Moral patienthood

Last updated

Moral patienthood [1] (also called moral patience, [2] moral patiency, [3] moral status [4] [5] , and moral considerability [6] ) is the state of being eligible for moral consideration by a moral agent. [4] In other words, the morality of an action depends at least partly on how it affects those beings that possess moral patienthood, which are called moral patients [7] or morally considerable beings. [6]

Contents

Notions of moral patienthood in non-human animals [8] [9] and artificial entities [10] [11] have been academically explored. More detail on the ethical treatment of nonhuman animals, specifically, can be seen at the Animal rights article.

Definition

Most authors define moral patients as "beings that are appropriate objects of direct moral concern". [4] This category may include moral agents, and usually does include them. For instance, Charles Taliaferro says: "A moral agent is someone who can bring about events in ways that are praiseworthy or subject to blame. A moral patient is someone who can be morally mistreated. All moral agents are moral patients, but not all moral patients (human babies, some nonhuman animals) are moral agents." [12]

Narrow usage

Some authors use the term in a more narrow sense, according to which moral patients are "beings who are appropriate objects of direct moral concern but are not (also) moral agents". [4] Tom Regan's The Case for Animal Rights used the term in this narrow sense. [13] This usage was shared by other authors who cited Regan, such as Nicholas Bunnin and Jiyuan Yu's Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy, [13] Dinesh Wadiwel's The War Against Animals, [14] and the Encyclopedia of Population. [15] These authors did not think that moral agents are not eligible for moral consideration, they simply had a different view on how a "moral patient" is defined.

Relationship with moral agency

The paper by Luciano Floridi and J.W. Sanders, On the Morality of Artificial Agents, defines moral agents as "all entities that can in principle qualify as sources of moral action", and defines moral patients, in accordance with the common usage, as "all entities that can in principle qualify as receivers of moral action". [16] However, they note that besides inclusion of agents within patients, other relationships of moral patienthood with moral agency are possible. Marian Quigley's Encyclopedia of Information Ethics and Security summarizes the possibilities that they gave:

How can we characterize the relationship between ethical agents and patients? According to Floridi and Sanders (2004), there are five logical relationships between the class of ethical agents and the class of patients: (1) agents and patients are disjoint, (2) patients can be a proper subset of agents, (3) agents and patients can intersect, (4) agents and patients can be equal, or (5) agents can be a proper subset of patients. Medical ethics, bioethics, and environmental ethics "typify" agents and patients when the patient is specified as any form of life. Animals, for example, can be moral patients but not moral agents. Also, there are ethics that typify moral agenthood to include legal entities (especially human-based entities) such as companies, agencies, and artificial agents, in addition to humans. [17]

Mireille Hildebrandt notes that Floridi and Sanders, in their paper, spoke of "damage" instead of "harm", and that in doing so, they "avoid the usual assumption that an entity must be sentient to count as a patient." [18]

Implications

Moral patienthood (or full moral patienthood, in theories which allow for partial moral status) has been alleged (by the cited sources) to imply the following moral obligations: [5]

Moral patienthood is, by itself, an independent reason to have these moral obligations; there may be other reasons to have these obligations, but merely having these obligations towards a being does not imply that the being is a moral patient. [5] (For instance, supposing that there is a moral obligation to keep promises, someone may acquire these moral obligations toward any being by simply promising to treat it like a moral patient.)

Grounds of moral patienthood

Moral patienthood has been claimed, in the literature, to be grounded in various properties. [5] [26]

PropertyDefinitionSources
Sophisticated cognitive capacitiesMoral patienthood is grounded in very sophisticated intellectual/emotional capacities (e.g., autonomy, self-awareness, valuing, caring). Kant ( Groundwork ) [27] ; Quinn [24] ; McMahan [20] ; Tooley [28] ; Singer [29] ; Buss [30] ; Theunissen [31] ; Feinberg [19] ; Jaworska [22]
Capacity to develop sophisticated cognitive capacitiesPotential for such capacities (a "future like ours" or similar) grounds moral patienthood (or some status/enhancement).Stone [32] ; Marquis [33] [34] ; Harman [35] [36] ; Steinbock [37] ; Boonin [38] ; Feinberg [19] ; Wilkins [39] ; McInerney [40]
Rudimentary cognitive capacitiesLower the bar to sentience, interests, basic emotions, or consciousness as sufficient for (full) status.Wood and O'Neill [41] ; Regan [42] ; Singer [29] ; DeGrazia [43] [44] ; Rachels [45] ; Harman [36] ; McMahan [20] ; Taylor [46] ; Naess [47] ; Johnson [48] ; Anderson [49]
Member of cognitively sophisticated speciesMoral patienthood via (i) being human or (ii) belonging to any cognitively sophisticated species/kind.Feinberg [19] ; Dworkin [50] ; Benn [51] ; Cohen [52] ; Scanlon [53] ; Finnis [54] ; Korsgaard [55] ; Sumner [56] ; McMahan [20] ; McMahan [21] ; Little [57] ; Quinn [24]
Special relationshipsStrong reasons (akin to moral patienthood) grounded in species/community, parent–child, or other special ties.Nozick [58] ; Scanlon [53] ; Kittay [59] ; Steinbock [37] ; Quinn [24] ; Warren [60] ; Anderson [49] ; Gilbert [61] ; McMahan [62] [20]
Incompletely realized sophisticated cognitive capacitiesHaving such capacities incompletely realized (via mentor-guided activities/standards) can elevate status (possibly up to full moral patienthood).Jaworska & Tannenbaum [63]
Not being designed by anyone to fulfill any purposeThe idea that an entity's not having been designed for a purpose grounds being treated as an end (and thus having moral status or some degree of it).Brennan [64] ; Katz [65]
Naturalness (unaltered by humans)The claim that being natural or unaltered by human intervention confers intrinsic value and thus some moral status.Elliot [66]
Harmony and beauty (aesthetic value) of ecosystemsAppeals to harmony, beauty, or aesthetic value of ecosystems (or nature generally) as grounds for moral considerability or status.Leopold ( A Sand County Almanac ) [67] ; Callicott [68]

History

Moral patienthood may have existed since prehistory, [69] [70] but most discussions of it as a distinct concept happened since the 1970s. News events where sources explicitly raised the issue of moral patienthood outside of philosophy are also added, except where they related to animals, since those are covered in the article "History of animal rights".

Before the 1970s

Philosophical writings from this period:

In 1969, the Hastings Center for Bioethics was founded. [71]

1970s

Philosophical writings from this period:

1980s

Philosophical writings from this period:

1990s

Philosophical writings from this period:

2000s

Philosophical writings from this period:

2010s

Philosophical writings from this period:

2020s

In 2021, Open Philanthropy recommended a grant of $315,500 to "support research related to moral patienthood and moral weight." [72]

In 2022, Google engineer Blake Lemoine publicly claimed that LaMDA (a language model) was "sentient". [73] [74]

Philosophical writings from this period:

See also

References

  1. Haji, Ishtiyaque; Bernstein, Mark H. (November 2001). "On Moral Considerability: An Essay on Who Morally Matters" . Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 63 (3): 730. doi:10.2307/3071172. JSTOR   3071172.
  2. Zhou, Xinyue; Guo, Siyuan; Huang, Rong; Ye, Weiling (2020), Wu, Shuang; Pantoja, Felipe; Krey, Nina (eds.), "Think versus Feel: Two Dimensions of Brand Anthropomorphism: An Abstract" , Marketing Opportunities and Challenges in a Changing Global Marketplace, Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 351–352, doi:10.1007/978-3-030-39165-2_138, ISBN   978-3-030-39164-5 , retrieved 2024-04-16
  3. Danaher, John (March 2019). "The rise of the robots and the crisis of moral patiency". AI & Society. 34 (1): 129–136. doi:10.1007/s00146-017-0773-9. ISSN   0951-5666.
  4. 1 2 3 4 Audi, Robert, ed. (2015). The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy (3 ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/cbo9781139057509. ISBN   978-1-139-05750-9.
  5. 1 2 3 4 Jaworska, Agnieszka; Tannenbaum, Julie (2023), "The Grounds of Moral Status", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2023 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2024-04-16
  6. 1 2 Gruen, Lori; Monsó, Susana (2024), "The Moral Status of Animals", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2024 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2025-08-04
  7. Moosavi, Parisa (2023-09-09). "Will intelligent machines become moral patients?". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 109 (1): 95–116. doi:10.1111/phpr.13019. ISSN   0031-8205.
  8. Lan T, Sinhababu N, Carrasco LR (2022) Recognition of intrinsic values of sentient beings explains the sense of moral duty towards global nature conservation. PLoS ONE 17(10): e0276614. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0276614
  9. Müller, N.D. (2022). Kantian Moral Concern, Love, and Respect. In: Kantianism for Animals. The Palgrave Macmillan Animal Ethics Series. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-01930-2_2
  10. Balle, S.N. Empathic responses and moral status for social robots: an argument in favor of robot patienthood based on K. E. Løgstrup. AI & Soc 37, 535–548 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-021-01211-2
  11. Harris, J., Anthis, J.R. The Moral Consideration of Artificial Entities: A Literature Review. Sci Eng Ethics 27, 53 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-021-00331-8
  12. Taliaferro, Charles; Marty, Elsa J., eds. (2018). A dictionary of philosophy of religion (2nd ed.). New York: Bloomsbury Academic, An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Inc. ISBN   978-1-5013-2523-6.
  13. 1 2 Bunnin, Nicholas; Yu, Jiyuan (2004). The Blackwell dictionary of Western philosophy. Malden, MA: Blackwell Pub. ISBN   978-1-4051-0679-5.
  14. Wadiwel, Dinesh Joseph (2015). The war against animals. Critical animal studies. Leiden; Boston: Brill. ISBN   978-90-04-30041-5.
  15. "Animal Rights | Encyclopedia.com". www.encyclopedia.com. Retrieved 2024-04-16.
  16. Floridi, Luciano; Sanders, J.W. (August 2004). "On the Morality of Artificial Agents" . Minds and Machines. 14 (3): 349–379. doi:10.1023/B:MIND.0000035461.63578.9d. hdl: 2299/1822 . ISSN   0924-6495.
  17. Quigley, Marian, ed. (2008). Encyclopedia of information ethics and security. Hershey: Information Science Reference. p. 516. ISBN   978-1-59140-987-8. OCLC   85444168.
  18. Duff, Antony; Green, Stuart P., eds. (2011). Philosophical foundations of criminal law. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. p. 523. ISBN   978-0-19-955915-2.
  19. 1 2 3 4 Regan, Tom; Beauchamp, Tom L., eds. (1993). Matters of life and death: new introductory essays in moral philosophy (3 ed.). New York: Random House. pp. 98–104, 193, 197–198. ISBN   978-0-07-051330-3.
  20. 1 2 3 4 5 McMahan, Jeff; MacMahan, Jeff (2003). The ethics of killing: problems at the margins of life. Oxford ethics series (1. iss. ... as paperback ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 45, 212–214, 216, 232, 235, 242, 225–226. ISBN   978-0-19-507998-2.
  21. 1 2 McMahan, Jeff (2008-01-01). "Challenges To Human Equality". The Journal of Ethics. 12 (1): 81–104. doi:10.1007/s10892-007-9020-9. ISSN   1572-8609.
  22. 1 2 3 Jaworska, Agnieszka (2007). "Caring and Full Moral Standing". Ethics. 117 (3): 460–497. doi:10.1086/512780. ISSN   0014-1704. JSTOR   10.1086/512780.
  23. Greenspan, Patricia (July 2010). "Making Room for Options: Moral Reasons, Imperfect Duties, and Choice". Social Philosophy and Policy. 27 (2): 181–205. doi:10.1017/S0265052509990203. ISSN   1471-6437.
  24. 1 2 3 4 Quinn, Warren (1984). "Abortion: Identity and Loss". Philosophy & Public Affairs. 13 (1): 24–54. ISSN   0048-3915. JSTOR   2265198.
  25. Broome, John (1990). "Fairness". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. 91: 87–101. doi:10.1093/aristotelian/91.1.87. ISSN   0066-7374. JSTOR   4545128.
  26. Bostrom, Nick (2024). Deep utopia: life and meaning in a solved world. Ideapress publishing. p. 81. ISBN   978-1-64687-164-3.
  27. Korsgaard, Christine M.; Gregor, Mary; Timmermann, Jens (2012-04-19). Kant: Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. pp. 428, 434, 436. doi:10.1017/cbo9780511919978. ISBN   978-1-107-00851-9 . Retrieved 2025-08-13.{{cite book}}: |website= ignored (help)
  28. TOOLEY, MICHAEL (2021-07-13), "Abortion and Infanticide", Rights and Wrongs of Abortion, Princeton University Press, p. 44, doi:10.2307/j.ctv1nxcvkr.6, ISBN   978-0-691-23316-1 , retrieved 2025-08-13
  29. 1 2 Singer, Peter (1993-01-29). Practical Ethics. Cambridge University Press. pp. 95, 100. ISBN   978-0-521-43971-8.
  30. Buss, Sarah (2012). "The Value of Humanity". The Journal of Philosophy. 109 (5/6): 352. doi:10.5840/jphil20121095/614. ISSN   0022-362X. JSTOR   43820709.
  31. Theunissen, L. Nandi (2020). The Value of Humanity. Oxford University Press. pp. 126–127. ISBN   978-0-19-883264-5.
  32. Stone, Jim (1987). "Why Potentiality Matters". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 17 (4): 815–829. doi:10.1080/00455091.1987.10715920. ISSN   0045-5091. JSTOR   40231569.
  33. Marquis, Don (Apr 1989). "Why abortion is immoral". The Journal of Philosophy. 86 (4): 183–202. doi:10.2307/2026961. ISSN   0022-362X. JSTOR   2026961. PMID   11782094.
  34. Marquis, Don (1995). "Fetuses, Futures and Values". Southwest Philosophy Review. 11 (2): 263–265. doi:10.5840/swphilreview199511238. ISSN   0897-2346.
  35. Harman, Elizabeth (1999). "Creation ethics: the moral status of early fetuses and the ethics of abortion". Philosophy & Public Affairs. 28 (4): 310–324. doi:10.1111/j.1088-4963.1999.00310.x. ISSN   0048-3915. PMID   11657937.
  36. 1 2 Harman, Elizabeth (May 2003). "The Potentiality Problem". Philosophical Studies. 114 (1–2): 187, 311. doi:10.1023/a:1024469419944. ISSN   0031-8116.
  37. 1 2 Steinbock, Bonnie (2011). Life before birth: the moral and legal status of embryos and fetuses (2nd ed.). New York Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 9, 13, 68–70. ISBN   978-0-19-534162-1.
  38. Boonin, David (2002). A Defense of Abortion. Cambridge Studies in Philosophy and Public Policy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 46–49, 62, 84 & n.36, 48. doi:10.1017/cbo9780511610172. ISBN   978-0-521-52035-5.
  39. Wilkins, B. T. (1993). "Does the fetus have a right to life?". Journal of Social Philosophy. 24 (1): 126–127. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9833.1993.tb00500.x. ISSN   0047-2786. PMID   16035157.
  40. McInerney, Peter K. (May 1990). "Does a fetus already have a future-like-ours?". The Journal of Philosophy. 87 (5): 264–268. doi:10.2307/2026834. ISSN   0022-362X. JSTOR   2026834. PMID   11782096.
  41. Wood, Allen W.; O'Neill, Onora (1998). "Kant on Duties Regarding Nonrational Nature". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes. 72: 197. ISSN   0309-7013. JSTOR   4107017.
  42. Regan, Tom (2004). The Case for Animal Rights. University of California Press. pp. 304, 324.
  43. DeGrazia, David (1996). Taking Animals Seriously: Mental Life and Moral Status. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/cbo9781139172967. ISBN   978-0-521-56140-2.
  44. DeGrazia, David (2008). "Moral Status As a Matter of Degree?". The Southern Journal of Philosophy. 46 (2): 181–198. doi:10.1111/j.2041-6962.2008.tb00075.x. ISSN   2041-6962.
  45. Rachels, James (1990). Created From Animals: The Moral Implications of Darwinism. Oxford University Press. pp. 186–194.
  46. Taylor, Paul W. (2011). Respect for nature: a theory of environmental ethics (25th anniversary ed.). Princeton: Princeton University Press. p. 75. ISBN   978-0-691-15024-6.
  47. Naess, Arne (1986). "The Deep Ecological Movement". Philosophical Inquiry. 8 (1–2): 14. doi:10.5840/philinquiry198681/22.
  48. Johnson, Lawrence E. (2000). A morally deep world: an essay on moral significance and environmental ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Pr. pp. 146, 148, 184, 287. ISBN   978-0-521-44706-5.
  49. 1 2 Sunstein, Cass R.; Nussbaum, Martha C. (2005-11-24). Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions. Oxford University Press. pp. 282–283, 284, 287–289. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195305104.003.0014. ISBN   978-0-19-530510-4.
  50. Dworkin, Ronald (2011). "3". Life's Dominion: An Argument about Abortion, Euthanasia, and Individual Freedom. Westminster: Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group. ISBN   978-0-679-73319-5.
  51. Benn, S. (1967). "Egalitarianism and Equal Consideration of Interests". In Pennock, J. R.; Chapman, J. (eds.). Nomos IX: Equality. New York: Atherton Press. pp. 69–71.
  52. Cohen, C. (1986-10-02). "The case for the use of animals in biomedical research". The New England Journal of Medicine. 315 (14): 865–870. doi:10.1056/NEJM198610023151405. ISSN   0028-4793. PMID   3748104.
  53. 1 2 Scanlon, Thomas (2000). What we owe to each other (1st ed.). Cambridge, Mass: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. pp. 185–186. ISBN   978-0-674-00423-8.
  54. Finnis, John (1995). "The Fragile Case for Euthanasia: A Reply to John Harris". In Keown, John (ed.). Euthanasia Examined: Ethical, Clinical and Legal Perspectives. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
  55. Korsgaard, Christine M. (2018-05-24). Fellow Creatures. Oxford Scholarship Online. Vol. 1. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780198753858.001.0001. ISBN   978-0-19-875385-8.
  56. Sumner, L. W. (1981). Abortion and Moral Theory. Princeton University Press. pp. 97–101. doi:10.2307/j.ctt7zvdmc. JSTOR   j.ctt7zvdmc.
  57. Little, Margaret Olivia (2008). "Abortion and the Margins of Personhood". Rutgers Law Journal. 39: 332, 339–341, 348.
  58. Nozick, Robert (2000). Socratic puzzles (3. print ed.). Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press. pp. 303–310. ISBN   978-0-674-81654-1.
  59. Kittay, Eva Feder (2005). "At the Margins of Moral Personhood". Ethics. 116 (1): 100–131. doi:10.1086/454366. ISSN   0014-1704. JSTOR   10.1086/454366. PMID   16578953.
  60. Warren, Mary Anne (1997). Moral status : obligations to persons and other living things. Internet Archive. Oxford : Clarendon Press. p. 176. ISBN   978-0-19-158815-0.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)
  61. Gilbert, Margaret (2018). Rights and Demands: A Foundational Inquiry. Oxford University Press. pp. 332, 341–342. ISBN   978-0-19-881376-7.
  62. McMahan, Jeff (2005). "Our Fellow Creatures". The Journal of Ethics. 9 (3/4): 355. doi:10.1007/s10892-005-3512-2. ISSN   1382-4554. JSTOR   25115832.
  63. Jaworska, Agnieszka; Tannenbaum, Julie (2014). "Person-Rearing Relationships as a Key to Higher Moral Status". Ethics. 124 (2): 242–271. doi:10.1086/673431. ISSN   0014-1704. JSTOR   10.1086/673431.
  64. Brennan, Andrew; Center for Environmental Philosophy, The University of North Texas (1984). "The Moral Standing of Natural Objects". Environmental Ethics. 6 (1): 44, 56. doi:10.5840/enviroethics19846118. ISSN   0163-4275.
  65. Katz, Eric (1997). Nature as Subject: Human Obligation and Natural Community. Bloomsbury Publishing PLC. pp. 129–131. ISBN   978-0-8476-8304-8.
  66. Elliot, Robert, ed. (1997). Faking nature: the ethics of environmental restoration. Environmental philosophies series. London New York: Routledge. p. 80. ISBN   978-0-415-11140-9.
  67. Leopold, Aldo (1972). A Sand county almanac and sketches here and there. New York usw: OUP. ISBN   978-0-19-500777-0.
  68. Callicott, J. Baird; Center for Environmental Philosophy, The University of North Texas (1980). "Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair". Environmental Ethics. 2 (4): 311–338. doi:10.5840/enviroethics19802424. ISSN   0163-4275.
  69. Oestigaard, Terje (2021-06-10). "Prehistoric Ethics". Current Swedish Archaeology. 26 (1): 65–70. doi:10.37718/csa.2016.06. ISSN   2002-3901.
  70. Gordijn, Bert; ten Have, Henk (2021-09-01). "Ethical (mis)use of prehistory". Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy. 24 (3): 303–304. doi:10.1007/s11019-021-10041-4. ISSN   1572-8633. PMID   34241744.
  71. Committee, The Hastings Center Bioethics Timeline. "The Hastings Center Bioethics Timeline". The Hastings Center for Bioethics. Retrieved 2025-08-14.
  72. Open Philanthropy (March 2021). "Rethink Priorities — Moral Patienthood and Moral Weight Research" . Retrieved December 1, 2023.
  73. Tiku, Nitasha (June 11, 2022). "The Google engineer who thinks the company's AI has come to life" . The Washington Post . ISSN   0190-8286. Archived from the original on June 11, 2022. Retrieved June 12, 2022.
  74. Luscombe, Richard (June 12, 2022). "Google engineer put on leave after saying AI chatbot has become sentient". The Guardian . ISSN   0261-3077. Archived from the original on June 12, 2022. Retrieved June 18, 2022.
  75. Harris, Jamie; Anthis, Jacy Reese (2021-08-09). "The Moral Consideration of Artificial Entities: A Literature Review". Science and Engineering Ethics. 27 (4): 53. doi:10.1007/s11948-021-00331-8. ISSN   1471-5546. PMC   8352798 . PMID   34370075.