The precise definition of life is a contested aspect of it, and several proposals have been advanced. Biology defines and studies life as we know it, but abiogenesis and astrobiology seek wider and more encompassing definitions. Abiogenesis is the process by which life surges from inorganic materials, so a definition tries to establish the frontier between inorganic matter and the earliest and basest lifeforms. Astrobiology seeks extraterrestrial life, which may differ from Earth's life.
Life does not have a simple definition, because life on Earth has a huge diversity, ranging from microscopic microorganisms to massive plants and trees, and in all sorts of habitats. [1] A common way to define life is by using a number of characteristics that should be common to all life forms. However, those characteristics are not universal, and there are exceptions and possible false positives with all of them.
Trivial definitions of life, such as those used in dictionaries and science divulgation, rely on several aspects that should take place in it, such as homeostasis, growth, reproduction, and death. Biology, however, provides a more reliable answer: all lifeforms on Earth are composed of cells (both unicellular and multicellular lifeforms), and reproduction replicates information from an ancestor into its offspring with the work of the DNA and the RNA. All lifeforms on Earth have this in common, and nothing that does not live does. It is, thus, a perfect working definition for most sciences. [6] However, it is an incomplete definition for abiogenesis, the science that studies the origin of life. Earth began completely lifeless, and by some unclear chemistry inorganic materials combined themselves and created life. But life as we know it is too complex to appear abruptly, the process must have had steps, and we would require a better definition of life to decide which of those steps can be considered lifeforms, even if more primitive. [7] As for astrobiology, all lifeforms known to us are from a single planet. Life in other planets may have developed in other ways, and we would need a broader definition that would cover such divergent lifeforms as well. [8]
The biggest problem with defining life by a number of characteristics is that it can provide false positives. Long and detailed lists leave potential lifeforms out, and small lists may include things that were not intended to be considered alive. [9] For example, Crystals can grow and tend towards equilibrium, similar to homeostasis, but are not alive. [10] Robert Saphiro and Gerald Feinberg proposed that life is the activity of a biosphere, defining biosphere as "a highly ordered system of matter and energy characterized by complex cycles that maintain or gradually increase the order of the system through the exchange of energy with the environment"; a definition that may be too broad. [9] There are four possible ways to organize a definition. The first one is that there are a number of features and all of them must apply for something to be alive; if something has only some features but not others, then it is not. This is the method used by divulgation outlets. The second is that there is a single necessary and sufficient condition that can define the presence or absence of life. The third is that there are several necessary and sufficient conditions that define life; this is the one used in science. And finally, there may be several types of life without a common characteristic between them all. [11]
Dr. Carol Cleland, a member of the NASA Astrobiology Institute, considers that the problem is caused by the vagueness of spoken language, and that science does not need a definition of life, but rather a general theory of living systems. She compares the problems defining life with the problems defining substances in the middle ages, before the discovery of molecules, and points out that nitric acid was considered a type of water back then because it shared some superficial properties. However, a general theory can not be formulated before a sample of extraterrestrial life can be found and studied. [10] At this point, there is not enough data to formulate such a theory, as it is unknown if life is abundant in the universe or just a rarity exclusive of Earth. [12]
Life on Earth is carbon-based life, and uses water as a solvent. It is often assumed that life in other planets may have a similar composition, disregarding hypothetical types of biochemistry. Scientist Carl Sagan defined it as "carbon chauvinism". However, as those lifeforms are only theoretical, the details of their metabolism are unknown and it would be complex to define what to seek when seeking such lifeforms. However, although it is accepted that life can be composed of substances other than carbon and water, their properties still make them the better ones suited for it. [13]
The NASA defines life as a "self-sustaining chemical reaction capable of Darwinian evolution". [14] Adaptation works with natural selection, but it is unclear if human beings are still subject to it. In nature unfit creatures would not reproduce and would not pass their genes to later beings, ensuring that only the best individuals did so, but human beings are capable of compassion and to practice medicine, which may negate the process. [15] And it's hard to test a being and detect if it's capable of evolution, as evolution takes place in the species over time and not in specific individuals. [16] It is also unclear if Darwinian evolution is a feature of all life, or just a characteristic of life on Earth. [14] However, no credible alternative to it has been formulated. [17] Evolution can also find false-positives such as computer virus coded with evolutionary algorithms. [17] Evolution does not explain either the origin of life, which is understood to be the result of abiogenesis, a chemical evolution rather than a biological one. It is still unclear if it would be possible to recognize the first organism capable of evolution: some scientists think that had to be a clear first living organism, and others that it would be a slow process with several stages. [17]
Viruses pose a challenge to the formulation of a definition of life, because of their unique system of reproduction. They are incapable of reproduction on their own, but they can reproduce by infecting a living cell and exploiting its reproduction for their own benefit. As a result, they are considered a borderline case, in the frontier between the living and non-living. Prions, abnormal protein molecules, are another borderline case, as they are also incapable of reproduction, but can infect other proteins and turn them into prions. Meaning, they don't make copies of themselves, but they increase their numbers by turning others. They are usually considered non-living, although they present some ambiguity. [2]
One of the first attempts to formulate a definition of life was done by Aristotle in Ancient Greece. Although the limited technology of the time only allowed the study of things visible to the naked eye, he emphasized that theoretical conjectures should be based on empirical investigations. He studied animal life in several ways, such as in its natural habitats, experimentation, dissection, and vivisection; and he is credited as the father of biology. Aristotle distinguished living and non-living things by the hability of living things to have nutrition, reproduction, perception, locomotion, and thinking. Of those, he considered nutrition and reproduction to take priority over the others. In his writings, nutrition makes reference to all the process of digestion, as a living thing acquires, processes, and uses nutrients to fill biological needs. [18]
Aristotle compared the structure and actions of a living thing to the blueprints and tools used to build a house, as everything is prearranged to reach a desired end product (a sane and mature organism and a finished house, respectively). However, he made a distinction between human construction and natural construction: a house does not get built or maintained by itself and requires actual planning and work by humans, whereas living organisms build and regenerate themselves. This concept was difficult to reconcile with the logical mechanistic conception of causation, as the ends do not naturally precede the actions that lead to them. To accommodate for the characteristics of life, Aristotle postulated a special form of natural causation, the "soul", that allows living things to be self-causing. Non-living things, lacking it, would not be self-causing. This was illustrated by locomotion: a stone can only be moved if an external force is applied to it, but an animal can move without an external influence making him do so. [19]
Aristotle understood that there were four types of causation: efficient, material, formal, and final. Efficient causation would be similar to the modern concept of cause-effect, and final causation is about actions done to achieve a desired goal. The concept of a soul allows animals to have final causations without an external guiding hand: unlike the construction of a house, nobody instructs a zygote how to grow into an adult specimen, as if the instructions and blueprints were already included within it. [20]
Aristotelianism was questioned in the 1630s by René Descartes in Treatise on Man , which described living beings as automata, built on muscles, bones, and organs instead of cogs and pistons. Shortly afterwards Isaac Newton postulated the three laws of motion, and final causation was not considered valid anymore. However, as the knowledge about plants and animals grew, it soon became clear that their working was fundamentally different to that of artificial machines. Scientists proposed vitalism to explain that a "vital force" made living organisms work. Immanuel Kant said that living organisms are built with a design, but as nature lacks a designer, it could only mean that living beings are naturally teleological and incapable of being explained purely by a framework of forces like the laws of motion. An alternative notion to vitalism, emergentism, proposed instead that all matter, living and non-living, is composed by the same basic physical stuff, subject to the laws of physics. As matter organization grows, it generates new properties and patterns that can not be explained solely by physics. [21]
This article needs additional or more specific categories .(August 2025) |