Philosophy of happiness

Last updated

The philosophy of happiness is the philosophical concern with the existence, nature, and attainment of happiness. Some philosophers believe happiness can be understood as the moral goal of life or as an aspect of chance; indeed, in most European languages the term happiness is synonymous with luck. [1] Thus, philosophers usually explicate on happiness as either a state of mind, or a life that goes well for the person leading it. [2] Given the pragmatic concern for the attainment of happiness, research in psychology has guided many modern-day philosophers in developing their theories. [3]

Contents

Ancient Greece

Democritus by Hendrick ter Brugghen, 1628. Hendrik ter Brugghen - Democritus.jpg
Democritus by Hendrick ter Brugghen, 1628.

Democritus

Democritus (c. 460 – c. 370 BC) is known as the 'laughing philosopher' because of his emphasis on the value of 'cheerfulness'. [4]

Plato

The man who makes everything that leads to happiness depends upon himself, and not upon other men, has adopted the very best plan for living happily

Plato (c. 428  c. 347 BCE) teaches in the Republic that a life committed to knowledge and virtue will result in happiness and self-realization. To achieve happiness, one should become immune to changes in the material world and strive to gain the knowledge of the eternal, immutable forms that reside in the realm of ideas. [5]

The Chariot Allegory from the Phaedrus is possibly Plato’s most important teaching on how to achieve inner happiness.

Plato sees societal happiness stemming from citizens treating each other justly, leading virtuous lives, and each fulfilling their social function. [6]

Aristotle

A marble statue of Aristotle, created by Romans in 330 BC. Aristotle Altemps Inv8575.jpg
A marble statue of Aristotle, created by Romans in 330 BC.

Aristotle (384 – 322 BCE) was considered an ancient Greek scholar in the disciplines of ethics, metaphysics, biology and botany, amongst others. [7] Aristotle described eudaimonia (Greek: εὐδαιμονία) as the goal of human thought and action. Eudaimonia is often translated to mean happiness, but some scholars contend that "human flourishing" may be a more accurate translation. [8] More specifically, eudaimonia ( arete , Greek: ἀρετή) refers to an inherently positive and divine state of being in which humanity can actively strive for and achieve. Given that this state is the most positive state for a human to be in, it is often simplified to mean happiness. However, Aristotle's use of the term in Nicomachiean Ethics extends beyond the general sense of happiness. [9]

Within the Nicomachean Ethics , Aristotle points to the fact that many aims are really only intermediate aims, and are desired only because they make the achievement of higher aims possible. [10] Therefore, things such as wealth, intelligence, and courage are valued only in relation to other things, while eudaimonia is the only thing valuable by itself.

Aristotle regarded virtue as necessary for a person to be happy and held that without virtue the most that may be attained is contentment. Within Aristotelian ethics, achieving virtue involves asking the question "how should I be" rather than "what should I do". A fully virtuous person is described as achieving eudaimonia, and therefore would be undeniably happy. [7] [11]

Cynics

The carved busts of Socrates, Antisthenes, Chrysippus, and Epicurus. Greek philosopher busts.jpg
The carved busts of Socrates, Antisthenes, Chrysippus, and Epicurus.

Antisthenes (c. 445 – c. 365 BCE), often regarded as the founder of Cynicism, advocated an ascetic life lived in accordance with virtue. Xenophon testifies that Antisthenes had praised the joy that sprang "from out of one's soul," [12] and Diogenes Laërtius relates that Antisthenes was fond of saying: "I would rather go mad than feel pleasure." [13] He maintained that virtue was sufficient in itself to ensure happiness, only needing the strength of a Socrates.

He, along with all following Cynics, rejected any conventional notions of happiness involving money, power, and fame, to lead entirely virtuous, and thus happy, lives. [14] Thus, happiness can be gained through rigorous training (askesis, Greek: ἄσκησις) and by living in a way which was natural for humans, rejecting all conventional desires, preferring a simple life free from all possessions.

Diogenes of Sinope (c. 412 – c. 323 BCE) is most frequently seen as the perfect embodiment of the philosophy. The Stoics themselves saw him as one of the few, if not only, who have had achieved the state of sage. [15]

Cyrenaics

As a consequence the sage, even if he has his troubles, will nonetheless be happy, even if few pleasures accrue to him.

The Cyrenaics were a school of philosophy established by Aristippus of Cyrene (c. 435 – c. 356 BCE). The school asserted that the only good is positive pleasure, and pain is the only evil. They posit that all feeling is momentary so all past and future pleasure have no real existence for an individual, and that among present pleasures there is no distinction of kind. [18] Claudius Aelianus, in his Historical Miscellany, [19] writes about Aristippus:

"He recommended that one should concrete on the present day, and indeed on the very part of it in which one is acting and thinking. For only the present, he said, truly belongs to us, and not what has passed by or what we are anticipating: for the one is gone and done with, and it is uncertain whether the other will come to be" [20]

Some immediate pleasures can create more than their equivalent of pain. The wise person should be in control of pleasures rather than be enslaved to them, otherwise pain will result, and this requires judgement to evaluate the different pleasures of life. [21]

Pyrrho

Pyrrho (c. 360 – c. 270 BCE) founded Pyrrhonism, the first Western school of philosophical skepticism. The goal of Pyrrhonist practice is to attain the state of ataraxia (ataraxia, Greek: ἀταραξία) – freedom from perturbation. Pyrrho identified that what prevented people from attaining ataraxia was their beliefs in non-evident matters, i.e., holding dogmas. To free people from belief the ancient Pyrrhonists developed a variety of skeptical arguments.

Epicurus

Of all the means which wisdom acquires to ensure happiness throughout the whole of life, by far the most important is friendship.

Epicurus [22]

Epicurus (c. 341 – c. 270 BCE), the founder of Epicureanism, taught that the aim of life was to attain a state of tranquility (ataraxia, Greek: ἀταραξία) and freedom from fear, as well as absence of bodily pain (aponia, Greek: ἀπονία). Toward these ends, Epicurus recommended an ascetic lifestyle, noble friendship, and the avoidance of politics.

One aid to achieving happiness is the tetrapharmakos or the four-fold cure:

A papyrus copy depicting the Epicurean tetrapharmakos in Philodemus of Gadara's Adversus Sophistas - (P.Herc.1005), col. 5 Tetrapharmakos PHerc 1005 col 5.png
A papyrus copy depicting the Epicurean tetrapharmakos in Philodemus of Gadara's Adversus Sophistas(P.Herc.1005), col. 5

"Do not fear god,
Do not worry about death;
What is good is easy to get, and
What is terrible is easy to endure."
( Philodemus, Herculaneum Papyrus, 1005, 4.9–14). [23]

Stoics

If you work at that which is before you, following right reason seriously, vigorously, calmly, without allowing anything else to distract you, but keeping your divine part pure, as if you were bound to give it back immediately; if you hold to this, expecting nothing, but satisfied to live now according to nature, speaking heroic truth in every word that you utter, you will live happy. And there is no man able to prevent this.

Stoicism was a school of philosophy established by Zeno of Citium (c. 334 – c. 262 BCE). While Zeno was syncretic in thought, his primary influence were the Cynics, with Crates of Thebes (c. 365 – c. 285 BCE) as his mentor. Stoicism is a philosophy of personal ethics that provides a system of logic and views about the natural world. [25]

Modern use of the term "stoic" typically refers not to followers of Stoicism, but to individuals who feel indifferent to experiences of the world, or represses feelings in general. [26] Given Stoicism's emphasis on feeling indifferent to negativity, it is seen as a path to achieving happiness. [27]

Stoics believe that "virtue is sufficient for happiness". [28] One who has attained this sense of virtue would become a sage. In the words of Epictetus, this sage would be "sick and yet happy, in peril and yet happy, dying and yet happy, in exile and happy, in disgrace and happy." [29]

The Stoics therefore spent their time trying to attain virtue. This would only be achieved if one was to dedicate their life studying Stoic logic, Stoic physics, and Stoic ethics. Stoics describe themselves as "living in agreement with nature." Certain schools of Stoicism refer to Aristotle's concept of eudaimonia as the goal of practicing Stoic philosophy. [30]

Ancient Rome

School of the Sextii

The School of the Sextii was founded by Quintus Sextius the Elder (fl. 50 BCE). It characterized itself mainly as a philosophical-medical school, blending Pythagorean, Platonic, Cynic, and Stoic elements together. [31] They argued that to achieve happiness, one ought to be vegetarian, have nightly examinations of conscience, and avoid both consumerism and politics, [32] and believe that an elusive incorporeal power pervades the body. [31]

Augustine of Hippo

The happy life is joy based on the truth. This is joy grounded in you, O God, who are the truth.

St. Augustine, Confessions . [33]

St. Augustine of Hippo (354 – 430 AD) was an early Christian theologian and philosopher [34] whose writings influenced the development of Western Christianity and Western philosophy.

For St. Augustine, all human actions revolve around love, and the primary problem humans face is the misplacing of love. [35] Only in God can one find happiness, as He is source of happiness. Since humanity was brought forth from God, but has since fallen, one's soul dimly remembers the happiness from when one was with God. [36] Thus, if one orients themselves toward the love of God, all other loves will become properly ordered. [37] In this manner, St. Augustine follows the Neoplatonic tradition in asserting that happiness lays in the contemplation of the purely intelligible realm. [36]

St. Augustine deals with the concept of happiness directly in his treatises De beata vita and Contra Academicos. [36]

Boethius

Mortal creatures have one overall concern. This they work at by toiling over a whole range of pursuits, advancing on different paths, but striving to attain the one goal of happiness.

Boethius (c. 480–524 AD) was a philosopher, most famous for writing The Consolation of Philosophy . The work has been described as having had the single most important influence on the Christianity of the Middle Ages and early Renaissance and as the last great work of the Classical Period. [39] [note 1] The book describes many themes, but among them he discusses how happiness can be attainable despite changing fortune, while considering the nature of happiness and God.

He posits that happiness is acquired by attaining the perfect good, and that perfect good is God. [38] He then concludes that as God ruled the universe through Love, prayer to God and the application of Love would lead to true happiness. [40]

Middle Ages

Avicenna

A drawing of Avicenna, 1960. Avicenna Drawing.jpg
A drawing of Avicenna, 1960.

Avicenna (c. 980–1037), also known as 'Ibn-Sina', was a polymath and jurist; he is regarded as one of the most significant thinkers in the Islamic Golden Age. [41] According to him, happiness is the aim of humans, and that real happiness is pure and free from worldly interest. [42] Ultimately, happiness is reached through the conjunction of the human intellect with the separate active intellect. [43]

Al-Ghazali

Al-Ghazali (c. 1058–1111) was a Muslim theologian, jurist, philosopher, and mystic of Persian descent. [44] Produced near the end of his life, al-Ghazali wrote The Alchemy of Happiness (Kimiya-yi Sa'ādat, (Persian : كيمياى سعادت). [45] In the work, he emphasizes the importance of observing the ritual requirements of Islam, the actions that would lead to salvation, and the avoidance of sin. According to Al-Ghazali, there are four main constituents of happiness: self-knowledge, knowledge of God, knowledge of this world as it really is, and the knowledge of the next world as it really is. [46] Only by exercising the human faculty of reason – a God-given ability – can one transform the soul from worldliness to complete devotion to God, the ultimate happiness. [47]

Maimonides

Maimonides (c. 1135–1204) was a Jewish philosopher and astronomer, [48] who became one of the most prolific and influential Torah scholars and physicians. [49] He writes that happiness is ultimately and essentially intellectual. [50]

Thomas Aquinas

Man is not perfectly happy, so long as something remains for him to desire and seek.

St. Thomas Aquinas (1225 – 1274 AD) was a philosopher and theologian who became a Doctor of the Church in 1323. [51] He syncretized Aristotelianism and Catholic theology in his magnum opus Summa Theologica . [52]

According to Thomas Aquinas, perfect happiness cannot be found in any physical pleasure, any amount of worldly power, any degree of temporal fame or honor, or indeed in any finite reality. [53] It can only be found in something that is infinite and perfect – and this is God. [54] And since God is not a material thing but is pure spirit, we are united to God by knowing and loving Him. Consequently, the union with God is the most perfect human happiness and the ultimate goal of human life. [55]

Early Modern

Michel de Montaigne

Michel de Montaigne (1533–1592) was a French philosopher. Influenced by Hellenistic philosophy and Christianity, alongside the conviction of the separation of public and private spheres of life, Montaigne writes that happiness is a subjective state of mind and that satisfaction differs from person to person. [56] He continues by acknowledging that one must be allowed a private sphere of life to realize those particular attempts of happiness without the interference of society. [56]

Jeremy Bentham

Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) was a British philosopher, jurist, and social reformer. He is regarded as the founder of modern utilitarianism.

The right course of action, according to Jeremy Bentham, is that which causes the highest amount of utility, where utility is defined as the aggregate pleasure (happiness) minus any suffering (pain) of each individual affected by the action. [57] For the purpose of calculating utility of a given action, he devised Felicific calculus. According to this calculus, for example, ascetic sacrifice is morally wrong. [57]

Arthur Schopenhauer

Arthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860) was a German philosopher. His philosophy express that egotistical acts are those that are guided by self-interest, desire for pleasure or happiness, whereas only compassion can be a moral act.

Schopenhauer explains happiness in terms of a wish that is satisfied, which in turn gives rise to a new wish. And the absence of satisfaction is suffering, which results in an empty longing. He also links happiness with the movement of time, as we feel happy when time moves faster and feel sad when time slows down. [58]

Nietzsche


Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900) was a German philosopher, poet, cultural critic, and philologist whose work has exerted a profound influence on contemporary philosophy. Nietzsche critiqued the English Utilitarians' focus on attaining the greatest happiness, stating that "Man does not strive for happiness, only the Englishman does". [59] Nietzsche meant that making happiness one's ultimate goal and the aim of one's existence, in his words "makes one contemptible." Nietzsche instead yearned for a culture that would set higher, more difficult goals than "mere happiness." He introduced the quasi-dystopic figure of the "last man" as a kind of thought experiment against the utilitarians and happiness-seekers. [60] [61]

These "small men" who seek after only their own pleasure and health, avoiding all danger, exertion, difficulty, challenge, and struggle are contemptible. Nietzsche instead wants us to consider the value of what is difficult, what can only be earned through struggle, difficulty, and pain. He wants us to consider the affirmative value of suffering and unhappiness which create everything of great worth in life, including all the highest achievements of human culture, not least of all philosophy. [62] [63]

Contemporary

Władysław Tatarkiewicz

Władysław Tatarkiewicz (1886–1980) was a Polish philosopher and historian. For Tatarkiewicz, happiness is a fundamental ethical category and true happiness requires total satisfaction, that is, satisfaction with life as a whole. [64]

Herbert Marcuse

Herbert Marcuse (1898–1979) was a German-American philosopher, sociologist, and political theorist, associated with the Frankfurt School of critical theory.

In his 1937 essay 'The Affirmative Character of Culture,' he suggests culture develops tension within the structure of society, and in that tension can challenge the current social order. If it separates itself from the everyday world, the demand for happiness will cease to be external, and begin to become an object of spiritual contemplation. [65] In the One-Dimensional Man , his criticism of consumerism suggests that the current system is one that claims to be democratic, but is authoritarian in character, as only a few individuals dictate the perceptions of freedom by only allowing certain choices of happiness to be available for purchase. [66] He further suggests that the conception that 'happiness can be bought' is one that is psychologically damaging.

Viktor Frankl

It is a characteristic of the American culture that, again and again, one is commanded and ordered to 'be happy.' But happiness cannot be pursued; it must ensue. One must have a reason to 'be happy'.

Viktor Frankl (1905–1997) was an Austrian neurologist, psychiatrist, Holocaust survivor and founder of logotherapy. His philosophy revolved around the emphasis on meaning, the value of suffering, and responsibility to something greater than the self; [67] only if one encounters those questions can one be happy.

Robert Nozick

Robert Nozick (1938–2002) was an American philosopher and professor at Harvard University. He is best known for his political philosophy and for his thought experiments. [68]

In the Experience Machine (1974) thought experiment he criticizes hedonistic notions of happiness by imagining a choice between everyday reality and an apparently preferable simulated reality which provides unlimited enjoyment. [69] The utility monster (1974) is a thought experiment created by Robert Nozick to criticize utilitarian notion of aggregate pleasure (happiness). [70]

Michel Onfray

Michel Onfray (born 1959) is a French writer and philosopher with a hedonistic, epicurean, and atheist worldview. In La puissance d'exister: Manifeste hédoniste, Onfray claims that the political dimension of hedonism runs from Epicurus to John Stuart Mill to Jeremy Bentham and Claude Adrien Helvétius. Political hedonism aims to create the greatest happiness for the greatest numbers. Onfray defines hedonism "as an introspective attitude to life based on taking pleasure yourself and pleasuring others, without harming yourself or anyone else." [71]

David Pearce

David Pearce (born 1959) is a British transhumanist philosopher who approaches ethical issues from a lexical negative utilitarian perspective. [72] [73] [74]

See also

Notes

  1. Dante identified Boethius as the "last of the Romans and first of the Scholastics" among the doctors in his Paradise (see The Divine Comedy and also below).

Related Research Articles

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Epicurus</span> Ancient Greek philosopher, founder of Epicureanism

Epicurus was an ancient Greek philosopher and sage who founded Epicureanism, a highly influential school of philosophy. He was born on the Greek island of Samos to Athenian parents. Influenced by Democritus, Aristippus, Pyrrho, and possibly the Cynics, he turned against the Platonism of his day and established his own school, known as "the Garden", in Athens. Epicurus and his followers were known for eating simple meals and discussing a wide range of philosophical subjects. He openly allowed women and slaves to join the school as a matter of policy. Of the over 300 works said to have been written by Epicurus about various subjects, the vast majority have been destroyed. Only three letters written by him—the letters to Menoeceus, Pythocles, and Herodotus—and two collections of quotes—the Principal Doctrines and the Vatican Sayings—have survived intact, along with a few fragments of his other writings. As a result of his work's destruction, most knowledge about his philosophy is due to later authors, particularly the biographer Diogenes Laërtius, the Epicurean Roman poet Lucretius and the Epicurean philosopher Philodemus, as well as the hostile but largely accurate accounts by the Pyrrhonist philosopher Sextus Empiricus, and the Academic Skeptic and statesman Cicero.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Zeno of Citium</span> Hellenistic philosopher, founder of Stoicism (c. 334–c. 262 BC)

Zeno of Citium was a Hellenistic philosopher from Citium, Cyprus. He was the founder of the Stoic school of philosophy, which he taught in Athens from about 300 BC. Based on the moral ideas of the Cynics, Stoicism laid great emphasis on goodness and peace of mind gained from living a life of virtue in accordance with nature. It proved very popular, and flourished as one of the major schools of philosophy from the Hellenistic period through to the Roman era, and enjoyed revivals in the Renaissance as Neostoicism and in the current era as Modern Stoicism.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Epicureanism</span> Philosophical system

Epicureanism is a system of philosophy founded around 307 BCE based upon the teachings of Epicurus, an ancient Greek philosopher. Epicurus was an atomist and materialist, following in the steps of Democritus. His materialism led him to religious skepticism and a general attack on superstition and divine intervention. Epicureanism was originally a challenge to Platonism, and its main opponent later became Stoicism. It is a form of hedonism insofar as it declares pleasure to be its sole intrinsic goal. However, the concept that the absence of pain and fear constitutes the greatest pleasure, and its advocacy of a simple life, make it very different from hedonism as colloquially understood.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Antisthenes</span> Greek philosopher, founder of Cynicism (c.446–c.366 BCE)

Antisthenes was a Greek philosopher and a pupil of Socrates. Antisthenes first learned rhetoric under Gorgias before becoming an ardent disciple of Socrates. He adopted and developed the ethical side of Socrates' teachings, advocating an ascetic life lived in accordance with virtue. Later writers regarded him as the founder of Cynic philosophy.

Ancient Greek philosophy arose in the 6th century BC. Philosophy was used to make sense of the world using reason. It dealt with a wide variety of subjects, including astronomy, epistemology, mathematics, political philosophy, ethics, metaphysics, ontology, logic, biology, rhetoric and aesthetics. Greek philosophy continued throughout the Hellenistic period and later evolved into Roman philosophy.

Eudaimonia, sometimes anglicized as eudaemonia or eudemonia, is a Greek word literally translating to the state or condition of 'good spirit', and which is commonly translated as 'happiness' or 'welfare'.

In Ancient Greek philosophy, ataraxia —generally translated as "unperturbedness", "imperturbability", "equanimity", or "tranquility"— is a lucid state of robust equanimity characterized by ongoing freedom from distress and worry. In non-philosophical usage, ataraxia was the ideal mental state for soldiers entering battle. Achieving ataraxia is a common goal for Pyrrhonism, Epicureanism, and Stoicism, but the role and value of ataraxia within each philosophy varies in accordance with their philosophical theories. The mental disturbances that prevent one from achieving ataraxia also vary among the philosophies, and each philosophy has a different understanding as to how to achieve ataraxia.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Virtue ethics</span> Normative ethical theories

Virtue ethics is an approach that treats virtue and character as the primary subjects of ethics, in contrast to other ethical systems that put consequences of voluntary acts, principles or rules of conduct, or obedience to divine authority in the primary role.

Eternal return is a philosophical concept which states that time repeats itself in an infinite loop, and that exactly the same events will continue to occur in exactly the same way, over and over again, for eternity.

Summum bonum is a Latin expression meaning the highest or ultimate good, which was introduced by the Roman philosopher Cicero to denote the fundamental principle on which some system of ethics is based — that is, the aim of actions, which, if consistently pursued, will lead to the best possible life. Since Cicero, the expression has acquired a secondary meaning as the essence or ultimate metaphysical principle of Goodness itself, or what Plato called the Form of the Good. These two meanings do not necessarily coincide. For example, Epicurean and Cyrenaic philosophers claimed that the 'good life' consistently aimed for pleasure, without suggesting that pleasure constituted the meaning or essence of Goodness outside the ethical sphere. In De finibus, Cicero explains and compares the ethical systems of several schools of Greek philosophy, including Stoicism, Epicureanism, Aristotelianism and Platonism, based on how each defines the ethical summum bonum differently.

Aristo of Chios, also spelled Ariston, was a Greek Stoic philosopher and colleague of Zeno of Citium. He outlined a system of Stoic philosophy that was, in many ways, closer to earlier Cynic philosophy. He rejected the logical and physical sides of philosophy endorsed by Zeno and emphasized ethics. Although agreeing with Zeno that Virtue was the supreme good, he rejected the idea that morally indifferent things such as health and wealth could be ranked according to whether they are naturally preferred. An important philosopher in his day, his views were eventually marginalized by Zeno's successors.

Ancient Roman philosophy is philosophy as it was practiced in the Roman Republic and its successor state, the Roman Empire. Roman philosophy includes not only philosophy written in Latin, but also philosophy written in Greek in the late Republic and Roman Empire. Important early Latin-language writers include Lucretius, Cicero, and Seneca the Younger. Greek was a popular language for writing about philosophy, so much so that the Roman Emperor Marcus Aurelius chose to write his Meditations in Greek.

Hellenistic philosophy is Ancient Greek philosophy corresponding to the Hellenistic period in Ancient Greece, from the death of Alexander the Great in 323 BC to the Battle of Actium in 31 BC. The dominant schools of this period were the Stoics, the Epicureans and the Skeptics.

Western philosophy refers to the philosophical thought and work of the Western world. Historically, the term refers to the philosophical thinking of Western culture, beginning with the ancient Greek philosophy of the pre-Socratics. The word philosophy itself originated from the Ancient Greek philosophía (φιλοσοφία), literally, "the love of wisdom" Ancient Greek: φιλεῖν phileîn, "to love" and σοφία sophía, "wisdom").

This page is a list of topics in ancient philosophy.

Apatheia, in Stoicism, refers to a state of mind in which one is not disturbed by the passions. It might better be translated by the word equanimity than the word indifference. The meaning of the word apatheia is quite different from that of the modern English apathy, which has a distinctly negative connotation that includes feelings of inertness, indifference, and impassiveness. According to the Stoics, apatheia was the quality that characterized the sage.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Cynicism (philosophy)</span> Ancient school of philosophy

Cynicism is a school of thought in ancient Greek philosophy, originating in the Classical period and extending into the Hellenistic and Roman Imperial periods. According to Cynicism, people are reasoning animals and the purpose of life and the way to gain happiness is to achieve virtue, in agreement with nature, following one's natural sense of reason by living simply and shamelessly free from social constraints. The Cynics rejected all conventional desires for wealth, power, glory, social recognition, conformity, and worldly possessions and even flouted such conventions openly and derisively in public.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Stoicism</span> Philosophical system

Stoicism is a school of Hellenistic philosophy that flourished in Ancient Greece and Ancient Rome. The Stoics believed that the practice of virtue is enough to achieve eudaimonia: a well-lived life. The Stoics identified the path to achieving it with a life spent practicing the four virtues in everyday life: wisdom, courage, temperance or moderation, and justice, and living in accordance with nature. It was founded in the ancient Agora of Athens by Zeno of Citium around 300 BC.

A sage, in classical philosophy, is someone who has attained wisdom. The term has also been used interchangeably with a 'good person', and a 'virtuous person'. Among the earliest accounts of the sage begin with Empedocles' Sphairos. Horace describes the Sphairos as "Completely within itself, well-rounded and spherical, so that nothing extraneous can adhere to it, because of its smooth and polished surface." Alternatively, the sage is one who lives "according to an ideal which transcends the everyday."

Ethics is the branch of philosophy that examines right and wrong moral behavior, moral concepts and moral language. Ethics or moral philosophy is a branch of philosophy that "involves systematizing, defending, and recommending concepts of right and wrong behavior". The field of ethics, along with aesthetics, concerns matters of value, and thus comprises the branch of philosophy called axiology.

References

  1. Cassin et al. Dictionary of Untranslatables. Princeton University Press, 2014. Print.
  2. Happiness. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2011.{{cite book}}: |website= ignored (help)
  3. Sturt, Henry (1903). "Happiness". International Journal of Ethics. 13 (2): 207–221. doi:10.1086/intejethi.13.2.2376452. JSTOR   2376452. S2CID   222446622.
  4. Democritus. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2016.{{cite book}}: |website= ignored (help)
  5. Johnson, Claire (28 July 2022). "How to Be Happy According to Plato". TheCollector.
  6. Mohr, Richard D. (1987). "A Platonic Happiness". History of Philosophy Quarterly. 4 (2): 131–145. JSTOR   27743804.
  7. 1 2 Dimmock, Mark; Fisher, Andrew (2017). "Aristotelian Virtue Ethics". Ethics for A-Level. Open Book Publishers. pp. 49–63. ISBN   978-1-78374-388-9. JSTOR   j.ctt1wc7r6j.7.
  8. Daniel N. Robinson. (1999). Aristotle's Psychology. Published by Daniel N. Robinson. ISBN   0-9672066-0-X ISBN   978-0967206608
  9. Aristotle., Bartlett, R. C., & Collins, S. D. (2011). Aristotle's Nicomachean ethics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  10. Book I Chapter 1 1094a.
  11. Kraut, Richard, "Aristotle's Ethics", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2012 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/aristotle-ethics/>
  12. Xenophon, Symposium, iv. 41.
  13. Diogenes Laërtius, Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers , vi. 3
  14. CynicsThe Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  15. "The Stoic Sage". ancientworlds.net.
  16. Diogenes Laërtius, Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers , ii. 96–97
  17. Diogenes the Cynics: Sayings and Anecdotes with Other Popular Moralists, trans. Robin Hard. Oxford University Press, 2012. Page 152.
  18. Annas, Julia (1995). The Morality of Happiness . Oxford University Press. p.  230. ISBN   0-19-509652-5.
  19. Aelian, Historical Miscellany 14.6
  20. Diogenes the Cynics: Sayings and Anecdotes with Other Popular Moralists, trans. Robin Hard. Oxford University Press, 2012. Page 124.
  21. Copleston, Frederick Charles (2003). A History of Philosophy: Book 1. Continuum International. p. 122. ISBN   0-8264-6895-0.
  22. Vincent Cook. "Epicurus – Principal Doctrines". epicurus.net. Archived from the original on 7 April 2007. Retrieved 3 October 2015.
  23. Hutchinson, D. S. (Introduction) (1994). The Epicurus Reader: Selected Writings and Testimonia. Cambridge: Hackett. p. vi.
  24. Marcus Aurelius, Meditations . iii.12
  25. Sharpe, Matthew. "Stoic Virtue Ethics." Handbook of Virtue Ethics, 2013, 28–41.
  26. "Modern Stoicism | Build The Fire". Build The Fire. 9 February 2016. Retrieved 22 June 2016.
  27. Harper, Douglas (November 2001). "Online Etymology Dictionary – Stoic". Retrieved 2 September 2006.
  28. Stoicism, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  29. Russell, Bertrand. A History of Western Philosophy
  30. Inwood, Brad (1986). "Goal and Target in Stoicism". The Journal of Philosophy. 83 (10): 547–556. doi:10.2307/2026429. JSTOR   2026429.
  31. 1 2 Paola, Omar Di (13 June 2014). "Philosophical thought of the School of the Sextii – Di Paola – EPEKEINA. International Journal of Ontology. History and Critics". Ricercafilosofica.it. 4 (1–2). doi:10.7408/epkn.v4i1-2.74.
  32. Emily Wilson, The Greatest Empire: A Life of Seneca. Oxford University Press, 2014. p.54-55
  33. St. Augustine, Confessions. Trans, Henry Chadwick. Oxford University Press, 2008. p:199
  34. Mendelson, Michael (24 March 2000). Saint Augustine. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 21 December 2012.
  35. https://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/ethics-everyone/201106/achieving-hapGenesis creation narrativepiness-advice-augustine
  36. 1 2 3 O'Connell, R. J. (1963). "The Enneads and St. Augustine's Image of Happiness". Vigiliae Christianae. 17 (3): 129–164. doi:10.2307/1582804. JSTOR   1582804.
  37. "Achieving Happiness: Advice from Augustine". Psychology Today.
  38. 1 2 "True Happiness and The Consolation of Philosophy". catholic.com. Archived from the original on 20 December 2016. Retrieved 3 October 2015.
  39. Introduction to The Consolation of Philosophy, Oxford World's Classics, 2000.
  40. Sanderson Beck (1996).
  41. "Avicenna (Persian philosopher and scientist) – Britannica Online Encyclopedia". Britannica.com. Retrieved 7 January 2012.
  42. Engebretson, Kath; de Souza, Marian; Durka, Gloria; Gearon, Liam (17 August 2010). International Handbook of Inter-religious Education. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 208. ISBN   978-1-4020-9260-2.
  43. "Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the Latin West". stanford.edu. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2018.
  44. "Ghazali, al-". The Columbia Encyclopedia. Retrieved 17 December 2012.
  45. Böwering, Gerhard (1995). "Review of The Alchemy of Happiness, Abû Hâmid Muḥammad al-Ghazzâlî". Journal of Near Eastern Studies. 54 (3): 227–228. doi:10.1086/373761. JSTOR   546305.
  46. Imam Muhammad Al-Ghazali (1910). "The Alchemy of Happiness" . Retrieved 8 January 2016.PD-icon.svg This article incorporates text from this source, which is in the public domain .
  47. Bodman, Herbert L. (1993). "Review of The Alchemy of Happiness". Journal of World History. 4 (2): 336–338. JSTOR   20078571.
  48. Maimonides: Abū ʿImrān Mūsā [Moses] ibn ʿUbayd Allāh [Maymūn] al-Qurṭubī
  49. A Biographical and Historiographical Critique of Moses Maimonides Archived 24 May 2013 at the Wayback Machine
  50. "Maimonides – Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". utm.edu.
  51. Catholic Online. "St. Thomas Aquinas". catholic.org.
  52. "Aquinas: Moral Philosophy – Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". utm.edu.
  53. "Summa Theologica: Things in which man's happiness consists (Prima Secundae Partis, Q. 2, a. 8)". www.newadvent.org.
  54. "Summa Theologica: What is happiness (Prima Secundae Partis, Q. 3, a. 8)". www.newadvent.org.
  55. "Summa Theologica: How God is known by us (Prima Pars, Q. 12, a. 4)". www.newadvent.org.
  56. 1 2 "Montaigne, Michel de – Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". utm.edu.
  57. 1 2 "Bentham, Jeremy – Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". utm.edu.
  58. Arthur Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Idea. Cologne 1997, Volume One, §52th.
  59. Nietzsche, Friedrich (1889). Twilight of the Idols. OUP Oxford. p. 1. ISBN   978-0140445145.
  60. "Nietzsche's Moral and Political Philosophy". stanford.edu. Archived from the original on 12 January 2012. Retrieved 10 August 2015.
  61. "Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–2004)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 15 August 2015. Retrieved 10 August 2015.
  62. "Nietzsche's Moral and Political Philosophy". stanford.edu. Archived from the original on 12 January 2012. Retrieved 10 August 2015.
  63. "Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–2004)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 15 August 2015. Retrieved 10 August 2015.
  64. Alex Michalos Review of W. Tatarkiewicz, "Analysis of Happiness".
  65. Herbert Marcuse. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2017.{{cite book}}: |website= ignored (help)
  66. Marcuse, Herbert (1991). "Introduction to the Second Edition". One-dimensional Man: studies in ideology of advanced industrial society. London: Routledge. p. 3. ISBN   978-0-415-07429-2.
  67. 1 2 Smith, Emily Esfahani (22 October 2014). "A Psychiatrist Who Survived The Holocaust Explains Why Meaningfulness Matters More Than Happiness". Business Insider. The Atlantic.
  68. Feser, Edward (4 May 2005). "Nozick, Robert". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy .
  69. Nozick, Robert (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia . New York: Basic Books. pp.  42–45. ISBN   0-465-09720-0.
  70. Kennard, Frederick (20 March 2015). Thought Experiments: Popular Thought Experiments in Philosophy, Physics, Ethics, Computer Science & Mathematics (First ed.). AMF. p. 322. ISBN   9781329003422.
  71. "Atheism à la mode – New Humanist". newhumanist.org.uk. 29 June 2007.
  72. Schneider, Susan. "Future Minds: Transhumanism, Cognitive Enhancement and the Nature of Persons". Penn Libraries. University of Pennsylvania. Retrieved 29 September 2022.
  73. Dobrodum, Olga; Kyvliuk, Olga (29 January 2021). "Transhumanism and Posthumanism: Reflection of the Human Civilization Future" (PDF). Philosophy and Cosmology. 26: 77–89. doi:10.29202/phil-cosm/26/6. S2CID   234292838 . Retrieved 29 September 2022.
  74. "Negative Utilitarianism FAQ". www.utilitarianism.com. Retrieved 14 September 2019.

Further reading