experience of a physical system by unfolding its complete causal powers. [4]

IIT was proposed by neuroscientist Giulio Tononi in 2004. [5] Despite significant interest, IIT remains controversial and has been widely criticized, with some claiming that it is unfalsifiable pseudoscience. [6]

Overview

Relationship to the "hard problem of consciousness"

David Chalmers has argued that any attempt to explain consciousness in purely physical terms (i.e., to start with the laws of physics as they are currently formulated and derive the necessary and inevitable existence of consciousness) eventually runs into the so-called "hard problem". Rather than try to start from physical principles and arrive at consciousness, IIT "starts with consciousness" (accepts the existence of our own consciousness as certain) and reasons about the properties that a postulated physical substrate would need to have in order to account for it. The ability to perform this jump from phenomenology to mechanism rests on IIT's assumption that if the formal properties of a conscious experience can be fully accounted for by an underlying physical system, then the properties of the physical system must be constrained by the properties of the experience. The limitations on the physical system for consciousness to exist are unknown and consciousness may exist on a spectrum, as implied by studies involving split-brain patients [7] and conscious patients with large amounts of brain matter missing. [8]

Specifically, IIT moves from phenomenology to mechanism by attempting to identify the essential properties of conscious experience (dubbed "axioms") and, from there, the essential properties of conscious physical systems (dubbed "postulates").

Mathematics: formalization of the postulates

For a complete and thorough account of the mathematical formalization of IIT this paper, [9] is the one advised.

Extensions

The calculation of even a modestly-sized system's is often computationally intractable, [9] so efforts have been made to develop heuristic or proxy measures of integrated information. For example, Masafumi Oizumi and colleagues have developed both [10] and geometric integrated information or , [11] which are practical approximations for integrated information. These are related to proxy measures developed earlier by Anil Seth and Adam Barrett. [12] However, none of these proxy measures have a mathematically proven relationship to the actual value, which complicates the interpretation of analyses that use them. They can give qualitatively different results even for very small systems. [13]

In 2021, Angus Leung and colleagues published a direct application of IIT's mathematical formalism to neural data. [14] To circumvent the computational challenges associated with larger datasets, the authors focused on neuronal population activity in the fly. The study showed that can readily be computed for smaller sets of neural data. Moreover, matching IIT's predictions, was significantly decreased when the animals underwent general anesthesia. [14]

A significant computational challenge in calculating integrated information is finding the minimum information partition of a neural system, which requires iterating through all possible network partitions. To solve this problem, Daniel Toker and Friedrich T. Sommer have shown that the spectral decomposition of the correlation matrix of a system's dynamics is a quick and robust proxy for the minimum information partition. [15]

While the algorithm [9] [16] for assessing a system's and conceptual structure is relatively straightforward, its high time complexity makes it computationally intractable for many systems of interest. [9] Heuristics and approximations can sometimes be used to provide ballpark estimates of a complex system's integrated information, but precise calculations are often impossible. These computational challenges, combined with the already difficult task of reliably and accurately assessing consciousness under experimental conditions, make testing many of the theory's predictions difficult.

Despite these challenges, researchers have attempted to use measures of information integration and differentiation to assess levels of consciousness in a variety of subjects. [17] [18] For instance, a recent study using a less computationally-intensive proxy for was able to reliably discriminate between varying levels of consciousness in wakeful, sleeping (dreaming vs. non-dreaming), anesthetized, and comatose (vegetative vs. minimally-conscious vs. locked-in) individuals. [19]

IIT also makes several predictions which fit well with existing experimental evidence, and can be used to explain some counterintuitive findings in consciousness research. [1] For example, IIT can be used to explain why some brain regions, such as the cerebellum do not appear to contribute to consciousness, despite their size and/or functional importance.

Reception

Integrated information theory has received both broad criticism and support.

Support

Neuroscientist Christof Koch, who has helped to develop later versions of the theory, has called IIT "the only really promising fundamental theory of consciousness". [20]

Neuroscientist and consciousness researcher Anil Seth is supportive of the theory, with some caveats, claiming that "conscious experiences are highly informative and always integrated."; and that "One thing that immediately follows from [IIT] is that you have a nice post hoc explanation for certain things we know about consciousness.". But he also claims "the parts of IIT that I find less promising are where it claims that integrated information actually is consciousness — that there's an identity between the two.", [21] and has criticized the panpsychist extrapolations of the theory. [22]

Philosopher David Chalmers, famous for the idea of the hard problem of consciousness, has expressed some enthusiasm about IIT. According to Chalmers, IIT is a development in the right direction, whether or not it is correct. [23]

Max Tegmark has tried to address the problem of the computational complexity behind the calculations. According to Max Tegmark "the integration measure proposed by IIT is computationally infeasible to evaluate for large systems, growing super-exponentially with the system's information content." [24] As a result, Φ can only be approximated in general. However, different ways of approximating Φ provide radically different results. [25] Other works have shown that Φ can be computed in some large mean-field neural network models, although some assumptions of the theory have to be revised to capture phase transitions in these large systems. [26] [27]

Criticism

Influential philosopher John Searle has given a critique of theory saying "The theory implies panpsychism" and "The problem with panpsychism is not that it is false; it does not get up to the level of being false. It is strictly speaking meaningless because no clear notion has been given to the claim.". [28] However, whether or not a theory has panpsychist implications (that all or most of what exists physically must be, be part of something that is, or be composed of parts that are, conscious) has no bearing on the scientific validity of the theory. Searle's take has also been countered by other philosophers, for misunderstanding and misrepresenting a theory that is actually resonant with his own ideas. [29]

Theoretical computer scientist Scott Aaronson has criticized IIT by demonstrating through its own formulation that an inactive series of logic gates, arranged in the correct way, would not only be conscious but be "unboundedly more conscious than humans are." [30] Tononi himself agrees with the assessment and argues that according to IIT, an even simpler arrangement of inactive logic gates, if large enough, would also be conscious. However he further argues that this is a strength of IIT rather than a weakness, because that's exactly the sort of cytoarchitecture followed by large portions of the cerebral cortex, [31] [32] specially at the back of the brain, [2] which is the most likely neuroanatomical correlate of consciousness according to some reviews. [33]

Philosopher Tim Bayne has criticized the axiomatic foundations of the theory. [34] He concludes that "the so-called 'axioms' that Tononi et al. appeal to fail to qualify as genuine axioms".

A peer-reviewed commentary by 58 scholars involved in the scientific study of consciousness rejects these conclusions about logic gates as "mysterious and unfalsifiable claims" that should be distinguished from "empirically productive hypotheses". [35] [ clarification needed ] IIT as a scientific theory of consciousness has been criticized in the scientific literature as only able to be "either false or unscientific" by its own definitions. [36] IIT has also been denounced by other members of the consciousness field as requiring "an unscientific leap of faith", but it is not clear that this is in fact the case if the theory is properly understood. [37] The theory has also been derided for failing to answer the basic questions required of a theory of consciousness. Philosopher Adam Pautz says "As long as proponents of IIT do not address these questions, they have not put a clear theory on the table that can be evaluated as true or false." [38] Neuroscientist Michael Graziano, proponent of the competing attention schema theory, rejects IIT as pseudoscience. He claims IIT is a "magicalist theory" that has "no chance of scientific success or understanding". [39] Similarly, IIT was criticized that its claims are "not scientifically established or testable at the moment". [40]

However, while it is true that the complete analysis suggested by IIT cannot be completed at the moment for human brains, IIT has already been applied to models of visual cortex to explain why visual space feels the way it does. [2]

Neuroscientists Björn Merker, David Rudrauf and Philosopher Kenneth Williford co-authored a paper criticizing IIT on several grounds. Firstly, by not demonstrating that all members of systems which do in fact combine integration and differentiation in the formal IIT sense are conscious, systems which demonstrate high levels of integration and differentiation of information might provide the necessary conditions for consciousness but those combinations of attributes do not amount to the conditions for consciousness. Secondly that the measure, Φ, reflects efficiency of global information transfer rather than level of consciousness, and that the correlation of Φ with level of consciousness through different states of wakefulness (e.g. awake, dreaming and dreamless sleep, anesthesia, seizures and coma) actually reflect the level of efficient network interactions performed for cortical engagement. Hence Φ reflects network efficiency rather than consciousness, which would be one of the functions served by cortical network efficiency. [41]

A letter published on 15 September 2023 in the preprint repository PsyArXiv and signed by 124 scholars asserted that until IIT is empirically testable, it should be labeled pseudoscience. [42] A number of researchers defended the theory in response. [6] Regarding this letter, IIT, and what he considers a similarly unscientific theory, Assembly theory (AT), University of Cambridge and University of Oxford computer scientist Hector Zenil made criticisms based on the lack of correspondence of the methods and theory in some of the IIT research papers and the media frenzy. [43] Zenil criticized both the shallowness and misleading nature of the media coverage, including in apparently respected journals such as Nature and Science . He also criticized testing methods and evidence used by IIT proponents, noting that one test amounted to simply applying LZW compression to measure entropy rather than to indicate consciousness as proponents claimed.

Adversarial Collaboration to test GNW and IIT

In 2019, the Templeton Foundation announced funding in excess of $6,000,000 to test opposing empirical predictions of IIT and a rival theory (Global Neuronal Workspace Theory GNWT). [44] [45] The originators of both theories signed off on experimental protocols and data analyses as well as the exact conditions that satisfy if their championed theory correctly predicted the outcome or not. [46] [47] Initial results were revealed in June 2023. [48] None of GNWT's predictions passed what was agreed upon pre-registration while two out of three of IIT's predictions passed that threshold. [49]

See also

Related Research Articles

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Consciousness</span> Awareness of existence

Consciousness, at its simplest, is awareness of internal and external existence. However, its nature has led to millennia of analyses, explanations and debate by philosophers, theologians, and all of science. Opinions differ about what exactly needs to be studied or even considered consciousness. In some explanations, it is synonymous with the mind, and at other times, an aspect of mind. In the past, it was one's "inner life", the world of introspection, of private thought, imagination and volition. Today, it often includes any kind of cognition, experience, feeling or perception. It may be awareness, awareness of awareness, or self-awareness either continuously changing or not. The disparate range of research, notions and speculations raises a curiosity about whether the right questions are being asked.

<i>Consciousness Explained</i> 1991 book by Daniel Dennett

Consciousness Explained is a 1991 book by the American philosopher Daniel Dennett, in which the author offers an account of how consciousness arises from interaction of physical and cognitive processes in the brain. Dennett describes consciousness as an account of the various calculations occurring in the brain at close to the same time. He compares consciousness to an academic paper that is being developed or edited in the hands of multiple people at one time, the "multiple drafts" theory of consciousness. In this analogy, "the paper" exists even though there is no single, unified paper. When people report on their inner experiences, Dennett considers their reports to be more like theorizing than like describing. These reports may be informative, he says, but a psychologist is not to take them at face value. Dennett describes several phenomena that show that perception is more limited and less reliable than we perceive it to be.

Phi is the 21st letter of the Greek alphabet.

Computational neuroscience is a branch of neuroscience which employs mathematics, computer science, theoretical analysis and abstractions of the brain to understand the principles that govern the development, structure, physiology and cognitive abilities of the nervous system.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Panpsychism</span> View that mind is a fundamental feature of reality

In the philosophy of mind, panpsychism is the view that the mind or a mind-like aspect is a fundamental and ubiquitous feature of reality. It is also described as a theory that "the mind is a fundamental feature of the world which exists throughout the universe". It is one of the oldest philosophical theories, and has been ascribed to philosophers including Thales, Plato, Spinoza, Leibniz, William James, Alfred North Whitehead, Bertrand Russell, and Galen Strawson. In the 19th century, panpsychism was the default philosophy of mind in Western thought, but it saw a decline in the mid-20th century with the rise of logical positivism. Recent interest in the hard problem of consciousness and developments in the fields of neuroscience, psychology, and quantum mechanics have revived interest in panpsychism in the 21st century.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Hard problem of consciousness</span> Philosophical concept, first stated by David Chalmers in 1995

In philosophy of mind, the hard problem of consciousness is to explain why and how humans and other organisms have qualia, phenomenal consciousness, or subjective experiences. It is contrasted with the "easy problems" of explaining why and how physical systems give a (healthy) human being the ability to discriminate, to integrate information, and to perform behavioral functions such as watching, listening, speaking, and so forth. The easy problems are amenable to functional explanation—that is, explanations that are mechanistic or behavioral—since each physical system can be explained purely by reference to the "structure and dynamics" that underpin the phenomenon.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Christof Koch</span> American neurophysiologist

Christof Koch is a German-American neurophysiologist and computational neuroscientist best known for his work on the neural basis of consciousness. He is the president and chief scientist of the Allen Institute for Brain Science in Seattle. From 1986 until 2013, he was a professor at the California Institute of Technology.

Global workspace theory (GWT) is a framework for thinking about consciousness proposed by cognitive scientists Bernard Baars and Stan Franklin in the late 1980s. It was developed to qualitatively account for a large set of matched pairs of conscious and unconscious processes. GWT has been influential in modeling consciousness and higher-order cognition as emerging from competition and integrated flows of information across widespread, parallel neural processes.

Lawrence M. Ward is a neuroscientist and psychophysicist at the Department of Psychology at the University of British Columbia. He studied at Harvard University (AB) and Duke University, where he received his PhD in Experimental Psychology with a minor in mathematics. His current interests are cognitive neuroscience of attention and consciousness with special emphasis on EEG and MEG studies of neuronal synchronization; information transfer between brain regions underlying cognition; psychophysics, biophysics and general theory of stochastic resonance; computational studies of neuronal oscillations and synchronization; neural plasticity; nonlinear dynamical systems theory and its applications in cognitive neuroscience. He co-authored the textbook "Sensation and Perception" with Stanley Coren, and James T. Enns, which went into six editions spanning the period 1978 to 2004.

PLOS Computational Biology is a monthly peer-reviewed open access scientific journal covering computational biology. It was established in 2005 by the Public Library of Science in association with the International Society for Computational Biology (ISCB) in the same format as the previously established PLOS Biology and PLOS Medicine. The founding editor-in-chief was Philip Bourne and the current ones are Feilim Mac Gabhann and Jason Papin.

Anders Krogh is a bioinformatician at the University of Copenhagen, where he leads the university's bioinformatics center. He is known for his pioneering work on the use of hidden Markov models in bioinformatics, and is co-author of a widely used textbook in bioinformatics. In addition, he also co-authored one of the early textbooks on neural networks. His current research interests include promoter analysis, non-coding RNA, gene prediction and protein structure prediction.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Giulio Tononi</span> Neuroscientist, psychiatrist, and professor

Giulio Tononi is a neuroscientist and psychiatrist who holds the David P. White Chair in Sleep Medicine, as well as a Distinguished Chair in Consciousness Science, at the University of Wisconsin. He is best known for his Integrated Information Theory (IIT), a mathematical theory of consciousness, which he has proposed since 2004.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Neural correlates of consciousness</span> Neuronal events sufficient for a specific conscious percept

The neural correlates of consciousness (NCC) are the minimal set of neuronal events and mechanisms sufficient for the occurrence of the mental states to which they are related. Neuroscientists use empirical approaches to discover neural correlates of subjective phenomena; that is, neural changes which necessarily and regularly correlate with a specific experience. The set should be minimal because, under the materialist assumption that the brain is sufficient to give rise to any given conscious experience, the question is which of its components are necessary to produce it.

The ISCB Overton Prize is a computational biology prize awarded annually for outstanding accomplishment by a scientist in the early to mid stage of his or her career. Laureates have made significant contribution to the field of computational biology either through research, education, service, or a combination of the three.

The ISCB Accomplishment by a Senior Scientist Award is an annual prize awarded by the International Society for Computational Biology for contributions to the field of computational biology.

The Dehaene–Changeux model (DCM), also known as the global neuronal workspace, or global cognitive workspace model, is a part of Bernard Baars's global workspace model for consciousness.

ISCB Fellowship is an award granted to scientists that the International Society for Computational Biology (ISCB) judges to have made “outstanding contributions to the fields of computational biology and bioinformatics”. As of 2019, there are 76 Fellows of the ISCB including Michael Ashburner, Alex Bateman, Bonnie Berger, Steven E. Brenner, Janet Kelso, Daphne Koller, Michael Levitt, Sarah Teichmann and Shoshana Wodak. See List of Fellows of the International Society for Computational Biology for a comprehensive listing.

Posterior cortex usually means the posterior (back) part of the complete cerebral cortex and includes the occipital, parietal, and temporal cortices. In other words, the posterior cortex includes all the cerebral cortex without the frontal cortex.

Erik Hoel is an American neuroscientist, neurophilosopher, and fiction writer. His main areas of research are the study and philosophy of consciousness, cognition, biological function of dreams, and mathematical theories of emergence. He is noted for using information theory and causal analysis to develop mathematical models to explore and understand the basis of consciousness and dreams. Hoel holds a PhD in neuroscience from the University of Wisconsin–Madison and in 2018 was recipient of the Forbes 30 Under 30 – Science award.

References

  1. 1 2 Tononi, Giulio (2015). "Integrated information theory". Scholarpedia. 10 (1): 4164. Bibcode:2015SchpJ..10.4164T. doi: 10.4249/scholarpedia.4164 .
  2. 1 2 3 Haun, Andrew; Tononi, Giulio (December 2019). "Why Does Space Feel the Way it Does? Towards a Principled Account of Spatial Experience". Entropy. 21 (12): 1160. Bibcode:2019Entrp..21.1160H. doi: 10.3390/e21121160 . PMC   7514505 .
  3. Tononi, Giulio; Koch, Christof (19 May 2015). "Consciousness: here, there and everywhere?". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 370 (1668): 20140167. doi:10.1098/rstb.2014.0167. ISSN   0962-8436. PMC   4387509 . PMID   25823865.
  4. Tononi, Giulio; Boly, Melanie; Massimini, Marcello; Koch, Christof (2016). "Integrated information theory: from consciousness to its physical substrate". Nature Reviews Neuroscience. 17 (7): 450–461. doi:10.1038/nrn.2016.44. PMID   27225071. S2CID   21347087.
  5. Tononi, Giulio (2 November 2004). "An information integration theory of consciousness". BMC Neuroscience. 5 (1): 42. doi: 10.1186/1471-2202-5-42 . ISSN   1471-2202. PMC   543470 . PMID   15522121.
  6. 1 2 Mariana Lenharo (20 September 2023). "Consciousness theory slammed as 'pseudoscience' — sparking uproar". Nature.
  7. De Haan, Edward H. F.; Corballis, Paul M.; Hillyard, Steven A.; Marzi, Carlo A.; Seth, Anil; Lamme, Victor A. F.; Volz, Lukas; Fabri, Mara; Schechter, Elizabeth; Bayne, Tim; Corballis, Michael; Pinto, Yair (2020). "Split-Brain: What We Know Now and Why This is Important for Understanding Consciousness". Neuropsychology Review. 30 (2): 224–233. doi:10.1007/s11065-020-09439-3. PMC   7305066 . PMID   32399946. S2CID   216440326.
  8. Feuillet, Lionel; Dufour, Henry; Pelletier, Jean (2007). "Brain of a white-collar worker". The Lancet. 370 (9583): 262. doi:10.1016/S0140-6736(07)61127-1. PMID   17658396. S2CID   7382008.
  9. 1 2 3 4 Mayner, William G. P.; Marshall, William; Albantakis, Larissa; Findlay, Graham; Marchman, Robert; Tononi, Giulio (26 July 2018). "PyPhi: A toolbox for integrated information theory". PLOS Computational Biology. 14 (7): e1006343. arXiv: 1712.09644 . Bibcode:2018PLSCB..14E6343M. doi: 10.1371/journal.pcbi.1006343 . ISSN   1553-7358. PMC   6080800 . PMID   30048445.
  10. Oizumi, Masafumi; Amari, Shun-ichi; Yanagawa, Toru; Fujii, Naotaka; Tsuchiya, Naotsugu (17 May 2015). "Measuring integrated information from the decoding perspective". PLOS Computational Biology. 12 (1): e1004654. arXiv: 1505.04368 . Bibcode:2016PLSCB..12E4654O. doi: 10.1371/journal.pcbi.1004654 . PMC   4721632 . PMID   26796119.
  11. Oizumi, Masafumi; Tsuchiya, Naotsugu; Amari, Shun-ichi (20 December 2016). "Unified framework for information integration based on information geometry". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 113 (51): 14817–14822. arXiv: 1510.04455 . Bibcode:2016PNAS..11314817O. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1603583113 . PMC   5187746 . PMID   27930289.
  12. Barrett, A.B.; Seth, A.K. (2011). "Practical measures of integrated information for time-series data". PLOS Comput. Biol. 7 (1): e1001052. Bibcode:2011PLSCB...7E1052B. doi: 10.1371/journal.pcbi.1001052 . PMC   3024259 . PMID   21283779.
  13. Mediano, Pedro; Seth, Anil; Barrett, Adam (25 December 2018). "Measuring Integrated Information: Comparison of Candidate Measures in Theory and Simulation". Entropy. 21 (1): 17. arXiv: 1806.09373 . Bibcode:2018Entrp..21...17M. doi: 10.3390/e21010017 . ISSN   1099-4300. PMC   7514120 . PMID   33266733.
  14. 1 2 Leung, Angus; Cohen, Dror; van Swinderen, Bruno; Tsuchiya, Naotsugu (2021). "Integrated information structure collapses with anesthetic loss of conscious arousal in Drosophila melanogaster". PLOS Computational Biology. 17 (2): e1008722. Bibcode:2021PLSCB..17E8722L. doi: 10.1371/journal.pcbi.1008722 . ISSN   1553-7358. PMC   7946294 . PMID   33635858.
  15. Toker, Daniel; Sommer, Friedrich T.; Marinazzo, Daniele (7 February 2019). "Information integration in large brain networks". PLOS Computational Biology. 15 (2): e1006807. Bibcode:2019PLSCB..15E6807T. doi: 10.1371/journal.pcbi.1006807 . PMC   6382174 . PMID   30730907.
  16. "CSC-UW/iit-pseudocode". GitHub. Retrieved 29 January 2016.
  17. Massimini, M.; Ferrarelli, F.; Murphy, Mj; Huber, R.; Riedner, Ba; Casarotto, S.; Tononi, G. (1 September 2010). "Cortical reactivity and effective connectivity during REM sleep in humans". Cognitive Neuroscience. 1 (3): 176–183. doi:10.1080/17588921003731578. ISSN   1758-8936. PMC   2930263 . PMID   20823938.
  18. Ferrarelli, Fabio; Massimini, Marcello; Sarasso, Simone; Casali, Adenauer; Riedner, Brady A.; Angelini, Giuditta; Tononi, Giulio; Pearce, Robert A. (9 February 2010). "Breakdown in cortical effective connectivity during midazolam-induced loss of consciousness". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 107 (6): 2681–2686. Bibcode:2010PNAS..107.2681F. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0913008107 . ISSN   1091-6490. PMC   2823915 . PMID   20133802.
  19. Casali, Adenauer G.; Gosseries, Olivia; Rosanova, Mario; Boly, Mélanie; Sarasso, Simone; Casali, Karina R.; Casarotto, Silvia; Bruno, Marie-Aurélie; Laureys, Steven; Massimini, Marcello (14 August 2013). "A Theoretically Based Index of Consciousness Independent of Sensory Processing and Behavior". Science Translational Medicine. 5 (198): 198ra105. doi:10.1126/scitranslmed.3006294. hdl:2268/171542. ISSN   1946-6234. PMID   23946194. S2CID   8686961.
  20. Zimmer, Carl (20 September 2010). "Sizing Up Consciousness by Its Bits". The New York Times. ISSN   0362-4331 . Retrieved 23 November 2015.
  21. Falk, Dan (30 September 2021). "Anil Seth Finds Consciousness in Life's Push Against Entropy". Quanta Magazine. Retrieved 16 December 2021.
  22. akseth (1 February 2018). "Conscious spoons, really? Pushing back against panpsychism". NeuroBanter. Retrieved 16 December 2021.
  23. Chalmers, David (14 July 2014), How do you explain consciousness? , retrieved 16 December 2021
  24. Tegmark, Max (2016). "Improved Measures of Integrated Information". PLOS Computational Biology. 12 (11): e1005123. arXiv: 1601.02626 . Bibcode:2016PLSCB..12E5123T. doi: 10.1371/journal.pcbi.1005123 . PMC   5117999 . PMID   27870846.
  25. Mediano, Pedro; Seth, Anil; Barrett, Adam (2019). "Measuring Integrated Information: Comparison of Candidate Measures in Theory and Simulation". Entropy. 21 (1): 17. arXiv: 1806.09373 . Bibcode:2018Entrp..21...17M. doi: 10.3390/e21010017 . PMC   7514120 . PMID   33266733.
  26. Aguilera, Miguel; Di Paolo, Ezequiel (2019). "Integrated information in the thermodynamic limit". Neural Networks. 114: 136–146. doi: 10.1016/j.neunet.2019.03.001 . hdl: 10810/32812 . PMID   30903946.
  27. Aguilera, Miguel (2019). "Scaling Behaviour and Critical Phase Transitions in Integrated Information Theory". Entropy. 21 (12): 1198. Bibcode:2019Entrp..21.1198A. doi: 10.3390/e21121198 . PMC   7514544 .
  28. Searle, John. "Can Information Theory Explain Consciousness?". The New York Review of Books.
  29. Fallon, Francis (1 September 2020). "Integrated Information Theory, Searle, and the Arbitrariness Question". Review of Philosophy and Psychology. 11 (3): 629–645. doi:10.1007/s13164-018-0409-0. ISSN   1878-5166. S2CID   149881007.
  30. Aaronson, Scott (21 May 2014). "Why I Am Not An Integrated Information Theorist (or, The Unconscious Expander)". Shetl-Optimized: The Blog of Scott Aaronson.
  31. Aaronson, Scott (30 May 2014). "Giulio Tononi and Me: A Phi-nal Exchange". Shetl-Optimized: The Blog of Scott Aaronson.
  32. Tononi, Giulio. "Why Scott should stare at a blank wall and reconsider (or, the conscious grid)". Shetl-Optimized: The Blog of Scott Aaronson.
  33. Boly, Melanie; Massimini, Marcello; Tsuchiya, Naotsugu; Postle, Bradley R.; Koch, Christof; Tononi, Giulio (4 October 2017). "Are the Neural Correlates of Consciousness in the Front or in the Back of the Cerebral Cortex? Clinical and Neuroimaging Evidence". Journal of Neuroscience. 37 (40): 9603–9613. doi:10.1523/JNEUROSCI.3218-16.2017. ISSN   0270-6474. PMC   5628406 . PMID   28978697. S2CID   41370141.
  34. Bayne, Tim (2018). "On the axiomatic foundations of the integrated information theory of consciousness". Neuroscience of Consciousness. 2018 (1): niy007. doi: 10.1093/nc/niy007 . PMC   6030813 . PMID   30042860.
  35. Michel, Matthias; Beck, Diane; Block, Ned; Blumenfeld, Hal; Brown, Richard; Carmel, David; Carrasco, Marisa; Chirimuuta, Mazviita; Chun, Marvin; Cleeremans, Axel; Dehaene, Stanislas; Fleming, Stephen; Frith, Chris; Haggard, Patrick; He, Biyu; Heyes, Cecilia; Goodale, Mel; Irvine, Liz; Kawato, Mitsuo; Kentridge, Robert; King, JR; Knight, Robert; Kouider, Sid; Lamme, Victor; Lamy, Dominique; Lau, Hakwan; Laureys, Steven; LeDoux, Joseph; Lin, Ying-Tung; Liu, Kayuet; Macknik, Stephen; Martinez-Conde, Susana; Mashour, George; Melloni, Lucia; Miracchi, Lisa; Mylopoulos, Myrto; Naccache, Lionel; Owen, Adrian; Passingham, Richard; Pessoa, Luiz; Peters, Megan; Rahnev, Dobromir; Ro, Tony; Rosenthal, David; Sasaki, Yuka; Sergent, Claire; Solovey, Guillermo; Schiff, Nicholas; Seth, Anil; Tallon-Baudry, Catherine; Tamietto, Marco; Tong, Frank; van Gaal, Simon; Vlassova, Alexandra; Watanabe, Takeo; Weisberg, Josh; Yan, Karen; Yoshida, Masatoshi (4 February 2019). "Opportunities and challenges for a maturing science of consciousness". Nature Human Behaviour. 3 (2): 104–107. doi:10.1038/s41562-019-0531-8. PMC   6568255 . PMID   30944453.
  36. Doerig, Adrian; Schruger, Aaron; Hess, Kathryn; Herzog, Michael (2019). "The unfolding argument: Why IIT and other causal structure theories cannot explain consciousness". Consciousness and Cognition. 72: 49–59. doi: 10.1016/j.concog.2019.04.002 . PMID   31078047.
  37. Lau, Hakwan; Michel, Matthias (2019). "On the dangers of conflating strong and weak versions of a theory of consciousness". PsyArXiv. doi:10.31234/osf.io/hjp3s. S2CID   203047817.
  38. Pautz, Adam (2019). "What is Integrated Information Theory?: A Catalogue of Questions". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 26` (1): 188–215.
  39. Jarrett, Christian (5 April 2020). "Consciousness: how can we solve the greatest mystery in science?". BBC Science Focus Magazine. Retrieved 2 February 2021.
  40. Lau, Hakwan (28 May 2020). "Open letter to NIH on Neuroethics Roadmap (BRAIN initiative) 2019". In Consciousness We Trust..
  41. Merker, Björn (19 May 2021). "The Integrated Information Theory of consciousness: A case of mistaken identity". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 45: e41. doi:10.1017/S0140525X21000881. PMID   34006338.
  42. Fleming, S. M.; Frith, C.; Goodale, M.; Lau, H.; LeDoux, J. E.; Lee, A. L. F.; et al. (2023). "The Integrated Information Theory of Consciousness as Pseudoscience". PsyArXiv (Preprint). doi: 10.31234/osf.io/zsr78 . Retrieved 18 September 2023.
  43. Zenil, Hector. "How Some Scientific Journalism is Failing Us, to both Readers & (less self-promotional) Scientists – Medium" . Retrieved 27 September 2023.
  44. "Accelerating Research on Consciousness: An Adversarial Collaboration to Test Contradictory Predictions of Global Neuronal Workspace and Integrated Information Theory". www.templetonworldcharity.org. Retrieved 16 July 2023.
  45. Melloni, Lucia; Mudrik, Liad; Pitts, Michael; Koch, Christof (28 May 2021). "Making the hard problem of consciousness easier". Science. 372 (6545): 911–912. doi:10.1126/science.abj3259. ISSN   0036-8075. PMID   34045342. S2CID   235218711.
  46. Melloni, Lucia; Mudrik, Liad; Pitts, Michael; Blumenfeld, Hal; Lange, Floris de; Jensen, Ole; Kreiman, Gabriel; Luo, Huan; Chalmers, David; Dehaene, Stanislas (16 January 2019). "Adversarial Collaboration to test GNW and IIT". Center for Open Science.
  47. Melloni, Lucia; Mudrik, Liad; Pitts, Michael; Bendtz, Katarina; Ferrante, Oscar; Gorska, Urszula; Hirschhorn, Rony; Khalaf, Aya; Kozma, Csaba; Lepauvre, Alex; Liu, Ling; Mazumder, David; Richter, David; Zhou, Hao; Blumenfeld, Hal (10 February 2023). "An adversarial collaboration protocol for testing contrasting predictions of global neuronal workspace and integrated information theory". PLOS ONE. 18 (2): e0268577. Bibcode:2023PLoSO..1868577M. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0268577 . ISSN   1932-6203. PMC   9916582 . PMID   36763595.
  48. Finkel, Elizabeth (30 June 2023). "Consciousness hunt yields results but not clarity". Science. 380 (6652): 1309–1310. Bibcode:2023Sci...380.1309F. doi:10.1126/science.adj4498. ISSN   0036-8075. PMID   37384689. S2CID   259287604.
  49. Ferrante, O.; et al. (Cogitate Consortium) (26 June 2023). "An adversarial collaboration to critically evaluate theories of consciousness". bioRxiv   10.1101/2023.06.23.546249 .

Websites

Software

Books

News articles

Talks