Transcendental number theory

Last updated

Transcendental number theory is a branch of number theory that investigates transcendental numbers (numbers that are not solutions of any polynomial equation with rational coefficients), in both qualitative and quantitative ways.

Contents

Transcendence

The fundamental theorem of algebra tells us that if we have a non-constant polynomial with rational coefficients (or equivalently, by clearing denominators, with integer coefficients) then that polynomial will have a root in the complex numbers. That is, for any non-constant polynomial with rational coefficients there will be a complex number such that . Transcendence theory is concerned with the converse question: given a complex number , is there a polynomial with rational coefficients such that If no such polynomial exists then the number is called transcendental.

More generally the theory deals with algebraic independence of numbers. A set of numbers {α1, α2, …, αn} is called algebraically independent over a field K if there is no non-zero polynomial P in n variables with coefficients in K such that P1, α2, …, αn) = 0. So working out if a given number is transcendental is really a special case of algebraic independence where n =1 and the field K is the field of rational numbers.

A related notion is whether there is a closed-form expression for a number, including exponentials and logarithms as well as algebraic operations. There are various definitions of "closed-form", and questions about closed-form can often be reduced to questions about transcendence.

History

Approximation by rational numbers: Liouville to Roth

Use of the term transcendental to refer to an object that is not algebraic dates back to the seventeenth century, when Gottfried Leibniz proved that the sine function was not an algebraic function. [1] The question of whether certain classes of numbers could be transcendental dates back to 1748 [2] when Euler asserted [3] that the number logab was not algebraic for rational numbers a and b provided b is not of the form b = ac for some rational c.

Euler's assertion was not proved until the twentieth century, but almost a hundred years after his claim Joseph Liouville did manage to prove the existence of numbers that are not algebraic, something that until then had not been known for sure. [4] His original papers on the matter in the 1840s sketched out arguments using simple continued fractions to construct transcendental numbers. Later, in the 1850s, he gave a necessary condition for a number to be algebraic, and thus a sufficient condition for a number to be transcendental. [5] This transcendence criterion was not strong enough to be necessary too, and indeed it fails to detect that the number e is transcendental. But his work did provide a larger class of transcendental numbers, now known as Liouville numbers in his honour.

Liouville's criterion essentially said that algebraic numbers cannot be very well approximated by rational numbers. So if a number can be very well approximated by rational numbers then it must be transcendental. The exact meaning of "very well approximated" in Liouville's work relates to a certain exponent. He showed that if α is an algebraic number of degree d  2 and ε is any number greater than zero, then the expression

can be satisfied by only finitely many rational numbers p/q. Using this as a criterion for transcendence is not trivial, as one must check whether there are infinitely many solutions p/q for every d  2.

In the twentieth century work by Axel Thue, [6] Carl Siegel, [7] and Klaus Roth [8] reduced the exponent in Liouville's work from d + ε to d/2 + 1 + ε, and finally, in 1955, to 2 + ε. This result, known as the Thue–Siegel–Roth theorem, is ostensibly the best possible, since if the exponent 2 + ε is replaced by just 2 then the result is no longer true. However, Serge Lang conjectured an improvement of Roth's result; in particular he conjectured that q2+ε in the denominator of the right-hand side could be reduced to .

Roth's work effectively ended the work started by Liouville, and his theorem allowed mathematicians to prove the transcendence of many more numbers, such as the Champernowne constant. The theorem is still not strong enough to detect all transcendental numbers, though, and many famous constants including e and π either are not or are not known to be very well approximable in the above sense. [9]

Auxiliary functions: Hermite to Baker

Fortunately other methods were pioneered in the nineteenth century to deal with the algebraic properties of e, and consequently of π through Euler's identity. This work centred on use of the so-called auxiliary function. These are functions which typically have many zeros at the points under consideration. Here "many zeros" may mean many distinct zeros, or as few as one zero but with a high multiplicity, or even many zeros all with high multiplicity. Charles Hermite used auxiliary functions that approximated the functions for each natural number in order to prove the transcendence of in 1873. [10] His work was built upon by Ferdinand von Lindemann in the 1880s [11] in order to prove that eα is transcendental for nonzero algebraic numbers α. In particular this proved that π is transcendental since eπi is algebraic, and thus answered in the negative the problem of antiquity as to whether it was possible to square the circle. Karl Weierstrass developed their work yet further and eventually proved the Lindemann–Weierstrass theorem in 1885. [12]

In 1900 David Hilbert posed his famous collection of problems. The seventh of these, and one of the hardest in Hilbert's estimation, asked about the transcendence of numbers of the form ab where a and b are algebraic, a is not zero or one, and b is irrational. In the 1930s Alexander Gelfond [13] and Theodor Schneider [14] proved that all such numbers were indeed transcendental using a non-explicit auxiliary function whose existence was granted by Siegel's lemma. This result, the Gelfond–Schneider theorem, proved the transcendence of numbers such as eπ and the Gelfond–Schneider constant.

The next big result in this field occurred in the 1960s, when Alan Baker made progress on a problem posed by Gelfond on linear forms in logarithms. Gelfond himself had managed to find a non-trivial lower bound for the quantity

where all four unknowns are algebraic, the αs being neither zero nor one and the βs being irrational. Finding similar lower bounds for the sum of three or more logarithms had eluded Gelfond, though. The proof of Baker's theorem contained such bounds, solving Gauss' class number problem for class number one in the process. This work won Baker the Fields medal for its uses in solving Diophantine equations. From a purely transcendental number theoretic viewpoint, Baker had proved that if α1, ..., αn are algebraic numbers, none of them zero or one, and β1, ..., βn are algebraic numbers such that 1, β1, ..., βn are linearly independent over the rational numbers, then the number

is transcendental. [15]

Other techniques: Cantor and Zilber

In the 1870s, Georg Cantor started to develop set theory and, in 1874, published a paper proving that the algebraic numbers could be put in one-to-one correspondence with the set of natural numbers, and thus that the set of transcendental numbers must be uncountable. [16] Later, in 1891, Cantor used his more familiar diagonal argument to prove the same result. [17] While Cantor's result is often quoted as being purely existential and thus unusable for constructing a single transcendental number, [18] [19] the proofs in both the aforementioned papers give methods to construct transcendental numbers. [20]

While Cantor used set theory to prove the plenitude of transcendental numbers, a recent development has been the use of model theory in attempts to prove an unsolved problem in transcendental number theory. The problem is to determine the transcendence degree of the field

for complex numbers x1, ..., xn that are linearly independent over the rational numbers. Stephen Schanuel conjectured that the answer is at least n, but no proof is known. In 2004, though, Boris Zilber published a paper that used model theoretic techniques to create a structure that behaves very much like the complex numbers equipped with the operations of addition, multiplication, and exponentiation. Moreover, in this abstract structure Schanuel's conjecture does indeed hold. [21] Unfortunately it is not yet known that this structure is in fact the same as the complex numbers with the operations mentioned; there could exist some other abstract structure that behaves very similarly to the complex numbers but where Schanuel's conjecture doesn't hold. Zilber did provide several criteria that would prove the structure in question was C, but could not prove the so-called Strong Exponential Closure axiom. The simplest case of this axiom has since been proved, [22] but a proof that it holds in full generality is required to complete the proof of the conjecture.

Approaches

A typical problem in this area of mathematics is to work out whether a given number is transcendental. Cantor used a cardinality argument to show that there are only countably many algebraic numbers, and hence almost all numbers are transcendental. Transcendental numbers therefore represent the typical case; even so, it may be extremely difficult to prove that a given number is transcendental (or even simply irrational).

For this reason transcendence theory often works towards a more quantitative approach. So given a particular complex number α one can ask how close α is to being an algebraic number. For example, if one supposes that the number α is algebraic then can one show that it must have very high degree or a minimum polynomial with very large coefficients? Ultimately if it is possible to show that no finite degree or size of coefficient is sufficient then the number must be transcendental. Since a number α is transcendental if and only if P(α)  0 for every non-zero polynomial P with integer coefficients, this problem can be approached by trying to find lower bounds of the form

where the right hand side is some positive function depending on some measure A of the size of the coefficients of P, and its degree d, and such that these lower bounds apply to all P ≠ 0. Such a bound is called a transcendence measure.

The case of d =1 is that of "classical" diophantine approximation asking for lower bounds for

.

The methods of transcendence theory and diophantine approximation have much in common: they both use the auxiliary function concept.

Major results

The Gelfond–Schneider theorem was the major advance in transcendence theory in the period 1900–1950. In the 1960s the method of Alan Baker on linear forms in logarithms of algebraic numbers reanimated transcendence theory, with applications to numerous classical problems and diophantine equations.

Mahler's classification

Kurt Mahler in 1932 partitioned the transcendental numbers into 3 classes, called S, T, and U. [23] Definition of these classes draws on an extension of the idea of a Liouville number (cited above).

Measure of irrationality of a real number

One way to define a Liouville number is to consider how small a given real number x makes linear polynomials |qx  p| without making them exactly 0. Here p, q are integers with |p|, |q| bounded by a positive integer H.

Let be the minimum non-zero absolute value these polynomials take and take:

ω(x, 1) is often called the measure of irrationality of a real number x. For rational numbers, ω(x, 1) = 0 and is at least 1 for irrational real numbers. A Liouville number is defined to have infinite measure of irrationality. Roth's theorem says that irrational real algebraic numbers have measure of irrationality 1.

Measure of transcendence of a complex number

Next consider the values of polynomials at a complex number x, when these polynomials have integer coefficients, degree at most n, and height at most H, with n, H being positive integers.

Let be the minimum non-zero absolute value such polynomials take at and take:

Suppose this is infinite for some minimum positive integer n. A complex number x in this case is called a U number of degree n.

Now we can define

ω(x) is often called the measure of transcendence of x. If the ω(x, n) are bounded, then ω(x) is finite, and x is called an S number. If the ω(x, n) are finite but unbounded, x is called a T number. x is algebraic if and only if ω(x) = 0.

Clearly the Liouville numbers are a subset of the U numbers. William LeVeque in 1953 constructed U numbers of any desired degree. [24] The Liouville numbers and hence the U numbers are uncountable sets. They are sets of measure 0. [25]

T numbers also comprise a set of measure 0. [26] It took about 35 years to show their existence. Wolfgang M. Schmidt in 1968 showed that examples exist. However, almost all complex numbers are S numbers. [27] Mahler proved that the exponential function sends all non-zero algebraic numbers to S numbers: [28] [29] this shows that e is an S number and gives a proof of the transcendence of π. This number π is known not to be a U number. [30] Many other transcendental numbers remain unclassified.

Two numbers x, y are called algebraically dependent if there is a non-zero polynomial P in two indeterminates with integer coefficients such that P(x, y) = 0. There is a powerful theorem that two complex numbers that are algebraically dependent belong to the same Mahler class. [24] [31] This allows construction of new transcendental numbers, such as the sum of a Liouville number with e or π.

The symbol S probably stood for the name of Mahler's teacher Carl Ludwig Siegel, and T and U are just the next two letters.

Koksma's equivalent classification

Jurjen Koksma in 1939 proposed another classification based on approximation by algebraic numbers. [23] [32]

Consider the approximation of a complex number x by algebraic numbers of degree ≤n and height ≤H. Let α be an algebraic number of this finite set such that |x  α| has the minimum positive value. Define ω*(x, H, n) and ω*(x, n) by:

If for a smallest positive integer n, ω*(x, n) is infinite, x is called a U*-number of degree n.

If the ω*(x, n) are bounded and do not converge to 0, x is called an S*-number,

A number x is called an A*-number if the ω*(x, n) converge to 0.

If the ω*(x, n) are all finite but unbounded, x is called a T*-number,

Koksma's and Mahler's classifications are equivalent in that they divide the transcendental numbers into the same classes. [32] The A*-numbers are the algebraic numbers. [27]

LeVeque's construction

Let

It can be shown that the nth root of λ (a Liouville number) is a U-number of degree n. [33]

This construction can be improved to create an uncountable family of U-numbers of degree n. Let Z be the set consisting of every other power of 10 in the series above for λ. The set of all subsets of Z is uncountable. Deleting any of the subsets of Z from the series for λ creates uncountably many distinct Liouville numbers, whose nth roots are U-numbers of degree n.

Type

The supremum of the sequence {ω(x,n)} is called the type. Almost all real numbers are S numbers of type 1, which is minimal for real S numbers. Almost all complex numbers are S numbers of type 1/2, which is also minimal. The claims of almost all numbers were conjectured by Mahler and in 1965 proved by Vladimir Sprindzhuk. [34]

Open problems

While the Gelfond–Schneider theorem proved that a large class of numbers was transcendental, this class was still countable. Many well-known mathematical constants are still not known to be transcendental, and in some cases it is not even known whether they are rational or irrational. A partial list can be found here.

A major problem in transcendence theory is showing that a particular set of numbers is algebraically independent rather than just showing that individual elements are transcendental. So while we know that e and π are transcendental that doesn't imply that e + π is transcendental, nor other combinations of the two (except eπ, Gelfond's constant, which is known to be transcendental). Another major problem is dealing with numbers that are not related to the exponential function. The main results in transcendence theory tend to revolve around e and the logarithm function, which means that wholly new methods tend to be required to deal with numbers that cannot be expressed in terms of these two objects in an elementary fashion.

Schanuel's conjecture would solve the first of these problems somewhat as it deals with algebraic independence and would indeed confirm that e + π is transcendental. It still revolves around the exponential function, however, and so would not necessarily deal with numbers such as Apéry's constant or the Euler–Mascheroni constant. Another extremely difficult unsolved problem is the so-called constant or identity problem. [35]

Notes

  1. N. Bourbaki, Elements of the History of Mathematics Springer (1994).
  2. Gelfond 1960 , p. 2.
  3. Euler, L. (1748). Introductio in analysin infinitorum. Lausanne.
  4. The existence proof based on the different cardinalities of the real and the algebraic numbers was not possible before Cantor's first set theory article in 1874.
  5. Liouville, J. (1844). "Sur les classes très étendues de quantités dont la valeur n'est ni algébrique ni même réductible à des irrationelles algébriques". Comptes rendus de l'Académie des Sciences de Paris. 18: 883–885, 910–911.; Journal Math. Pures et Appl.16, (1851), pp.133–142.
  6. Thue, A. (1909). "Über Annäherungswerte algebraischer Zahlen". J. Reine Angew. Math. 1909 (135): 284–305. doi:10.1515/crll.1909.135.284. S2CID   125903243.
  7. Siegel, C. L. (1921). "Approximation algebraischer Zahlen". Mathematische Zeitschrift . 10 (3–4): 172–213. doi: 10.1007/BF01211608 .
  8. Roth, K. F. (1955). "Rational approximations to algebraic numbers". Mathematika . 2 (1): 1–20. doi:10.1112/S0025579300000644. And "Corrigendum", p. 168, doi : 10.1112/S002559300000826.
  9. Mahler, K. (1953). "On the approximation of π". Proc. Akad. Wetensch. Ser. A. 56: 30–42.
  10. Hermite, C. (1873). "Sur la fonction exponentielle". C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris. 77.
  11. Lindemann, F. (1882). "Ueber die Zahl π". Mathematische Annalen . 20 (2): 213–225. doi: 10.1007/BF01446522 .
  12. Weierstrass, K. (1885). "Zu Hrn. Lindemann's Abhandlung: 'Über die Ludolph'sche Zahl'". Sitzungber. Königl. Preuss. Akad. Wissensch. Zu Berlin. 2: 1067–1086.
  13. Gelfond, A. O. (1934). "Sur le septième Problème de D. Hilbert". Izv. Akad. Nauk SSSR. 7: 623–630.
  14. Schneider, T. (1935). "Transzendenzuntersuchungen periodischer Funktionen. I. Transzendend von Potenzen". Journal für die reine und angewandte Mathematik . 1935 (172): 65–69. doi:10.1515/crll.1935.172.65. S2CID   115310510.
  15. A. Baker, Linear forms in the logarithms of algebraic numbers. I, II, III, Mathematika 13 ,(1966), pp.204–216; ibid. 14, (1967), pp.102–107; ibid. 14, (1967), pp.220–228, MR 0220680
  16. Cantor, G. (1874). "Ueber eine Eigenschaft des Inbegriffes aller reelen algebraischen Zahlen". J. Reine Angew. Math. (in German). 1874 (77): 258–262. doi:10.1515/crll.1874.77.258. S2CID   199545885.
  17. Cantor, G. (1891). "Ueber eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre". Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung (in German). 1: 75–78.
  18. Kac, M.; Stanislaw, U. (1968). Mathematics and Logic . Fredering A. Praeger. p.  13.
  19. Bell, E. T. (1937). Men of Mathematics. New York: Simon & Schuster. p.  569.
  20. Gray, R. (1994). "Georg Cantor and Transcendental Numbers" (PDF). American Mathematical Monthly . 101 (9): 819–832. doi:10.1080/00029890.1994.11997035. JSTOR   2975129.
  21. Zilber, B. (2005). "Pseudo-exponentiation on algebraically closed fields of characteristic zero". Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 132 (1): 67–95. doi: 10.1016/j.apal.2004.07.001 . MR   2102856.
  22. Marker, D. (2006). "A remark on Zilber's pseudoexponentiation". Journal of Symbolic Logic. 71 (3): 791–798. doi:10.2178/jsl/1154698577. JSTOR   27588482. MR   2250821. S2CID   1477361.
  23. 1 2 Bugeaud 2012 , p. 250.
  24. 1 2 LeVeque 2002 , p. II:172.
  25. Burger & Tubbs 2004 , p. 170.
  26. Burger & Tubbs 2004 , p. 172.
  27. 1 2 Bugeaud 2012 , p. 251.
  28. LeVeque 2002 , pp. II:174–186.
  29. Burger & Tubbs 2004 , p. 182.
  30. Baker 1975, p. 86.
  31. Burger & Tubbs 2004 , p. 163.
  32. 1 2 Baker 1975 , p. 87.
  33. Baker 1975 , p. 90.
  34. Baker 1975 , p. 86.
  35. Richardson, D. (1968). "Some Undecidable Problems Involving Elementary Functions of a Real Variable". Journal of Symbolic Logic. 33 (4): 514–520. doi:10.2307/2271358. JSTOR   2271358. MR   0239976. S2CID   37066167.

Related Research Articles

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Algebraic number</span> Complex number that is a root of a non-zero polynomial in one variable with rational coefficients

An algebraic number is a number that is a root of a non-zero polynomial in one variable with integer coefficients. For example, the golden ratio, , is an algebraic number, because it is a root of the polynomial x2x − 1. That is, it is a value for x for which the polynomial evaluates to zero. As another example, the complex number is algebraic because it is a root of x4 + 4.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Complex number</span> Number with a real and an imaginary part

In mathematics, a complex number is an element of a number system that extends the real numbers with a specific element denoted i, called the imaginary unit and satisfying the equation ; every complex number can be expressed in the form , where a and b are real numbers. Because no real number satisfies the above equation, i was called an imaginary number by René Descartes. For the complex number ,a is called the real part, and b is called the imaginary part. The set of complex numbers is denoted by either of the symbols or C. Despite the historical nomenclature, "imaginary" complex numbers have a mathematical existence as firm as that of the real numbers, and they are fundamental tools in the scientific description of the natural world.

In mathematics, a transcendental number is a real or complex number that is not algebraic: that is, not the root of a non-zero polynomial with integer coefficients. The best-known transcendental numbers are π and e. The quality of a number being transcendental is called transcendence.

In number theory, a Liouville number is a real number with the property that, for every positive integer , there exists a pair of integers with such that

In mathematics, a transcendental extension is a field extension such that there exists an element in the field that is transcendental over the field ; that is, an element that is not a root of any univariate polynomial with coefficients in . In other words, a transcendental extension is a field extension that is not algebraic. For example, and are both transcendental extensions of

In abstract algebra, a subset of a field is algebraically independent over a subfield if the elements of do not satisfy any non-trivial polynomial equation with coefficients in .

In mathematics, a transcendental function is an analytic function that does not satisfy a polynomial equation whose coefficients are functions of the independent variable that can be written using only the basic operations of addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division. This is in contrast to an algebraic function.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Lindemann–Weierstrass theorem</span> On algebraic independence of exponentials of linearly independent algebraic numbers over Q

In transcendental number theory, the Lindemann–Weierstrass theorem is a result that is very useful in establishing the transcendence of numbers. It states the following:

In mathematics, complex multiplication (CM) is the theory of elliptic curves E that have an endomorphism ring larger than the integers. Put another way, it contains the theory of elliptic functions with extra symmetries, such as are visible when the period lattice is the Gaussian integer lattice or Eisenstein integer lattice.

In mathematics, the Gelfond–Schneider theorem establishes the transcendence of a large class of numbers.

In mathematics, Roth's theorem or Thue–Siegel–Roth theorem is a fundamental result in diophantine approximation to algebraic numbers. It is of a qualitative type, stating that algebraic numbers cannot have many rational approximations that are 'very good'. Over half a century, the meaning of very good here was refined by a number of mathematicians, starting with Joseph Liouville in 1844 and continuing with work of Axel Thue, Carl Ludwig Siegel, Freeman Dyson, and Klaus Roth.

In mathematics, the exponential of pieπ, also called Gelfond's constant, is the real number e raised to the power π.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Schanuel's conjecture</span> Major unsolved problem in transcendental number theory

In mathematics, specifically transcendental number theory, Schanuel's conjecture is a conjecture about the transcendence degree of certain field extensions of the rational numbers , which would establish the transcendence of a large class of numbers, for which this is currently unknown. It is due to Stephen Schanuel and was published by Serge Lang in 1966.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Irrationality measure</span> Function that quantifies how near a number is to being rational

In mathematics, an irrationality measure of a real number is a measure of how "closely" it can be approximated by rationals.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Period (algebraic geometry)</span> Numbers expressible as integrals of algebraic functions

In mathematics, specifically algebraic geometry, a period or algebraic period is a complex number that can be expressed as an integral of an algebraic function over an algebraic domain. The periods are a class of numbers which includes, alongside the algebraic numbers, many well known mathematical constants such as the number π. Sums and products of periods remain periods, such that the periods form a ring.

In mathematics, E-functions are a type of power series that satisfy particular arithmetic conditions on the coefficients. They are of interest in transcendental number theory, and are closely related to G-functions.

In mathematics, auxiliary functions are an important construction in transcendental number theory. They are functions that appear in most proofs in this area of mathematics and that have specific, desirable properties, such as taking the value zero for many arguments, or having a zero of high order at some point.

In mathematics, specifically the field of transcendental number theory, the four exponentials conjecture is a conjecture which, given the right conditions on the exponents, would guarantee the transcendence of at least one of four exponentials. The conjecture, along with two related, stronger conjectures, is at the top of a hierarchy of conjectures and theorems concerning the arithmetic nature of a certain number of values of the exponential function.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Irrational number</span> Number that is not a ratio of integers

In mathematics, the irrational numbers are all the real numbers that are not rational numbers. That is, irrational numbers cannot be expressed as the ratio of two integers. When the ratio of lengths of two line segments is an irrational number, the line segments are also described as being incommensurable, meaning that they share no "measure" in common, that is, there is no length, no matter how short, that could be used to express the lengths of both of the two given segments as integer multiples of itself.

In transcendental number theory, a mathematical discipline, Baker's theorem gives a lower bound for the absolute value of linear combinations of logarithms of algebraic numbers. Nearly fifteen years earlier, Alexander Gelfond had considered the problem with only integer coefficients to be of "extraordinarily great significance". The result, proved by Alan Baker, subsumed many earlier results in transcendental number theory. Baker used this to prove the transcendence of many numbers, to derive effective bounds for the solutions of some Diophantine equations, and to solve the class number problem of finding all imaginary quadratic fields with class number 1.

References

Further reading