Moral patienthood [1] (also called moral patience, [2] moral patiency, [3] moral status [4] [5] , and moral considerability [6] ) is the state of being eligible for moral consideration by a moral agent. [4] In other words, the morality of an action depends at least partly on how it affects those beings that possess moral patienthood, which are called moral patients [7] or morally considerable beings. [6]
Notions of moral patienthood in non-human animals [8] [9] and artificial entities [10] [11] have been academically explored. More detail on the ethical treatment of nonhuman animals, specifically, can be seen at the Animal rights article.
Most authors define moral patients as "beings that are appropriate objects of direct moral concern". [4] This category may include moral agents, and usually does include them. For instance, Charles Taliaferro says: "A moral agent is someone who can bring about events in ways that are praiseworthy or subject to blame. A moral patient is someone who can be morally mistreated. All moral agents are moral patients, but not all moral patients (human babies, some nonhuman animals) are moral agents." [12]
Some authors use the term in a more narrow sense, according to which moral patients are "beings who are appropriate objects of direct moral concern but are not (also) moral agents". [4] Tom Regan's The Case for Animal Rights used the term in this narrow sense. [13] This usage was shared by other authors who cited Regan, such as Nicholas Bunnin and Jiyuan Yu's Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy, [13] Dinesh Wadiwel's The War Against Animals, [14] and the Encyclopedia of Population. [15] These authors did not think that moral agents are not eligible for moral consideration, they simply had a different view on how a "moral patient" is defined.
The paper by Luciano Floridi and J.W. Sanders, On the Morality of Artificial Agents, defines moral agents as "all entities that can in principle qualify as sources of moral action", and defines moral patients, in accordance with the common usage, as "all entities that can in principle qualify as receivers of moral action". [16] However, they note that besides inclusion of agents within patients, other relationships of moral patienthood with moral agency are possible. Marian Quigley's Encyclopedia of Information Ethics and Security summarizes the possibilities that they gave:
How can we characterize the relationship between ethical agents and patients? According to Floridi and Sanders (2004), there are five logical relationships between the class of ethical agents and the class of patients: (1) agents and patients are disjoint, (2) patients can be a proper subset of agents, (3) agents and patients can intersect, (4) agents and patients can be equal, or (5) agents can be a proper subset of patients. Medical ethics, bioethics, and environmental ethics "typify" agents and patients when the patient is specified as any form of life. Animals, for example, can be moral patients but not moral agents. Also, there are ethics that typify moral agenthood to include legal entities (especially human-based entities) such as companies, agencies, and artificial agents, in addition to humans. [17]
Mireille Hildebrandt notes that Floridi and Sanders, in their paper, spoke of "damage" instead of "harm", and that in doing so, they "avoid the usual assumption that an entity must be sentient to count as a patient." [18]
Moral patienthood (or full moral patienthood, in theories which allow for partial moral status) has been alleged (by the cited sources) to imply the following moral obligations: [5]
Moral patienthood is, by itself, an independent reason to have these moral obligations; there may be other reasons to have these obligations, but merely having these obligations towards a being does not imply that the being is a moral patient. [5] (For instance, supposing that there is a moral obligation to keep promises, someone may acquire these moral obligations toward any being by simply promising to treat it like a moral patient.)
Moral patienthood has been claimed, in the literature, to be grounded in various properties. [5] [26]
Property | Definition | Sources |
---|---|---|
Sophisticated cognitive capacities | Moral patienthood is grounded in very sophisticated intellectual/emotional capacities (e.g., autonomy, self-awareness, valuing, caring). | Kant ( Groundwork ) [27] ; Quinn [24] ; McMahan [20] ; Tooley [28] ; Singer [29] ; Buss [30] ; Theunissen [31] ; Feinberg [19] ; Jaworska [22] |
Capacity to develop sophisticated cognitive capacities | Potential for such capacities (a "future like ours" or similar) grounds moral patienthood (or some status/enhancement). | Stone [32] ; Marquis [33] [34] ; Harman [35] [36] ; Steinbock [37] ; Boonin [38] ; Feinberg [19] ; Wilkins [39] ; McInerney [40] |
Rudimentary cognitive capacities | Lower the bar to sentience, interests, basic emotions, or consciousness as sufficient for (full) status. | Wood and O'Neill [41] ; Regan [42] ; Singer [29] ; DeGrazia [43] [44] ; Rachels [45] ; Harman [36] ; McMahan [20] ; Taylor [46] ; Naess [47] ; Johnson [48] ; Anderson [49] |
Member of cognitively sophisticated species | Moral patienthood via (i) being human or (ii) belonging to any cognitively sophisticated species/kind. | Feinberg [19] ; Dworkin [50] ; Benn [51] ; Cohen [52] ; Scanlon [53] ; Finnis [54] ; Korsgaard [55] ; Sumner [56] ; McMahan [20] ; McMahan [21] ; Little [57] ; Quinn [24] |
Special relationships | Strong reasons (akin to moral patienthood) grounded in species/community, parent–child, or other special ties. | Nozick [58] ; Scanlon [53] ; Kittay [59] ; Steinbock [37] ; Quinn [24] ; Warren [60] ; Anderson [49] ; Gilbert [61] ; McMahan [62] [20] |
Incompletely realized sophisticated cognitive capacities | Having such capacities incompletely realized (via mentor-guided activities/standards) can elevate status (possibly up to full moral patienthood). | Jaworska & Tannenbaum [63] |
Not being designed by anyone to fulfill any purpose | The idea that an entity's not having been designed for a purpose grounds being treated as an end (and thus having moral status or some degree of it). | Brennan [64] ; Katz [65] |
Naturalness (unaltered by humans) | The claim that being natural or unaltered by human intervention confers intrinsic value and thus some moral status. | Elliot [66] |
Harmony and beauty (aesthetic value) of ecosystems | Appeals to harmony, beauty, or aesthetic value of ecosystems (or nature generally) as grounds for moral considerability or status. | Leopold ( A Sand County Almanac ) [67] ; Callicott [68] |
Moral patienthood may have existed since prehistory, [69] [70] but most discussions of it as a distinct concept happened since the 1970s. News events where sources explicitly raised the issue of moral patienthood outside of philosophy are also added, except where they related to animals, since those are covered in the article "History of animal rights".
Philosophical writings from this period:
In 1969, the Hastings Center for Bioethics was founded. [71]
Philosophical writings from this period:
Philosophical writings from this period:
Philosophical writings from this period:
Philosophical writings from this period:
Philosophical writings from this period:
In 2021, Open Philanthropy recommended a grant of $315,500 to "support research related to moral patienthood and moral weight." [72]
In 2022, Google engineer Blake Lemoine publicly claimed that LaMDA (a language model) was "sentient". [73] [74]
Philosophical writings from this period:
{{cite book}}
: |website=
ignored (help){{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)