Proportionality for solid coalitions

Last updated

Proportionality for solid coalitions (PSC) is a criterion of proportionality for ranked voting systems. It is an adaptation of the quota rule to voting systems in which there are no official party lists, and voters can directly support candidates. The criterion was first proposed by the British philosopher and logician Michael Dummett. [1] [2]

Contents

PSC is a weak definition of proportionality, which only guarantees proportional representation for cloned candidates, also called solid coalitions. In other words, voters must rank all candidates within the same party first (before candidates of other parties) to ensure it is adequately represented. On the other hand, PSC does not guarantee proportional representation if voters rank candidates of different parties together (as they will no longer form a solid coalition). As a result, PSC systems like the single transferable vote [3] can become disproportional if there are substantial cross-cutting cleavages, or if voters' ideologies are not well-described by a hierarchical structure of nested clusters, [4] [5] [6] a behavior analogous to center-squeeze for single-winner instant-runoff voting.

Solid coalitions

In party-list systems, proportional representation guarantees each party a number of representatives proportional to its number of votes. In systems without parties, the natural analogue of a "party" is a solid coalition. A solid coalition is a group of voters who prefer any candidate within a certain set of candidates over any candidate not in the set. A set of voters is a solid coalition for a set of candidates , if every voter in ranks every candidate in ahead of every candidate that is not in .

When a voter is part of a solid coalition that prefers some set of candidates, they are said to be "solidly supporting" or "solidly committed to" that set of candidates. [7] [8] Any voter who ranks a candidate as their first-preference solidly supports that candidate.

Note that a solid coalition may be "nested" within another solid coalition, so there may be some faction of voters that can further be split into subfactions. However, solid coalitions cannot cut across different factions. For example, say voters are organized along a political spectrum, with factions on the far-left, center-left, center, center-right, and far-right. Then, the three moderate groups will not form a solid coalition, because some members of the center-right may not rank the center-left candidate above the far-right candidate. Such an effect can lead to an anti-centrist bias in STV, unless the number of seats is very large, because centrists' second preferences are generally split between first-choice and second-choice votes.

Quotas

In the following let be the number of voters, be the number of seats to be filled and be some positive integer.

–PSC or Hare-PSC is defined with respect to the Hare quota . It says that if there is a solid coalition for a set of candidates with at least Hare quotas, then at least candidates from this set must be elected. (If has less than candidates, all of them must be elected). [4] This criterion was proposed by Michael Dummett. [1]

In the single-winner case, it is equivalent to the unanimity criterion, as a Hare quota in the single-winner case includes all voters.

–PSC, also called Droop-PSC, is defined like –PSC but using the Droop quota instead of the Hare quota, i.e. Droop quotas entitle a solid coalition to candidates. [4]

It is a generalization of the majority criterion in the sense that it relates to groups of supported candidates (solid coalitions) instead of just one candidate, and there may be more than one seat to be filled. [2] An advantage of Droop proportionality is that any solid coalition with a majority will always be able to elect at least half of seats.[ citation needed ] However, this comes at the cost of a substantial seat bias in favor of larger parties. [9] This means a coalition of smaller parties who together win a majority of the vote can nevertheless fail to reach a majority in the legislature.

Examples of quota-proportional methods include the expanding approvals rule, the method of equal shares, and the single transferable vote. [3]

Generalizations

Aziz and Lee define a property called generalized PSC, and another property, called inclusion PSC, that apply also to weak rankings (rankings with indifferences). Their expanding approvals rule satisfies these generalizations of PSC. [10]

Brill and Peters define a fairness property called Rank-PJR+, which also applies to weak rankings, but makes positive guarantees also to coalitions that are only partially solid. Rank-PJR+ is attained by the expanding approvals rule, but violated by the single transferable vote. It can be decided in polynomial time whether a given committee satisfies Rank-PJR+. [5]

See also

Related Research Articles

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Single transferable vote</span> Multi-winner electoral system

The single transferable vote (STV), a type of proportional ranked choice voting, is a multi-winner electoral system in which each voter casts a single vote in the form of a ranked-choice ballot. Voters have the option to rank candidates, and their vote may be transferred according to alternative preferences if their preferred candidate is eliminated or elected with surplus votes, so that their vote is used to elect someone they prefer over others in the running. STV aims to approach proportional representation based on votes cast in the district where it is used, so that each vote is worth about the same as another.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Droop quota</span> Quantity of votes in election studies

In the study of electoral systems, the Droop quota is the minimum number of supporters a party or candidate needs to receive in a district to guarantee they will win at least one seat in a legislature.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Quota method</span> Proportional-representation voting system

The quota methods are a family of apportionment rules, i.e. algorithms for distributing the seats in a legislative body among a number of administrative divisions. The quota methods are based on calculating a fixed electoral quota, i.e. a given number of votes needed to win a seat. This is used to calculate each party's seat entitlement. Every party is assigned the integer portion of this entitlement, and any seats left over are distributed according to a specified rule.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Random ballot</span> Electoral system with lottery among ballots

A random ballot or random dictatorship is a randomized electoral system where the election is decided on the basis of a single randomly-selected ballot. A closely-related variant is called random serialdictatorship, which repeats the procedure and draws another ballot if multiple candidates are tied on the first ballot.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Hare quota</span> Electoral system quota formula

In the study of apportionment, the Harequota is the number of voters represented by each legislator under an idealized system of proportional representation, where every legislator represents an equal number of voters. The Hare quota is the total number of votes divided by the number of seats to be filled. The Hare quota was used in the original proposal for a single transferable vote system, and is still occasionally used, although it has since been largely supplanted by the Droop quota.

In electoral systems, a wasted vote is any vote cast that is not "used" to elect a winner, and so is not represented in the outcome. However, the term is vague and ill-defined, having been used to refer to a wide variety of unrelated concepts and metrics. The precise definition of a wasted vote can have a major impact on the conclusions of an analysis. For example, under the narrowest possible definition of a wasted vote, the single transferable vote (STV) can be considered to waste zero votes. However, if the wasted vote definition is expanded even slightly, it is possible for up to 100% of STV votes to be classified as wasted because STV fails the unanimity criterion; that is, it is possible to elect a legislature that every single voter agrees is worse than some alternative.

The single transferable vote (STV) is a proportional representation system that elects multiple winners. It is one of several ways of choosing winners from ballots that rank candidates by preference. Under STV, an elector's vote is initially allocated to their first-ranked candidate. Candidates are elected (winners) if their vote tally reaches quota. After the winners in the first count are determined, if seats are still open, surplus votes — those in excess of an electoral quota— are transferred from winners to the remaining candidates (hopefuls) according to the surplus ballots' next usable back-up preference.

Later-no-harm is a property of some ranked-choice voting systems, first described by Douglas Woodall. In later-no-harm systems, increasing the rating or rank of a candidate ranked below the winner of an election cannot cause a higher-ranked candidate to lose.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Electoral quota</span> Number of votes a candidate needs to win

In proportional representation systems, an electoral quota is the number of votes a candidate needs to be guaranteed election.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Schulze STV</span> Proportional-representation ranked voting system

Schulze STV is a draft single transferable vote (STV) ranked voting system designed to achieve proportional representation. It was invented by Markus Schulze, who developed the Schulze method for resolving ties using a Condorcet method. Schulze STV is similar to CPO-STV in that it compares possible winning candidate pairs and selects the Condorcet winner. It is not used in parliamentary elections.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Semi-proportional representation</span> Family of electoral systems

Semi-proportional representation characterizes multi-winner electoral systems which allow representation of minorities, but are not intended to reflect the strength of the competing political forces in close proportion to the votes they receive. Semi-proportional voting systems are generally used as a compromise between complex and expensive but more-proportional systems and simple winner-take-all systems. Examples of semi-proportional systems include the single non-transferable vote, limited voting, and parallel voting.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Proportional approval voting</span> Multiple-winner electoral system

Proportional approval voting (PAV) is a proportional electoral system for multiwinner elections. It is a multiwinner approval method that extends the highest averages method of apportionment commonly used to calculate apportionments for party-list proportional representation. However, PAV allows voters to support only the candidates they approve of, rather than being forced to approve or reject all candidates on a given party list.

Combinatorial participatory budgeting, also called indivisible participatory budgeting or budgeted social choice, is a problem in social choice. There are several candidate projects, each of which has a fixed costs. There is a fixed budget, that cannot cover all these projects. Each voter has different preferences regarding these projects. The goal is to find a budget-allocation - a subset of the projects, with total cost at most the budget, that will be funded. Combinatorial participatory budgeting is the most common form of participatory budgeting.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Justified representation</span> Criterion for evaluating fairness of electoral systems

Justified representation (JR) is a criterion of fairness in multiwinner approval voting. It can be seen as an adaptation of the proportional representation criterion to approval voting.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Multiwinner approval voting</span> Family of proportional election methods

Multiwinner approval voting, sometimes also called approval-based committee (ABC) voting, refers to a family of multi-winner electoral systems that use approval ballots. Each voter may select ("approve") any number of candidates, and multiple candidates are elected.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Multiwinner voting</span> Process of electing more than one winner in the same election / district

Multiwinner, at-large, or committeevoting refers to electoral systems that elect several candidates at once. Such methods can be used to elect parliaments or committees.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Mathematics of apportionment</span> Mathematical principles

In mathematics and social choice, apportionment problems are a class of fair division problems where the goal is to divide (apportion) a whole number of identical goods fairly between multiple groups with different entitlements. The original example of an apportionment problem involves distributing seats in a legislature between different federal states or political parties. However, apportionment methods can be applied to other situations as well, including bankruptcy problems, inheritance law, manpower planning, and rounding percentages.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Phragmen's voting rules</span> Method of counting votes and determining results

Phragmén's voting rules are rules for multiwinner voting. They allow voters to vote for individual candidates rather than parties, but still guarantee proportional representation. They were published by Lars Edvard Phragmén in French and Swedish between 1893 and 1899, and translated to English by Svante Janson in 2016.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Expanding approvals rule</span>

The expanding approvals rule (EAR) is a rule for multi-winner elections that guarantees a form of proportional representation called proportionality for solid coalitions. It is a generalization of the highest median rules to include multiwinner elections and participatory budgeting. When working with ranked ballots, it is sometimes called the Bucklin transferable vote. However, the rule can be more effectively implemented using rated ballots, which are easier to use and provide additional cardinal utility information that can be used for better decision-making.

Thiele's voting rules are rules for multiwinner voting. They allow voters to vote for individual candidates rather than parties, but still guarantee proportional representation. They were published by Thorvald Thiele in Danish in 1895, and translated to English by Svante Janson in 2016. They were used in Swedish parliamentary elections to distribute seats within parties, and are still used in city council elections.

References

  1. 1 2 Dummett, M.: Voting procedures. Oxford Clarendon Press (1984).
  2. 1 2 D. R. Woodall: Monotonicity of single-seat preferential election rules. Discrete Applied Mathematics 77 (1997), p. 83–84.
  3. 1 2 Tideman, Nicolaus (1995-03-01). "The Single Transferable Vote". Journal of Economic Perspectives. 9 (1): 27–38. doi: 10.1257/jep.9.1.27 . ISSN   0895-3309.
  4. 1 2 3 Tideman N.: Collective Decisions and Voting. Ashgate Publishing Ltd, Aldershot, 2006, p. 268–269.
  5. 1 2 Brill, Markus; Peters, Jannik (2023). "Robust and Verifiable Proportionality Axioms for Multiwinner Voting". arXiv: 2302.01989 [cs.GT].
  6. Aziz, Haris; Lee, Barton (2018-06-04). "The Expanding Approvals Rule: Improving Proportional Representation and Monotonicity". arXiv: 1708.07580 [cs.GT].
  7. Aziz, Haris; Lee, Barton E. (2020). "A characterization of proportionally representative committees". arXiv: 2002.09598 [cs.GT].
  8. Aziz, Haris; Lee, Barton (2017). "The Expanding Approvals Rule: Improving Proportional Representation and Monotonicity". arXiv: 1708.07580 [cs.GT].
  9. Pukelsheim, Friedrich (2017), Pukelsheim, Friedrich (ed.), "Preferring Stronger Parties to Weaker Parties: Majorization", Proportional Representation: Apportionment Methods and Their Applications, Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 149–157, doi:10.1007/978-3-319-64707-4_8, ISBN   978-3-319-64707-4 , retrieved 2021-09-01
  10. Aziz, Haris; Lee, Barton E. (2019-08-09). "The expanding approvals rule: improving proportional representation and monotonicity". Social Choice and Welfare. 54 (1). Springer Science and Business Media LLC: 8. arXiv: 1708.07580 . doi:10.1007/s00355-019-01208-3. ISSN   0176-1714. S2CID   46926459.