Afshar experiment

Last updated

The Afshar experiment is a variation of the double slit experiment in quantum mechanics, devised and carried out by Shahriar Afshar while at the private, Boston-based Institute for Radiation-Induced Mass Studies (IRIMS). [1] The results were presented at a Harvard seminar in March 2004. [2] Afshar claimed that the experiment gives information about which of two paths a photon takes through the apparatus while simultaneously allowing interference between the two paths to be observed, by showing that a grid of wires, placed at the nodes of the interference pattern, does not alter the beams. [3] Afshar claimed that the experiment violates the principle of complementarity of quantum mechanics, [4] which states roughly that the particle and wave aspects of quantum objects cannot be observed at the same time, and specifically the Englert–Greenberger duality relation. [5] The experiment has been repeated by a number of investigators but its interpretation is controversial and there are several theories that explain the effect without violating complementarity. [6] [7] [8] [9] [10]

Contents

Overview

Afshar's experiment uses a variant of Thomas Young's classic double-slit experiment to create interference patterns to investigate complementarity. One of Afshar's assertions is that, in his experiment, it is possible to check for interference fringes of a photon stream (a measurement of the wave nature of the photons) while at the same time determining each photon's "which-path" information (a measurement of the particle nature of the photons). [3] [11] In his experiment, pinhole A is correlated to detector 1 when pinhole B is closed, and pinhole B is correlated to detector 2 when pinhole A is closed. Afshar's claim for the violation of the principle of complementarity depends crucially on his assertion that these correlations remain, and thus which-path information is preserved, when both pinholes are open, and cites Wheeler [12] in support. [5]

History

Shahriar S. Afshar's experimental work was done initially at the Institute for Radiation-Induced Mass Studies (IRIMS) in Boston in 2001 and later reproduced at Harvard University in 2003, while he was a research scholar there. [1] The results were presented at a Harvard seminar in March 2004, [2] and published as conference proceeding by The International Society for Optical Engineering (SPIE). [3] The experiment was featured as the cover story in the July 24, 2004 edition of New Scientist . [1] [13] The New Scientist feature article itself generated many responses, including various letters to the editor that appeared in the August 7 and August 14, 2004 issues, arguing against the conclusions being drawn by Afshar, with John G. Cramer's response. [14] Afshar presented his work also at the American Physical Society meeting in Los Angeles, in late March 2005. [15] His peer-reviewed paper was published in Foundations of Physics in January 2007. [5]

Experimental setup

Fig.1 Experiment without obstructing wire grid Afshar-experiment.png
Fig.1 Experiment without obstructing wire grid
Fig.2 Experiment with obstructing wire grid and one pinhole covered Afshar-experiment-wire.png
Fig.2 Experiment with obstructing wire grid and one pinhole covered
Fig.3 Experiment with wire grid and both pinholes open. The wires lie in the dark fringes and thus block very little light Afshar-experiment-1.png
Fig.3 Experiment with wire grid and both pinholes open. The wires lie in the dark fringes and thus block very little light

The experiment uses a setup similar to that for the double-slit experiment. In Afshar's variant, light generated by a laser passes through two closely spaced circular pinholes (not slits). After the dual pinholes, a lens refocuses the light so that the image of each pinhole falls on separate photon-detectors (Fig. 1). With Pinhole 2 closed, a photon that goes through Pinhole 1 impinges only on Photon Detector 1. Similarly, with Pinhole 1 closed, a photon that goes through Pinhole 2 impinges only on Photon Detector 2. With both pinholes open, Afshar claims, citing Wheeler [12] in support, that Pinhole 1 remains correlated to Photon Detector 1 (and vice versa for Pinhole 2 to Photon Detector 2), and therefore that which-way information is preserved when both pinholes are open. [5]

When the light acts as a wave, because of quantum interference one can observe that there are regions that the photons avoid, called dark fringes. A grid of thin wires is placed just before the lens (Fig. 2) so that the wires lie in the dark fringes of an interference pattern which is produced by the dual pinhole setup. If one of the pinholes is blocked, the interference pattern will no longer be formed, and the grid of wires causes appreciable diffraction in the light and blocks some of it from detection by the corresponding photon detector. However, when both pinholes are open, the effect of the wires is negligible, comparable to the case in which there are no wires placed in front of the lens (Fig.3), because the wires lie in the dark fringes of an interference pattern. The effect is not dependent on the light intensity (photon flux).

To establish violation of the principle of complementarity, Afshar considers the case in which both pinholes are open and asserts both high visibility V of interference as well as high distinguishability D (corresponding to which-path information), so that V2 + D2 > 1. [5] His claim depends heavily on whether which-path information is preserved when both pinholes are open.

Afshar's interpretation

Afshar's conclusion is that, when both pinholes are open, the light exhibits wave-like behavior when going past the wires, since the light goes through the spaces between the wires but avoids the wires themselves, but also exhibits particle-like behavior after going through the lens, with photons going to a correlated photo-detector. Afshar argues that this behavior contradicts the principle of complementarity to the extent that it shows both wave and particle characteristics in the same experiment for the same photons.

Reception

Specific criticism

A number of scientists have published criticisms of Afshar's interpretation of his results, some of which reject the claims of a violation of complementarity, while differing in the way they explain how complementarity copes with the experiment. Afshar has responded to these critics in his academic talks, his blog, and other forums. For example, one paper contests Afshar's core claim, that the Englert–Greenberger duality relation is violated. The researchers re-ran the experiment, using a different method for measuring the visibility of the interference pattern than that used by Afshar, and found no violation of complementarity, concluding "This result demonstrates that the experiment can be perfectly explained by the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics." [8]

Below is a synopsis of papers by several critics highlighting their main arguments and the disagreements they have amongst themselves:

Specific support

See also

Related Research Articles

Double-slit experiment Physics experiment, showing light can be modelled by both waves and particles

In modern physics, the double-slit experiment is a demonstration that light and matter can display characteristics of both classically defined waves and particles; moreover, it displays the fundamentally probabilistic nature of quantum mechanical phenomena. This type of experiment was first performed, using light, by Thomas Young in 1801, as a demonstration of the wave behavior of light. At that time it was thought that light consisted of either waves or particles. With the beginning of modern physics, about a hundred years later, it was realized that light could in fact show behavior characteristic of both waves and particles. In 1927, Davisson and Germer demonstrated that electrons show the same behavior, which was later extended to atoms and molecules. Thomas Young's experiment with light was part of classical physics well before quantum mechanics, and the concept of wave-particle duality. He believed it demonstrated that the wave theory of light was correct, and his experiment is sometimes referred to as Young's experiment or Young's slits.

Wave–particle duality is the concept in quantum mechanics that every particle or quantum entity may be described as either a particle or a wave. It expresses the inability of the classical concepts "particle" or "wave" to fully describe the behaviour of quantum-scale objects. As Albert Einstein wrote:

It seems as though we must use sometimes the one theory and sometimes the other, while at times we may use either. We are faced with a new kind of difficulty. We have two contradictory pictures of reality; separately neither of them fully explains the phenomena of light, but together they do.

The de Broglie–Bohm theory, also known as the pilot wave theory, Bohmian mechanics, Bohm's interpretation, and the causal interpretation, is an interpretation of quantum mechanics. In addition to the wavefunction, it also postulates an actual configuration of particles exists even when unobserved. The evolution over time of the configuration of all particles is defined by a guiding equation. The evolution of the wave function over time is given by the Schrödinger equation. The theory is named after Louis de Broglie (1892–1987) and David Bohm (1917–1992).

In physics, two wave sources are perfectly coherent if their frequency and waveform are identical and their phase difference is constant. Coherence is an ideal property of waves that enables stationary interference. It contains several distinct concepts, which are limiting cases that never quite occur in reality but allow an understanding of the physics of waves, and has become a very important concept in quantum physics. More generally, coherence describes all properties of the correlation between physical quantities of a single wave, or between several waves or wave packets.

The transactional interpretation of quantum mechanics (TIQM) takes the wave function of the standard quantum formalism, and its complex conjugate, to be retarded and advanced waves that form a quantum interaction as a Wheeler–Feynman handshake or transaction. It was first proposed in 1986 by John G. Cramer, who argues that it helps in developing intuition for quantum processes. He also suggests that it avoids the philosophical problems with the Copenhagen interpretation and the role of the observer, and also resolves various quantum paradoxes. TIQM formed a minor plot point in his science fiction novel Einstein's Bridge.

Mach–Zehnder interferometer

In physics, the Mach–Zehnder interferometer is a device used to determine the relative phase shift variations between two collimated beams derived by splitting light from a single source. The interferometer has been used, among other things, to measure phase shifts between the two beams caused by a sample or a change in length of one of the paths. The apparatus is named after the physicists Ludwig Mach and Ludwig Zehnder; Zehnder's proposal in an 1891 article was refined by Mach in an 1892 article. Demonstrations of Mach-Zehnder interferometry with particles other than photons had been demonstrated as well in multiple experiments.

The Unruh effect is the hypothetical prediction that an accelerating observer will observe a thermal bath, like blackbody radiation, whereas an inertial observer would observe none. In other words, the background appears to be warm from an accelerating reference frame; in layman's terms, an accelerating thermometer in empty space, subtracting any other contribution to its temperature, will record a non-zero temperature, just from its acceleration. Heuristically, for a uniformly accelerating observer, the ground state of an inertial observer is seen as a mixed state in thermodynamic equilibrium with a non-zero temperature bath.

In Bell tests, there may be problems of experimental design or set-up that affect the validity of the experimental findings. These problems are often referred to as "loopholes". See the article on Bell's theorem for the theoretical background to these experimental efforts. The purpose of the experiment is to test whether nature is best described using a local hidden variable theory or by the quantum entanglement theory of quantum mechanics.

A Bell test, also known as Bell inequality test or Bell experiment, is a real-world physics experiment designed to test the theory of quantum mechanics in relation to Albert Einstein's concept of local realism. The experiments test whether or not the real world satisfies local realism, which requires the presence of some additional local variables to explain the behavior of particles like photons and electrons. To date, all Bell tests have found that the hypothesis of local hidden variables is inconsistent with the way that physical systems behave.

A local hidden-variable theory in the interpretation of quantum mechanics is a hidden-variable theory that has the added requirement of being consistent with local realism. It refers to all types of the theory that attempt to account for the probabilistic features of quantum mechanics by the mechanism of underlying inaccessible variables, with the additional requirement from local realism that distant events be independent, ruling out instantaneous interactions between separate events.

In physics, complementarity is both a theoretical and an experimental result of quantum mechanics, also referred to as principle of complementarity. Formulated by Niels Bohr, a leading founder of quantum mechanics, the complementarity principle holds that objects have certain pairs of complementary properties which cannot all be observed or measured simultaneously.

Elitzur–Vaidman bomb tester Quantum mechanics thought experiment

The Elitzur–Vaidman bomb-tester is a quantum mechanics thought experiment that uses interaction-free measurements to verify that a bomb is functional without having to detonate it. It was conceived in 1993 by Avshalom Elitzur and Lev Vaidman. Since their publication, real-world experiments have confirmed that their theoretical method works as predicted.

In quantum mechanics, the quantum eraser experiment is an interferometer experiment that demonstrates several fundamental aspects of quantum mechanics, including quantum entanglement and complementarity. The quantum eraser experiment is a variation of Thomas Young's classic double-slit experiment. It establishes that when action is taken to determine which of 2 slits a photon has passed through, the photon cannot interfere with itself. When a stream of photons is marked in this way, then the interference fringes characteristic of the Young experiment will not be seen. The experiment also creates situations in which a photon that has been "marked" to reveal through which slit it has passed can later be "unmarked." A photon that has been "marked" cannot interfere with itself and will not produce fringe patterns, but a photon that has been "marked" and then "unmarked" will interfere with itself and produce the fringes characteristic of Young's experiment.

A delayed-choice quantum eraser experiment, first performed by Yoon-Ho Kim, R. Yu, S. P. Kulik, Y. H. Shih and Marlan O. Scully, and reported in early 1999, is an elaboration on the quantum eraser experiment that incorporates concepts considered in Wheeler's delayed-choice experiment. The experiment was designed to investigate peculiar consequences of the well-known double-slit experiment in quantum mechanics, as well as the consequences of quantum entanglement.

Wheelers delayed-choice experiment Number of quantum physics thought experiments

Wheeler's delayed-choice experiment is actually several thought experiments in quantum physics, proposed by John Archibald Wheeler, with the most prominent among them appearing in 1978 and 1984. These experiments are attempts to decide whether light somehow "senses" the experimental apparatus in the double-slit experiment it will travel through and adjusts its behavior to fit by assuming the appropriate determinate state for it, or whether light remains in an indeterminate state, neither wave nor particle until measured.

The wave–particle duality relation, often loosely referred to as the Englert–Greenberger–Yasin duality relation, or the Englert–Greenberger relation, relates the visibility, , of interference fringes with the definiteness, or distinguishability, , of the photons' paths in quantum optics. As an inequality:

Popper's experiment is an experiment proposed by the philosopher Karl Popper to put to the test different interpretations of quantum mechanics (QM). In fact, as early as 1934, Popper started criticising the increasingly more accepted Copenhagen interpretation, a popular subjectivist interpretation of quantum mechanics. Therefore, in his most famous book Logik der Forschung he proposed a first experiment alleged to empirically discriminate between the Copenhagen Interpretation and a realist interpretation, which he advocated. Einstein, however, wrote a letter to Popper about the experiment in which he raised some crucial objections and Popper himself declared that this first attempt was "a gross mistake for which I have been deeply sorry and ashamed of ever since".

In physics, the observer effect is the disturbance of an observed system by the act of observation. This is often the result of instruments that, by necessity, alter the state of what they measure in some manner. A common example is checking the pressure in an automobile tire; this is difficult to do without letting out some of the air, thus changing the pressure. Similarly, it is not possible to see any object without light hitting the object, and causing it to reflect that light. While the effects of observation are often negligible, the object still experiences a change. This effect can be found in many domains of physics, but can usually be reduced to insignificance by using different instruments or observation techniques.

Dipankar Home is an Indian theoretical physicist at Bose Institute, Kolkata. He works on the fundamental aspects of quantum mechanics, including quantum entanglement and Quantum communication. He is co-author with Partha Ghose of the popular book Riddles in your Teacup - Fun with Everyday Scientific Puzzles.

Quantum microscopy is a novel tool that allows microscopic properties of matter and quantum particles to be measured and directly visualized. There are various types of microscopy that use quantum principles. The first microscope to make use of quantum concepts was the scanning tunneling microscope, which paved the way for development of the photoionization microscope and the quantum entanglement microscope.

References

  1. 1 2 3 Chown, Marcus (2004). "Quantum rebel wins over doubters". New Scientist . 183 (2457): 30–35.(subscription required)
  2. 1 2 S. S. Afshar (2004). "Waving Copenhagen Good-bye: Were the founders of Quantum Mechanics wrong?". Harvard Seminar Announcement. Retrieved 2013-12-01.
  3. 1 2 3 S. S. Afshar (2005). Roychoudhuri, Chandrasekhar; Creath, Katherine (eds.). "Violation of the principle of complementarity, and its implications". Proceedings of SPIE . The Nature of Light: What Is a Photon?. 5866: 229–244. arXiv: quant-ph/0701027 . Bibcode:2005SPIE.5866..229A. doi:10.1117/12.638774.
  4. J. Zheng; C. Zheng (2011). "Variant simulation system using quaternion structures". Journal of Modern Optics . 59 (5): 484. Bibcode:2012JMOp...59..484Z. doi:10.1080/09500340.2011.636152.
  5. 1 2 3 4 5 S. S. Afshar; E. Flores; K. F. McDonald; E. Knoesel (2007). "Paradox in wave-particle duality". Foundations of Physics . 37 (2): 295–305. arXiv: quant-ph/0702188 . Bibcode:2007FoPh...37..295A. doi:10.1007/s10701-006-9102-8.
  6. 1 2 R. Kastner (2005). "Why the Afshar experiment does not refute complementarity?". Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics . 36 (4): 649–658. arXiv: quant-ph/0502021 . Bibcode:2005SHPMP..36..649K. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2005.04.006.
  7. 1 2 O. Steuernagel (2007). "Afshar's experiment does not show a violation of complementarity". Foundations of Physics . 37 (9): 1370. arXiv: quant-ph/0512123 . Bibcode:2007FoPh...37.1370S. doi:10.1007/s10701-007-9153-5.
  8. 1 2 V. Jacques; et al. (2008). "Illustration of quantum complementarity using single photons interfering on a grating". New Journal of Physics . 10 (12): 123009. arXiv: 0807.5079 . Bibcode:2008NJPh...10l3009J. doi:10.1088/1367-2630/10/12/123009.
  9. D. D. Georgiev (2007). "Single photon experiments and quantum complementarity" (PDF). Progress in Physics . 2: 97–103. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2010-09-27. Retrieved 2009-08-15.
  10. D. D. Georgiev (2012). "Quantum histories and quantum complementarity". ISRN Mathematical Physics. 2012: 327278. doi: 10.5402/2012/327278 . Archived from the original on 2012-09-26. Retrieved 2012-02-25.
  11. S. S. Afshar (2006). "Violation of Bohr's complementarity: One slit or both?". AIP Conference Proceedings . 810: 294–299. arXiv: quant-ph/0701039 . Bibcode:2006AIPC..810..294A. doi:10.1063/1.2158731.
  12. 1 2 Wheeler, John (1978). Mathematical foundations of quantum theory. Elsevier. p. 9-48.
  13. Afshar's Quantum Bomshell [ permanent dead link ][ dead link ] Science Friday
  14. J. G. Cramer (2004). "Bohr is still wrong". New Scientist . 183 (2461): 26.
  15. S. S. Afshar (2005). "Experimental Evidence for Violation of Bohr's Principle of Complementarity". APS Meeting, March 21–25, los Angeles, California: 33009. Bibcode:2005APS..MARP33009A.
  16. R. E. Kastner (2006). "The Afshar Experiment and Complementarity". APS Meeting, March 13–17, Baltimore, Maryland: 40011. Bibcode:2006APS..MARD40011K.
  17. D. Reitzner. "Comment on Afshar's experiments". arXiv: quant-ph/0701152 .Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  18. W. Unruh (2004). "Shahriar Afshar – Quantum Rebel?".
  19. L. Motl (2004). "Violation of complementarity?".
  20. Aurelien Drezet (2005). "Complementarity and Afshar's experiment". arXiv: quant-ph/0508091 .
  21. Aurelien Drezet (2011). "Wave particle duality and the Afshar experiment" (PDF). Progress in Physics . 1: 57–67. arXiv: 1008.4261 . Archived from the original (PDF) on 2011-10-11. Retrieved 2012-02-25.
  22. Andrew Knight. "No Paradox in Wave-Particle Duality". Foundations of Physics . 50 (11): 1723–1727. arXiv: 2006.05315 . doi:10.1007/s10701-020-00379-9.
  23. E. Flores and E. Knoesel. "Why Kastner analysis does not apply to a modified Afshar experiment". arXiv: quant-ph/0702210 .Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  24. J. G. Cramer (2005). "A farewell to Copenhagen?". Analog Science Fiction and Fact . Archived from the original on 2004-12-08. Retrieved 2004-12-21.

Further reading