This article includes a list of general references, but it lacks sufficient corresponding inline citations .(June 2012) |
In calculus, the extreme value theorem states that if a real-valued function is continuous on the closed and bounded interval , then must attain a maximum and a minimum, each at least once. That is, there exist numbers and in such that:
The extreme value theorem is more specific than the related boundedness theorem, which states merely that a continuous function on the closed interval is bounded on that interval; that is, there exist real numbers and such that:
This does not say that and are necessarily the maximum and minimum values of on the interval which is what the extreme value theorem stipulates must also be the case.
The extreme value theorem is used to prove Rolle's theorem. In a formulation due to Karl Weierstrass, this theorem states that a continuous function from a non-empty compact space to a subset of the real numbers attains a maximum and a minimum.
The extreme value theorem was originally proven by Bernard Bolzano in the 1830s in a work Function Theory but the work remained unpublished until 1930. Bolzano's proof consisted of showing that a continuous function on a closed interval was bounded, and then showing that the function attained a maximum and a minimum value. Both proofs involved what is known today as the Bolzano–Weierstrass theorem. [1]
The following examples show why the function domain must be closed and bounded in order for the theorem to apply. Each fails to attain a maximum on the given interval.
Defining in the last two examples shows that both theorems require continuity on .
When moving from the real line to metric spaces and general topological spaces, the appropriate generalization of a closed bounded interval is a compact set. A set is said to be compact if it has the following property: from every collection of open sets such that , a finite subcollection can be chosen such that . This is usually stated in short as "every open cover of has a finite subcover". The Heine–Borel theorem asserts that a subset of the real line is compact if and only if it is both closed and bounded. Correspondingly, a metric space has the Heine–Borel property if every closed and bounded set is also compact.
The concept of a continuous function can likewise be generalized. Given topological spaces , a function is said to be continuous if for every open set , is also open. Given these definitions, continuous functions can be shown to preserve compactness: [2]
Theorem — If are topological spaces, is a continuous function, and is compact, then is also compact.
In particular, if , then this theorem implies that is closed and bounded for any compact set , which in turn implies that attains its supremum and infimum on any (nonempty) compact set . Thus, we have the following generalization of the extreme value theorem: [2]
Theorem — If is a nonempty compact set and is a continuous function, then is bounded and there exist such that and .
Slightly more generally, this is also true for an upper semicontinuous function. (see compact space#Functions and compact spaces).
We look at the proof for the upper bound and the maximum of . By applying these results to the function , the existence of the lower bound and the result for the minimum of follows. Also note that everything in the proof is done within the context of the real numbers.
We first prove the boundedness theorem, which is a step in the proof of the extreme value theorem. The basic steps involved in the proof of the extreme value theorem are:
Boundedness Theorem — If is continuous on then it is bounded on
Suppose the function is not bounded above on the interval . Then, for every natural number , there exists an such that . This defines a sequence . Because is bounded, the Bolzano–Weierstrass theorem implies that there exists a convergent subsequence of . Denote its limit by . As is closed, it contains . Because is continuous at , we know that converges to the real number (as is sequentially continuous at ). But for every , which implies that diverges to , a contradiction. Therefore, is bounded above on . ∎
Consider the set of points in such that is bounded on . We note that is one such point, for is bounded on by the value . If is another point, then all points between and also belong to . In other words is an interval closed at its left end by .
Now is continuous on the right at , hence there exists such that for all in . Thus is bounded by and on the interval so that all these points belong to .
So far, we know that is an interval of non-zero length, closed at its left end by .
Next, is bounded above by . Hence the set has a supremum in ; let us call it . From the non-zero length of we can deduce that .
Suppose . Now is continuous at , hence there exists such that for all in so that is bounded on this interval. But it follows from the supremacy of that there exists a point belonging to , say, which is greater than . Thus is bounded on which overlaps so that is bounded on . This however contradicts the supremacy of .
We must therefore have . Now is continuous on the left at , hence there exists such that for all in so that is bounded on this interval. But it follows from the supremacy of that there exists a point belonging to , say, which is greater than . Thus is bounded on which overlaps so that is bounded on . ∎
By the boundedness theorem, f is bounded from above, hence, by the Dedekind-completeness of the real numbers, the least upper bound (supremum) M of f exists. It is necessary to find a point d in [a, b] such that M = f(d). Let n be a natural number. As M is the least upper bound, M – 1/n is not an upper bound for f. Therefore, there exists dn in [a, b] so that M – 1/n < f(dn). This defines a sequence {dn}. Since M is an upper bound for f, we have M – 1/n < f(dn) ≤ M for all n. Therefore, the sequence {f(dn)} converges to M.
The Bolzano–Weierstrass theorem tells us that there exists a subsequence {}, which converges to some d and, as [a, b] is closed, d is in [a, b]. Since f is continuous at d, the sequence {f()} converges to f(d). But {f(dnk)} is a subsequence of {f(dn)} that converges to M, so M = f(d). Therefore, f attains its supremum M at d. ∎
The set {y∈R : y = f(x) for some x∈ [a,b]} is a bounded set. Hence, its least upper bound exists by least upper bound property of the real numbers. Let M = sup(f(x)) on [a, b]. If there is no point x on [a, b] so that f(x) = M, then f(x) < M on [a, b]. Therefore, 1/(M−f(x)) is continuous on [a, b].
However, to every positive number ε, there is always some x in [a, b] such that M−f(x) < ε because M is the least upper bound. Hence, 1/(M−f(x)) > 1/ε, which means that 1/(M−f(x)) is not bounded. Since every continuous function on [a, b] is bounded, this contradicts the conclusion that 1/(M−f(x)) was continuous on [a, b]. Therefore, there must be a point x in [a, b] such that f(x) = M. ∎
In the setting of non-standard calculus, let N be an infinite hyperinteger. The interval [0, 1] has a natural hyperreal extension. Consider its partition into N subintervals of equal infinitesimal length 1/N, with partition points xi = i /N as i "runs" from 0 to N. The function ƒ is also naturally extended to a function ƒ* defined on the hyperreals between 0 and 1. Note that in the standard setting (when N is finite), a point with the maximal value of ƒ can always be chosen among the N+1 points xi, by induction. Hence, by the transfer principle, there is a hyperinteger i0 such that 0 ≤ i0 ≤ N and for all i = 0, ..., N. Consider the real point where st is the standard part function. An arbitrary real point x lies in a suitable sub-interval of the partition, namely , so that st(xi) = x. Applying st to the inequality , we obtain . By continuity of ƒ we have
Hence ƒ(c) ≥ ƒ(x), for all real x, proving c to be a maximum of ƒ. [3] ∎
Statement If is continuous on then it attains its supremum on
By the Boundedness Theorem, is bounded above on and by the completeness property of the real numbers has a supremum in . Let us call it , or . It is clear that the restriction of to the subinterval where has a supremum which is less than or equal to , and that increases from to as increases from to .
If then we are done. Suppose therefore that and let . Consider the set of points in such that .
Clearly ; moreover if is another point in then all points between and also belong to because is monotonic increasing. Hence is a non-empty interval, closed at its left end by .
Now is continuous on the right at , hence there exists such that for all in . Thus is less than on the interval so that all these points belong to .
Next, is bounded above by and has therefore a supremum in : let us call it . We see from the above that . We will show that is the point we are seeking i.e. the point where attains its supremum, or in other words .
Suppose the contrary viz. . Let and consider the following two cases:
If the continuity of the function f is weakened to semi-continuity, then the corresponding half of the boundedness theorem and the extreme value theorem hold and the values –∞ or +∞, respectively, from the extended real number line can be allowed as possible values.[ clarification needed ]
A function is said to be upper semi-continuous if
Theorem — If a function f : [a, b] → [–∞, ∞) is upper semi-continuous, then f is bounded above and attains its supremum.
If for all x in [a,b], then the supremum is also and the theorem is true. In all other cases, the proof is a slight modification of the proofs given above. In the proof of the boundedness theorem, the upper semi-continuity of f at x only implies that the limit superior of the subsequence {f(xnk)} is bounded above by f(x) < ∞, but that is enough to obtain the contradiction. In the proof of the extreme value theorem, upper semi-continuity of f at d implies that the limit superior of the subsequence {f(dnk)} is bounded above by f(d), but this suffices to conclude that f(d) = M. ∎
Applying this result to −f proves a similar result for the infimums of lower semicontinuous functions. A function is said to be lower semi-continuous if
Theorem — If a function f : [a, b] → (–∞, ∞] is lower semi-continuous, then f is bounded below and attains its infimum.
A real-valued function is upper as well as lower semi-continuous, if and only if it is continuous in the usual sense. Hence these two theorems imply the boundedness theorem and the extreme value theorem.
In mathematics, a continuous function is a function such that a small variation of the argument induces a small variation of the value of the function. This implies there are no abrupt changes in value, known as discontinuities. More precisely, a function is continuous if arbitrarily small changes in its value can be assured by restricting to sufficiently small changes of its argument. A discontinuous function is a function that is not continuous. Until the 19th century, mathematicians largely relied on intuitive notions of continuity and considered only continuous functions. The epsilon–delta definition of a limit was introduced to formalize the definition of continuity.
In mathematical analysis, the intermediate value theorem states that if is a continuous function whose domain contains the interval [a, b], then it takes on any given value between and at some point within the interval.
In complex analysis, the Riemann mapping theorem states that if is a non-empty simply connected open subset of the complex number plane which is not all of , then there exists a biholomorphic mapping from onto the open unit disk
In the branch of mathematics known as real analysis, the Riemann integral, created by Bernhard Riemann, was the first rigorous definition of the integral of a function on an interval. It was presented to the faculty at the University of Göttingen in 1854, but not published in a journal until 1868. For many functions and practical applications, the Riemann integral can be evaluated by the fundamental theorem of calculus or approximated by numerical integration, or simulated using Monte Carlo integration.
In mathematics, the branch of real analysis studies the behavior of real numbers, sequences and series of real numbers, and real functions. Some particular properties of real-valued sequences and functions that real analysis studies include convergence, limits, continuity, smoothness, differentiability and integrability.
In mathematics, a real function of real numbers is said to be uniformly continuous if there is a positive real number such that function values over any function domain interval of the size are as close to each other as we want. In other words, for a uniformly continuous real function of real numbers, if we want function value differences to be less than any positive real number , then there is a positive real number such that for any and in any interval of length within the domain of .
In mathematical analysis, semicontinuity is a property of extended real-valued functions that is weaker than continuity. An extended real-valued function is uppersemicontinuous at a point if, roughly speaking, the function values for arguments near are not much higher than
In vector calculus, Green's theorem relates a line integral around a simple closed curve C to a double integral over the plane region D bounded by C. It is the two-dimensional special case of Stokes' theorem. In one dimension, it is equivalent to the fundamental theorem of calculus. In three dimensions, it is equivalent to the divergence theorem.
In mathematics, the uniform boundedness principle or Banach–Steinhaus theorem is one of the fundamental results in functional analysis. Together with the Hahn–Banach theorem and the open mapping theorem, it is considered one of the cornerstones of the field. In its basic form, it asserts that for a family of continuous linear operators whose domain is a Banach space, pointwise boundedness is equivalent to uniform boundedness in operator norm.
In calculus and real analysis, absolute continuity is a smoothness property of functions that is stronger than continuity and uniform continuity. The notion of absolute continuity allows one to obtain generalizations of the relationship between the two central operations of calculus—differentiation and integration. This relationship is commonly characterized in the framework of Riemann integration, but with absolute continuity it may be formulated in terms of Lebesgue integration. For real-valued functions on the real line, two interrelated notions appear: absolute continuity of functions and absolute continuity of measures. These two notions are generalized in different directions. The usual derivative of a function is related to the Radon–Nikodym derivative, or density, of a measure. We have the following chains of inclusions for functions over a compact subset of the real line:
In mathematics, specifically differential calculus, the inverse function theorem gives a sufficient condition for a function to be invertible in a neighborhood of a point in its domain: namely, that its derivative is continuous and non-zero at the point. The theorem also gives a formula for the derivative of the inverse function. In multivariable calculus, this theorem can be generalized to any continuously differentiable, vector-valued function whose Jacobian determinant is nonzero at a point in its domain, giving a formula for the Jacobian matrix of the inverse. There are also versions of the inverse function theorem for holomorphic functions, for differentiable maps between manifolds, for differentiable functions between Banach spaces, and so forth.
In mathematics, a function defined on some set with real or complex values is called bounded if the set of its values is bounded. In other words, there exists a real number such that
In the mathematical field of numerical analysis, a Bernstein polynomial is a polynomial expressed as a linear combination of Bernstein basis polynomials. The idea is named after mathematician Sergei Natanovich Bernstein.
The Arzelà–Ascoli theorem is a fundamental result of mathematical analysis giving necessary and sufficient conditions to decide whether every sequence of a given family of real-valued continuous functions defined on a closed and bounded interval has a uniformly convergent subsequence. The main condition is the equicontinuity of the family of functions. The theorem is the basis of many proofs in mathematics, including that of the Peano existence theorem in the theory of ordinary differential equations, Montel's theorem in complex analysis, and the Peter–Weyl theorem in harmonic analysis and various results concerning compactness of integral operators.
In mathematics, nonstandard calculus is the modern application of infinitesimals, in the sense of nonstandard analysis, to infinitesimal calculus. It provides a rigorous justification for some arguments in calculus that were previously considered merely heuristic.
In mathematics, specifically the study of differential equations, the Picard–Lindelöf theorem gives a set of conditions under which an initial value problem has a unique solution. It is also known as Picard's existence theorem, the Cauchy–Lipschitz theorem, or the existence and uniqueness theorem.
In mathematics, a function is locally bounded if it is bounded around every point. A family of functions is locally bounded if for any point in their domain all the functions are bounded around that point and by the same number.
In mathematics, quadratic variation is used in the analysis of stochastic processes such as Brownian motion and other martingales. Quadratic variation is just one kind of variation of a process.
In mathematics, Helly's selection theorem states that a uniformly bounded sequence of monotone real functions admits a convergent subsequence. In other words, it is a sequential compactness theorem for the space of uniformly bounded monotone functions. It is named for the Austrian mathematician Eduard Helly. A more general version of the theorem asserts compactness of the space BVloc of functions locally of bounded total variation that are uniformly bounded at a point.
The fundamental theorem of calculus is a theorem that links the concept of differentiating a function with the concept of integrating a function. Roughly speaking, the two operations can be thought of as inverses of each other.