Quantum cognition

Last updated

Quantum cognition uses the mathematical formalism of quantum probability theory to model psychology phenomena when classical probability theory fails. [1] The field focuses on modeling phenomena in cognitive science that have resisted traditional techniques or where traditional models seem to have reached a barrier (e.g., human memory), [2] and modeling preferences in decision theory that seem paradoxical from a traditional rational point of view (e.g., preference reversals). [3] Since the use of a quantum-theoretic framework is for modeling purposes, the identification of quantum structures in cognitive phenomena does not presuppose the existence of microscopic quantum processes in the human brain. [4] [5]

Contents

Quantum cognition can be applied to model cognitive phenomena such as information processing [6] by the human brain, language, decision making, [7] human memory, concepts and conceptual reasoning, human judgment, and perception. [8] [9] [10]

Challenges for classical probability theory

Classical probability theory is a rational approach to inference which does not easily explain some observations of human inference in psychology. Some cases where quantum probability theory has advantages include the conjunction fallacy, the disjunction fallacy, the failures of the sure-thing principle, and question-order bias in judgement. [1] :752

Conjunction fallacy

If participants in a psychology experiment are told about "Linda", described as looking like a feminist but not like a bank teller, then asked to rank the probability, that Linda is feminist, a bank teller or a feminist and a bank teller, they respond with values that indicate:

Rational classical probability theory makes the incorrect prediction: it expects humans to rank the conjunction less probable than the bank teller option. Many variations of this experiment demonstrate that the fallacy represents human cognition in this case and not an artifact of one presentation. [1] :753

Quantum cognition models this probability-estimation scenario with quantum probability theory which always ranks sequential probability, , greater than the direct probability, . The idea is that a person's understanding of "bank teller" is affected by the context of the question involving "feminist". [1] :753 The two questions are "incompatible": to treat them with classical theory would require separate reasoning steps. [11]

Main subjects of research

Quantum-like models of information processing

The quantum cognition concept is based on the observation that various cognitive phenomena are more adequately described by quantum probability theory than by the classical probability theory (see examples below). Thus, the quantum formalism is considered an operational formalism that describes non-classical processing of probabilistic data.

Here, contextuality is the key word (see the monograph of Khrennikov for detailed representation of this viewpoint). [8] Quantum mechanics is fundamentally contextual. [12] Quantum systems do not have objective properties which can be defined independently of measurement context. As has been pointed out by Niels Bohr, the whole experimental arrangement must be taken into account. Contextuality implies existence of incompatible mental variables, violation of the classical law of total probability, and constructive or destructive interference effects. Thus, the quantum cognition approach can be considered an attempt to formalize contextuality of mental processes, by using the mathematical apparatus of quantum mechanics.

Decision making

Suppose a person is given an opportunity to play two rounds of the following gamble: a coin toss will determine whether the subject wins $200 or loses $100. Suppose the subject has decided to play the first round, and does so. Some subjects are then given the result (win or lose) of the first round, while other subjects are not yet given any information about the results. The experimenter then asks whether the subject wishes to play the second round. Performing this experiment with real subjects gives the following results:

  1. When subjects believe they won the first round, the majority of subjects choose to play again on the second round.
  2. When subjects believe they lost the first round, the majority of subjects choose to play again on the second round.

Given these two separate choices, according to the sure thing principle of rational decision theory, they should also play the second round even if they don't know or think about the outcome of the first round. [13] But, experimentally, when subjects are not told the results of the first round, the majority of them decline to play a second round. [14] This finding violates the law of total probability, yet it can be explained as a quantum interference effect in a manner similar to the explanation for the results from double-slit experiment in quantum physics. [9] [15] [16] Similar violations of the sure-thing principle are seen in empirical studies of the Prisoner's Dilemma and have likewise been modeled in terms of quantum interference. [17]

The above deviations from classical rational expectations in agents’ decisions under uncertainty produce well known paradoxes in behavioral economics, that is, the Allais, Ellsberg and Machina paradoxes. [18] [19] [20] These deviations can be explained if one assumes that the overall conceptual landscape influences the subject's choice in a neither predictable nor controllable way. A decision process is thus an intrinsically contextual process, hence it cannot be modeled in a single Kolmogorovian probability space, which justifies the employment of quantum probability models in decision theory. More explicitly, the paradoxical situations above can be represented in a unified Hilbert space formalism where human behavior under uncertainty is explained in terms of genuine quantum aspects, namely, superposition, interference, contextuality and incompatibility. [21] [22] [23] [16]

Considering automated decision making, quantum decision trees have different structure compared to classical decision trees. Data can be analyzed to see if a quantum decision tree model fits the data better. [24]

Human probability judgments

Quantum probability provides a new way to explain human probability judgment errors including the conjunction and disjunction errors. [25] A conjunction error occurs when a person judges the probability of a likely event L and an unlikely event U to be greater than the unlikely event U; a disjunction error occurs when a person judges the probability of a likely event L to be greater than the probability of the likely event L or an unlikely event U. Quantum probability theory is a generalization of Bayesian probability theory because it is based on a set of von Neumann axioms that relax some of the classic Kolmogorov axioms. [26] The quantum model introduces a new fundamental concept to cognition—the compatibility versus incompatibility of questions and the effect this can have on the sequential order of judgments. Quantum probability provides a simple account of conjunction and disjunction errors as well as many other findings such as order effects on probability judgments. [27] [28] [29]

The liar paradox - The contextual influence of a human subject on the truth behavior of a cognitive entity is explicitly exhibited by the so-called liar paradox, that is, the truth value of a sentence like "this sentence is false". One can show that the true-false state of this paradox is represented in a complex Hilbert space, while the typical oscillations between true and false are dynamically described by the Schrödinger equation. [30] [31]

Knowledge representation

Concepts are basic cognitive phenomena, which provide the content for inference, explanation, and language understanding. Cognitive psychology has researched different approaches for understanding concepts including exemplars, prototypes, and neural networks, and different fundamental problems have been identified, such as the experimentally tested non classical behavior for the conjunction and disjunction of concepts, more specifically the Pet-Fish problem or guppy effect, [32] and the overextension and underextension of typicality and membership weight for conjunction and disjunction. [33] [34] By and large, quantum cognition has drawn on quantum theory in three ways to model concepts.

  1. Exploit the contextuality of quantum theory to account for the contextuality of concepts in cognition and language and the phenomenon of emergent properties when concepts combine [4] [35] [36] [37] [38]
  2. Use quantum entanglement to model the semantics of concept combinations in a non-decompositional way, and to account for the emergent properties/associates/inferences in relation to concept combinations [39]
  3. Use quantum superposition to account for the emergence of a new concept when concepts are combined, and as a consequence put forward an explanatory model for the Pet-Fish problem situation, and the overextension and underextension of membership weights for the conjunction and disjunction of concepts. [27] [35] [36]

The large amount of data collected by Hampton [33] [34] on the combination of two concepts can be modeled in a specific quantum-theoretic framework in Fock space where the observed deviations from classical set (fuzzy set) theory, the above-mentioned over- and under- extension of membership weights, are explained in terms of contextual interactions, superposition, interference, entanglement and emergence. [27] [40] [41] [42] And, more, a cognitive test on a specific concept combination has been performed which directly reveals, through the violation of Bell's inequalities, quantum entanglement between the component concepts. [43] [44]

Semantic analysis and information retrieval

The research in (iv) had a deep impact on the understanding and initial development of a formalism to obtain semantic information when dealing with concepts, their combinations and variable contexts in a corpus of unstructured documents. This conundrum of natural language processing (NLP) and information retrieval (IR) on the web – and data bases in general – can be addressed using the mathematical formalism of quantum theory. As basic steps, (a) K. Van Rijsbergen introduced a quantum structure approach to IR, [45] (b) Widdows and Peters utilised a quantum logical negation for a concrete search system, [38] [46] and Aerts and Czachor identified quantum structure in semantic space theories, such as latent semantic analysis. [47] Since then, the employment of techniques and procedures induced from the mathematical formalisms of quantum theory – Hilbert space, quantum logic and probability, non-commutative algebras, etc. – in fields such as IR and NLP, has produced significant results. [48]

History

Ideas for applying the formalisms of quantum theory to cognition first appeared in the 1990s by Diederik Aerts and his collaborators Jan Broekaert, Sonja Smets and Liane Gabora, by Harald Atmanspacher, Robert Bordley, and Andrei Khrennikov. A special issue on Quantum Cognition and Decision appeared in the Journal of Mathematical Psychology (2009, vol 53.), which planted a flag for the field. A few books related to quantum cognition have been published including those by Khrennikov (2004, 2010), Ivancivic and Ivancivic (2010), Busemeyer and Bruza (2012), E. Conte (2012). The first Quantum Interaction workshop was held at Stanford in 2007 organized by Peter Bruza, William Lawless, C. J. van Rijsbergen, and Don Sofge as part of the 2007 AAAI Spring Symposium Series. This was followed by workshops at Oxford in 2008, Saarbrücken in 2009, at the 2010 AAAI Fall Symposium Series held in Washington, D.C., 2011 in Aberdeen, 2012 in Paris, and 2013 in Leicester. Tutorials also were presented annually beginning in 2007 until 2013 at the annual meeting of the Cognitive Science Society. A Special Issue on Quantum models of Cognition appeared in 2013 in the journal Topics in Cognitive Science .

See also

Related Research Articles

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Cognitive science</span> Interdisciplinary scientific study of cognitive processes

Cognitive science is the interdisciplinary, scientific study of the mind and its processes. It examines the nature, the tasks, and the functions of cognition. Mental faculties of concern to cognitive scientists include language, perception, memory, attention, reasoning, and emotion; to understand these faculties, cognitive scientists borrow from fields such as linguistics, psychology, artificial intelligence, philosophy, neuroscience, and anthropology. The typical analysis of cognitive science spans many levels of organization, from learning and decision to logic and planning; from neural circuitry to modular brain organization. One of the fundamental concepts of cognitive science is that "thinking can best be understood in terms of representational structures in the mind and computational procedures that operate on those structures."

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Cognitive bias</span> Systematic pattern of deviation from norm or rationality in judgment

A cognitive bias is a systematic pattern of deviation from norm or rationality in judgment. Individuals create their own "subjective reality" from their perception of the input. An individual's construction of reality, not the objective input, may dictate their behavior in the world. Thus, cognitive biases may sometimes lead to perceptual distortion, inaccurate judgment, illogical interpretation, and irrationality.

Liane Gabora is a professor of psychology at the University of British Columbia - Okanagan. She is known for her theory of the "Origin of the modern mind through conceptual closure," which built on her earlier work on "Autocatalytic closure in a cognitive system: A tentative scenario for the origin of culture."

An interpretation of quantum mechanics is an attempt to explain how the mathematical theory of quantum mechanics might correspond to experienced reality. Although quantum mechanics has held up to rigorous and extremely precise tests in an extraordinarily broad range of experiments, there exist a number of contending schools of thought over their interpretation. These views on interpretation differ on such fundamental questions as whether quantum mechanics is deterministic or stochastic, local or non-local, which elements of quantum mechanics can be considered real, and what the nature of measurement is, among other matters.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Decision theory</span> Branch of applied probability theory

Decision theory is a branch of applied probability theory and analytic philosophy concerned with the theory of making decisions based on assigning probabilities to various factors and assigning numerical consequences to the outcome.

In quantum mechanics, the measurement problem is the problem of definite outcomes: quantum systems have superpositions but quantum measurements only give one definite result.

In the interpretation of quantum mechanics, a local hidden-variable theory is a hidden-variable theory that satisfies the principle of locality. These models attempt to account for the probabilistic features of quantum mechanics via the mechanism of underlying, but inaccessible variables, with the additional requirement that distant events be statistically independent.

Prototype theory is a theory of categorization in cognitive science, particularly in psychology and cognitive linguistics, in which there is a graded degree of belonging to a conceptual category, and some members are more central than others. It emerged in 1971 with the work of psychologist Eleanor Rosch, and it has been described as a "Copernican Revolution" in the theory of categorization for its departure from the traditional Aristotelian categories. It has been criticized by those that still endorse the traditional theory of categories, like linguist Eugenio Coseriu and other proponents of the structural semantics paradigm.

In mathematical physics, Gleason's theorem shows that the rule one uses to calculate probabilities in quantum physics, the Born rule, can be derived from the usual mathematical representation of measurements in quantum physics together with the assumption of non-contextuality. Andrew M. Gleason first proved the theorem in 1957, answering a question posed by George W. Mackey, an accomplishment that was historically significant for the role it played in showing that wide classes of hidden-variable theories are inconsistent with quantum physics. Multiple variations have been proven in the years since. Gleason's theorem is of particular importance for the field of quantum logic and its attempt to find a minimal set of mathematical axioms for quantum theory.

Decision field theory (DFT) is a dynamic-cognitive approach to human decision making. It is a cognitive model that describes how people actually make decisions rather than a rational or normative theory that prescribes what people should or ought to do. It is also a dynamic model of decision-making rather than a static model, because it describes how a person's preferences evolve across time until a decision is reached rather than assuming a fixed state of preference. The preference evolution process is mathematically represented as a stochastic process called a diffusion process. It is used to predict how humans make decisions under uncertainty, how decisions change under time pressure, and how choice context changes preferences. This model can be used to predict not only the choices that are made but also decision or response times.

Mioara Mugur-Schächter is a French-Romanian physicist, specialized in fundamental quantum mechanics, probability theory and theory of communication of information. She is also an epistemologist (methodologist) of generation of scientific knowledge. As a professor of theoretical physics at the University of Reims, she founded the Laboratory of Quantum Mechanics and Structures of Information which she directed until 1994. She is currently president of the Centre pour la Synthèse d'une Épistémologie Formalisée (CeSEF).

Quantum finance is an interdisciplinary research field, applying theories and methods developed by quantum physicists and economists in order to solve problems in finance. It is a branch of econophysics. Today several financial applications like fraud detection, portfolio optimization, product recommendation and stock price prediction are being explored using quantum computing.

José Acacio de Barros is a Brazilian-American physicist and philosopher with contributions to the foundations of quantum mechanics, quantum cosmology, and quantum cognition. Dr. de Barros received his PhD in Physics from the Centro Brasileiro de Pesquisas Fisicas (CBPF) in 1991 under the supervision of Francisco Antonio Doria and Antonio Fernandes da Fonseca Teixeira. Since 2007 he has been in the Liberal Studies faculty of San Francisco State University. Before going to San Francisco, he was an associate professor of physics at the Federal University at Juiz de Fora, Brazil, and he was a visiting associate professor at the Center for the Study of Language and Information at Stanford University, and has also held visiting positions at the Centro Brasileiro de Pesquisas Fisicas. Dr. de Barros has been a long-term collaborator of Philosopher Patrick Suppes, with whom he published extensively on the foundations of quantum mechanics and joint probabilities. Among his most influential work is his joint research with Nelson Pinto-Neto, in which Bohm's interpretation of quantum mechanics was applied to quantum cosmology, paving the way for bouncing models using realistic interpretation of quantum mechanics. His recent work attempts to give a neurophysiological foundation to quantum-like effects in psychology. He is also among the main proponents, in collaboration with Gary Oas, of the use of negative probabilities to understand quantum systems.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Quantum Bayesianism</span> Interpretation of quantum mechanics

In physics and the philosophy of physics, quantum Bayesianism is a collection of related approaches to the interpretation of quantum mechanics, the most prominent of which is QBism. QBism is an interpretation that takes an agent's actions and experiences as the central concerns of the theory. QBism deals with common questions in the interpretation of quantum theory about the nature of wavefunction superposition, quantum measurement, and entanglement. According to QBism, many, but not all, aspects of the quantum formalism are subjective in nature. For example, in this interpretation, a quantum state is not an element of reality—instead, it represents the degrees of belief an agent has about the possible outcomes of measurements. For this reason, some philosophers of science have deemed QBism a form of anti-realism. The originators of the interpretation disagree with this characterization, proposing instead that the theory more properly aligns with a kind of realism they call "participatory realism", wherein reality consists of more than can be captured by any putative third-person account of it.

Quantum contextuality is a feature of the phenomenology of quantum mechanics whereby measurements of quantum observables cannot simply be thought of as revealing pre-existing values. Any attempt to do so in a realistic hidden-variable theory leads to values that are dependent upon the choice of the other (compatible) observables which are simultaneously measured. More formally, the measurement result of a quantum observable is dependent upon which other commuting observables are within the same measurement set.

Jerome Robert Busemeyer is a Distinguished Professor at Indiana University Bloomington in the Department of Psychological & Brain Sciences and Cognitive Science Program.

Intuitive statistics, or folk statistics, is the cognitive phenomenon where organisms use data to make generalizations and predictions about the world. This can be a small amount of sample data or training instances, which in turn contribute to inductive inferences about either population-level properties, future data, or both. Inferences can involve revising hypotheses, or beliefs, in light of probabilistic data that inform and motivate future predictions. The informal tendency for cognitive animals to intuitively generate statistical inferences, when formalized with certain axioms of probability theory, constitutes statistics as an academic discipline.

Quantum foundations is a discipline of science that seeks to understand the most counter-intuitive aspects of quantum theory, reformulate it and even propose new generalizations thereof. Contrary to other physical theories, such as general relativity, the defining axioms of quantum theory are quite ad hoc, with no obvious physical intuition. While they lead to the right experimental predictions, they do not come with a mental picture of the world where they fit.

Quantum social science is an emerging field of interdisciplinary research which draws parallels between quantum physics and the social sciences. Although there is no settled consensus on a single approach, a unifying theme is that, while the social sciences have long modelled themselves on mechanistic science, they can learn much from quantum ideas such as complementarity and entanglement. Some authors are motivated by quantum mind theories that the brain, and therefore human interactions, are literally based on quantum processes, while others are more interested in taking advantage of the quantum toolkit to simulate social behaviours which elude classical treatment. Quantum ideas have been particularly influential in psychology but are starting to affect other areas such as international relations and diplomacy in what one 2018 paper called a "quantum turn in the social sciences".

Emmanuel Haven is an academic, author and researcher. He previously held a personal Chair at the University of Leicester (UK) and is currently full professor and the Dr. Alex Faseruk Chair in Financial Management at the Faculty of Business Administration, Memorial University.

References

  1. 1 2 3 4 Pothos, Emmanuel M.; Busemeyer, Jerome R. (2022-01-04). "Quantum Cognition". Annual Review of Psychology. 73 (1): 749–778. doi:10.1146/annurev-psych-033020-123501. ISSN   0066-4308. PMID   34546804.
  2. Bruza, P.; Kitto, K.; Nelson, D.; McEvoy, C. (2009). "Is there something quantum-like about the human mental lexicon?". Journal of Mathematical Psychology. 53 (5): 362–377. doi:10.1016/j.jmp.2009.04.004. PMC   2834425 . PMID   20224806.
  3. Lambert Mogiliansky, A.; Zamir, S.; Zwirn, H. (2009). "Type indeterminacy: A model of the KT (Kahneman–Tversky)-man". Journal of Mathematical Psychology. 53 (5): 349–361. arXiv: physics/0604166 . doi:10.1016/j.jmp.2009.01.001. S2CID   15463046.
  4. 1 2 de Barros, J. A.; Suppes, P. (2009). "Quantum mechanics, interference, and the brain". Journal of Mathematical Psychology. 53 (5): 306–313. doi:10.1016/j.jmp.2009.03.005.
  5. Khrennikov, A. (2008). "The Quantum-Like Brain on the Cognitive and Subcognitive Time Scales". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 15 (7): 39–77. ISSN   1355-8250.
  6. Pothos, E. M.; Busemeyer, J. R. (2013). "Can quantum probability provide a new direction for cognitive modeling". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 36 (3): 255–274. doi:10.1017/S0140525X12001525. PMID   23673021. S2CID   53130527.
  7. Aerts, D.; Aerts, S. (1994). "Applications of quantum statistics in psychological studies of decision processes". Foundations of Science. 1: 85–97. doi:10.1007/BF00208726.
  8. 1 2 Khrennikov, A. (2010). Ubiquitous Quantum Structure: from Psychology to Finances. Springer. ISBN   978-3-642-42495-3.
  9. 1 2 Busemeyer, J.; Bruza, P. (2012). Quantum Models of Cognition and Decision. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN   978-1-107-01199-1.
  10. Wang, Z.; Busemeyer, J. R.; Atmanspacher, H.; Pothos, E. M. (2013). "The potential of using quantum theory to build models of cognition". Topics in Cognitive Science. 5 (4): 672–688. doi: 10.1111/tops.12043 . PMID   24027215.
  11. Pothos, Emmanuel M.; Busemeyer, Jerome R.; Shiffrin, Richard M.; Yearsley, James M. (July 2017). "The rational status of quantum cognition". Journal of Experimental Psychology: General. 146 (7): 968–987. doi:10.1037/xge0000312. ISSN   1939-2222. PMID   28447840.
  12. Khrennikov, A. (2009). Contextual Approach to Quantum Formalism. Fundamental Theories of Physics. Vol. 160. Springer. ISBN   978-1-4020-9592-4.
  13. Savage, L. J. (1954). The Foundations of Statistics. John Wiley & Sons.
  14. Tversky, A.; Shafir, E. (1992). "The disjunction effect in choice under uncertainty". Psychological Science. 3 (5): 305–309. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.1992.tb00678.x. S2CID   144374616.
  15. Pothos, E. M.; Busemeyer, J. R. (2009). "A quantum probability explanation for violations of 'rational' decision theory". Proceedings of the Royal Society. B: Biological Sciences. 276 (1665): 2171–2178. doi:10.1098/rspb.2009.0121. PMC   2677606 . PMID   19324743.
  16. 1 2 Yukalov, V. I.; Sornette, D. (21 February 2010). "Decision theory with prospect interference and entanglement" (PDF). Theory and Decision. 70 (3): 283–328. doi:10.1007/s11238-010-9202-y. hdl: 20.500.11850/29070 . S2CID   15377072.
  17. Musser, George (16 October 2012). "A New Enlightenment". Scientific American. 307 (5): 76–81. doi:10.1038/scientificamerican1112-76.
  18. Allais, M. (1953). "Le comportement de l'homme rationnel devant le risque: Critique des postulats et axiomes de l'ecole Americaine". Econometrica . 21 (4): 503–546. doi:10.2307/1907921. JSTOR   1907921.
  19. Ellsberg, D. (1961). "Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms" (PDF). Quarterly Journal of Economics . 75 (4): 643–669. doi:10.2307/1884324. JSTOR   1884324.
  20. Machina, M. J. (2009). "Risk, Ambiguity, and the Rank-Dependence Axioms". American Economic Review . 99 (1): 385–392. doi:10.1257/aer.99.1.385.
  21. Aerts, D.; Sozzo, S.; Tapia, J. (2012). "A quantum model for the Ellsberg and Machina paradoxes". In Busemeyer, J.; Dubois, F.; Lambert-Mogilansky, A. (eds.). Quantum Interaction 2012. LNCS. Vol. 7620. Berlin: Springer. pp. 48–59.
  22. Aerts, D.; Sozzo, S.; Tapia, J. (2014). "Identifying quantum structures in the Ellsberg paradox". International Journal of Theoretical Physics. 53 (10): 3666–3682. arXiv: 1302.3850 . Bibcode:2014IJTP...53.3666A. doi:10.1007/s10773-014-2086-9. S2CID   119158347.
  23. La Mura, P. (2009). "Projective expected utility". Journal of Mathematical Psychology. 53 (5): 408–414. arXiv: 0802.3300 . doi:10.1016/j.jmp.2009.02.001. S2CID   12099816.
  24. Kak, S. (2017). Incomplete Information and Quantum Decision Trees. IEEE International Conference on Systems, Man, and Cybernetics. Banff, Canada, October. doi:10.1109/SMC.2017.8122615.
  25. Tversky, A.; Kahneman, D. (1983). "Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: The conjunction fallacy in probability judgment". Psychological Review. 90 (4): 293–315. doi:10.1037/0033-295X.90.4.293.
  26. Bond, Rachael L.; He, Yang-Hui; Ormerod, Thomas C. (2018). "A quantum framework for likelihood ratios". International Journal of Quantum Information . 16 (1): 1850002. arXiv: 1508.00936 . Bibcode:2018IJQI...1650002B. doi:10.1142/s0219749918500028. ISSN   0219-7499. S2CID   85523100.
  27. 1 2 3 Aerts, D. (2009). "Quantum structure in cognition". Journal of Mathematical Psychology. 53 (5): 314–348. arXiv: 0805.3850 . doi:10.1016/j.jmp.2009.04.005. S2CID   14436506.
  28. Busemeyer, J. R.; Pothos, E.; Franco, R.; Trueblood, J. S. (2011). "A quantum theoretical explanation for probability judgment 'errors'" (PDF). Psychological Review. 118 (2): 193–218. doi:10.1037/a0022542. PMID   21480739.
  29. Trueblood, J. S.; Busemeyer, J. R. (2011). "A quantum probability account of order effects in inference". Cognitive Science. 35 (8): 1518–1552. doi: 10.1111/j.1551-6709.2011.01197.x . PMID   21951058.
  30. Aerts, D.; Broekaert, J.; Smets, S. (1999). "The liar paradox in a quantum mechanical perspective". Foundations of Science. 4 (2): 115–132. doi:10.1023/A:1009610326206. S2CID   119404170.
  31. Aerts, D.; Aerts, S.; Broekaert, J.; Gabora, L. (2000). "The violation of Bell inequalities in the macroworld". Foundations of Physics. 30 (9): 1387–1414. arXiv: quant-ph/0007044 . Bibcode:2000quant.ph..7044A. doi:10.1023/A:1026449716544. S2CID   3262876.
  32. Osherson, D. N.; Smith, E. E. (1981). "On the adequacy of prototype theory as a theory of concepts". Cognition. 9 (1): 35–58. doi:10.1016/0010-0277(81)90013-5. PMID   7196818. S2CID   10482356.
  33. 1 2 Hampton, J. A. (1988). "Overextension of conjunctive concepts: Evidence for a unitary model for concept typicality and class inclusion". Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition. 14 (1): 12–32. doi:10.1037/0278-7393.14.1.12.
  34. 1 2 Hampton, J. A. (1988). "Disjunction of natural concepts". Memory & Cognition. 16 (6): 579–591. doi: 10.3758/BF03197059 . PMID   3193889.
  35. 1 2 Aerts, D.; Gabora, L. (2005). "A state-context-property model of concepts and their combinations I: The structure of the sets of contexts and properties". Kybernetes. 34 (1&2): 167–191. arXiv: quant-ph/0402207 . doi:10.1108/03684920510575799. S2CID   15124657.
  36. 1 2 Aerts, D.; Gabora, L. (2005). "A state-context-property model of concepts and their combinations II: A Hilbert space representation". Kybernetes. 34 (1&2): 192–221. arXiv: quant-ph/0402205 . doi:10.1108/03684920510575807. S2CID   13988880.
  37. Gabora, L.; Aerts, D. (2002). "Contextualizing concepts using a mathematical generalization of the quantum formalism". Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence . 14 (4): 327–358. arXiv: quant-ph/0205161 . doi:10.1080/09528130210162253. S2CID   10643452.
  38. 1 2 Widdows, D.; Peters, S. (2003). Word Vectors and Quantum Logic: Experiments with negation and disjunction. Eighth Mathematics of Language Conference. pp. 141–154.
  39. Bruza, P. D.; Cole, R. J. (2005). "Quantum logic of semantic space: An exploratory investigation of context effects in practical reasoning". In Artemov, S.; Barringer, H.; d'Avila Garcez, A. S.; Lamb, L. C.; Woods, J. (eds.). We Will Show Them: Essays in Honour of Dov Gabbay. College Publications. ISBN   1-904987-11-7.
  40. Aerts, D. (2009). "Quantum particles as conceptual entities: A possible explanatory framework for quantum theory". Foundations of Science. 14 (4): 361–411. arXiv: 1004.2530 . doi:10.1007/s10699-009-9166-y. S2CID   119209842.
  41. Aerts, D.; Broekaert, J.; Gabora, L.; Sozzo, S. (2013). "Quantum structure and human thought". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 36 (3): 274–276. doi:10.1017/S0140525X12002841. PMID   23673022.
  42. Aerts, Diederik; Gabora, Liane; Sozzo, Sandro (September 2013). "Concepts and Their Dynamics: A Quantum-Theoretic Modeling of Human Thought". Topics in Cognitive Science. 5 (4): 737–772. arXiv: 1206.1069 . doi:10.1111/tops.12042. PMID   24039114. S2CID   6300002.
  43. Aerts, D.; Sozzo, S. (2012). "Quantum structures in cognition: Why and how concepts are entangled". In Song, D.; Melucci, M.; Frommholz, I. (eds.). Quantum Interaction 2011. LNCS. Vol. 7052. Berlin: Springer. pp. 116–127. ISBN   978-3-642-24970-9.
  44. Aerts, D.; Sozzo, S. (2014). "Quantum entanglement in concept combinations". International Journal of Theoretical Physics. 53 (10): 3587–3603. arXiv: 1302.3831 . Bibcode:2014IJTP...53.3587A. doi:10.1007/s10773-013-1946-z. S2CID   17064563.
  45. Van Rijsbergen, K. (2004). The Geometry of Information Retrieval. Cambridge University Press. ISBN   0-521-83805-3.
  46. Widdows, D. (2006). Geometry and meaning. CSLI Publications. ISBN   1-57586-448-7.
  47. Aerts, D.; Czachor, M. (2004). "Quantum aspects of semantic analysis and symbolic artificial intelligence". Journal of Physics A. 37 (12): L123–L132. arXiv: quant-ph/0309022 . doi:10.1088/0305-4470/37/12/L01. S2CID   16701954.
  48. Sorah, Michael. "Parserless Extraction; Using a Multidimensional Transient State Vector Machine" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 2017-04-04. Retrieved 2017-04-03.

Further reading