School of Names | |||||||||||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Chinese | 名家 | ||||||||||||||
| |||||||||||||||
Alternative Chinese name | |||||||||||||||
Chinese | 形名家 | ||||||||||||||
Literal meaning | School of forms and names | ||||||||||||||
|
The School of Names,or School of Forms and Names, [1] is a school of thought in Chinese philosophy that grew out of Mohist logic. Sometimes termed Logicians or Sophists modernly,Han scholars used it in reference to figures earlier termed Disputers in the Zhuangzi,as a view seemingly dating back to the Warring States period (c. 479 –221 BC). Rather than a unified movement like the Mohists,it represents a social category of early linguistic debaters. Some arguments in later Mohist texts would appear directed at their kind of debates. Figures associated with it include Deng Xi,Yin Wen,Hui Shi,and Gongsun Long. [2] A Three Kingdoms era figure,Xu Gan,is relevant for discussions of names and realities,but was more Confucian and less relativist.
Including figures referenced by the Zhuangzi,some likely served as a bridge between Mohism and the relativism of Zhuangzi Daoism. Hui Shi is noted for relativism,but also "embracing the ten thousand things". But he may not have had much connection with Gongsun Long,and they would have had backgrounds ranging from Mohist and Confucian to Daoistic. Gongsun Long is familiar with both Mohism and Confucianism,and is not always a relativist. He uses Confucianism to defend the White Horse Dialogue,believed in kindness and duty,and has a rectification of names doctrine aimed at actualities and social order. Willing to argue either side of an issue,they were taken as sophist by their critics,but some arguments were not necessarily intended to be paradoxical.
A contemporary of Confucius and the younger Mozi,Deng Xi,associated with litigation,is taken by Liu Xiang as the originator of the principle of xíngmíng,or ensuring that ministers' deeds (xing) harmonized with their words (ming). [3] A primary concern of the bureaucratically oriented Shen Buhai and Han Fei,some of their administrators would have had a concern for relations in the bureaucracy, [4] but with Gongsun Long as example,most were still likely more socially or philosophically oriented than the late,stringent Han Feizi;it cannot be assumed that many were familiar with Shang Yang.
The earliest literary occurrence for xingming is in the Zhan Guo Ce ,in reference to what would become known as the School of Names,amongst other more modern terms. The philosophy of the Logicians is often considered to be akin to those of the sophists or of the dialecticians. Joseph Needham notes that their works have been lost,except for the partially preserved oeuvre of Gongsun Long,and the paradoxes of Chapter 33 of the Zhuangzi . [5] Needham considers the disappearance of the greater part of Gongsun Long's work one of the worst losses in the ancient Chinese books,as what remains is said to reach the highest point of ancient Chinese philosophical writing. [1]
One of the few surviving lines from the school,"a one-foot stick,every day take away half of it,in a myriad ages it will not be exhausted",resembles Zeno's paradoxes. However,some of their other aphorisms seem contradictory or unclear when taken out of context,for example,"dogs are not hounds". As with the Legalists,Sinologist Kidder Smith highlights the mixed posthumous reception received by the school of names. Already opposed by the Later Mohists in their own era for their paradoxes,many of them,despite being remembered as sophists,would also have been administrators,with Hui Shi a prime minister,while Gongsun Long was a diplomat and peace activist,as typical of the Mohists. Shen Buhai may not have been familiar with Shang Yang,but likely was familiar with "school of names" type arguments on language and the correlation between the names and realities of things,with language useful in administration. [6] [7]
In the Han dynasty secretaries of government who had charge of the records of decisions in criminal matters would come to be called called xingming. The Han-era scholars Sima Qian (c. 145 –c. 86 BC) and Liu Xiang (77–6 BC) attribute it to the doctrine of Shen Buhai (400 –c. 337 BC). [8] Shen actually used the older,more philosophically common equivalent,ming-shi,or name and reality,linking the "Legalist doctrine of names" with the debates of the school of names. [9] [10] Such discussions are also prominent in the Han Feizi . [11]
Ming ('name') sometimes has the sense of "speech",so as to compare the statements of an aspiring officer with the reality of his actions—or of "reputation",again compared with real conduct (xing 'form' or shi 'reality'). [12] Two anecdotes in the Han Feizi provide examples—member of the School of Names Ni Yue argued that a white horse is not a horse,and defeated all debaters,but was still tolled at the gate. In another,the chief minister of Yan pretended to see a white horse dash out the gate. All of his subordinates denied having seen anything,save one,who ran out after it and returned claiming to have seen it,and was thereby identified as a flatterer. [13]
Shen Buhai's personnel control,or rectification of names such as titles thereby worked for "strict performance control" correlating claims,performances and posts. [14] It would become a central tenet of both Legalist statecraft and its Huang–Lao derivatives. Rather than having to look for "good" men,mingshi or xingming can seek the right man for a particular post,though doing so implies a total organizational knowledge of the regime. [15] More simply though,it can allow ministers to "name" themselves through accounts of specific cost and time frame,leaving their definition to competing ministers. Claims or utterances "bind the speaker to the realization a job". This was the doctrine favoured by Han Fei,with subtle differences. Favouring exactness,it combats the tendency to promise too much. The correct articulation of ming is considered crucial to the realization of projects. [16]
Chinese philosophy originates in the Spring and Autumn period and Warring States period, during a period known as the "Hundred Schools of Thought", which was characterized by significant intellectual and cultural developments. Although much of Chinese philosophy begun in the Warring States period, elements of Chinese philosophy have existed for several thousand years. Some can be found in the I Ching, an ancient compendium of divination, which dates back to at least 672 BCE.
Gongsun Long, courtesy name Zibing, was a Chinese philosopher, writer, and member of the School of Names, also known as the Logicians, of ancient Chinese philosophy. Gongsun ran a school and received patronage from rulers, advocating peaceful means of resolving disputes amid the martial culture of the Warring States period. His collected works comprise the Gongsun Longzi (公孫龍子) anthology. Comparatively few details are known about his life, and much of his work has been lost—only six of the fourteen essays he originally authored are still extant.
Fajia, or the School of fa, often translated as Legalism, is a school of mainly Warring States period classical Chinese philosophy. Often interpreted in the West along realist lines, its members works contributed variously to the formation of the bureaucratic Chinese empire, and early elements of Daoism. The later Han takes Guan Zhong as forefather of the Fajia. Its more Legalistic figures include ministers Li Kui and Shang Yang, and more Daoistic figures Shen Buhai and philosopher Shen Dao, with the late Han Feizi drawing on both. Later centuries took Xun Kuang as a teacher of Han Fei and Li Si. Succeeding emperors and reformers often followed the templates set by Han Fei, Shen Buhai and Shang Yang, but the Qin to Tang were more characterized by their traditions.
Shen Buhai was a Chinese statesman, reformer and diplomat. The Shiji records that he served as Chancellor of the Han state under Marquis Zhao of Han for fifteen years, from 351 or 354 BC to his natural death in office in around 337 BC. A contemporary of syncretist Shi Jiao and Shang Yang, he was born in the State of Zheng, and was likely a minor official there. After Han conquered Zheng in 375 BC, he rose up in the ranks of the Han officialdom, dividing up its territories and reforming it's administration and military defenses.
Shen Dao was a mid Warring states period Chinese philosopher and writer. Early remembered modernly for his influence on the Han Feizi with regards the concept of shi, most of his work would appear to have concerned the concept of fa commonly shared by others that the Han Confucian archivists classified as "Legalist". In his time, Shen Dao was more concerned with having laws, and argues the value of bad laws over no laws. His remaining fragments are the most substantial of any Jixia Academy scholar.
Han Fei, also known as Han Feizi, was a Chinese Legalist philosopher and statesman during the Warring States period. He was a prince of the state of Han.
The Han Feizi is an ancient Chinese text attributed to the Legalist political philosopher Han Fei. It comprises a selection of essays in the Legalist tradition, elucidating theories of state power, and synthesizing the methodologies of his predecessors. Its 55 chapters, most of which date to the Warring States period mid-3rd century BCE, are the only such text to survive fully intact. The Han Feizi is believed to contain the first commentaries on the Dao De Jing. Traditionally associated with the Qin dynasty, succeeding emperors and reformers were still influenced by Shen Buhai and the Han Feizi, with Shang Yang's current again coming to prominence in the time of Emperor Wu.
Wu wei is a polymorphic, ancient Chinese concept expressesing an ideal practice of "inaction", "inexertion" or "effortless action", as a state of personal harmony and free-flowing, spontaneous creative manifestation. Often centering on the behavior of the emperor, it most commonly refers to an ideal form of government. Wu wei emerged in the Spring and Autumn period, with early literary examples in the Classic of Poetry. It would become an important concept in the Confucian Analects, integrally connected to the Confucian ethic of practical morality as a state of spirit or being connecting intention and action. It would go on to become a central concept in "Legalist" statecraft and Daoism, including the political laissez-faire of the early Daoistic Han dynasty.
Zichan (c.581-522) was a Chinese statesman during the late Spring and Autumn period. From 543 until his death in 522 BCE, he served as the chief minister of the State of Zheng. Also known as Gongsun Qiao (traditional Chinese: 公孫僑; simplified Chinese: 公孙侨, he is better known by his courtesy name Zichan.
The White Horse Dialogue in Chinese philosophy is a debate between two unnamed speakers on a proposition often translated as 'a white horse is not a horse'. It appears in the Warring States period text Gongsun Longzi attributed to Gongsun Long, grouped under the philosophical School of Names in later taxonomies.
The Huainanzi is an ancient Chinese text consisting of a collection of essays resulting from a series of scholarly debates held at the court of Liu An, Prince of Huainan before 139 BCE. Compiled as a handbook for an enlightened sovereign and his court, the work attempts to define the conditions for a perfect socio-political order, derived mainly from a perfect ruler. Including Chinese folk theories of yin and yang and Wu Xing, the Huainanzi draws on Taoist, Legalist, Confucian, and Mohist concepts, but subverts the latter three in favor of a less active ruler, as prominent in the early Han dynasty before the Emperor Wu. The work is notable as a primary evidence of Zhuangzi influence in the Han.
The Guanzi is an anonymously written, foundational Chinese political and philosophical text. Compiled in the early Han dynasty, earlier versions potentially date back to the late Warring states period. At over 135,000 characters, it is one of the longest early Chinese philosophical texts. It covers broad subject matter, notably including price regulation of commodities via the concept of "light and heavy" (轻重). Despite its later dating, it is arguably one of the most representative texts of the concepts of political economy that developed during the Spring and Autumn period. Ming dynasty agricultural scientist Xu Guangqi still frequently cited the Guanzi and the Xunzi.
Sima Tan was a Chinese astrologist, astronomer, and historian during the Western Han dynasty. His work Records of the Grand Historian was completed by his son Sima Qian, who is considered the founder of Chinese historiography.
The rectification of names is originally a doctrine of feudal Confucian designations and relationships, behaving accordingly to ensure social harmony. Without such accordance society would essentially crumble and "undertakings would not be completed." Mencius extended the doctrine to include questions of political legitimacy.
Deng Xi was a Chinese philosopher and rhetorician associated with the School of Names. Once a senior official of the Zheng state, and a contemporary of Confucius, he is regarded as China's earliest known lawyer, with clever use of words and language in lawsuits. The Zuo Zhuan and Annals of Lü Buwei critically credit Deng with the authorship of a penal code, the earliest known statute in Chinese criminology entitled the "Bamboo Law". This was developed to take the place of the harsh, more Confucian criminal code developed by the Zheng statesman Zichan.
Huang–Lao was the most influential Chinese school of thought in the early Han dynasty, having its origins in a broader political-philosophical drive looking for solutions to strengthen the feudal order as depicted in Zhou politics. Not systematically explained by historiographer Sima Qian, it is generally interpreted as a school of Syncretism, developing into a major religion, the beginnings of religious Taoism.
State consequentialism is a modern minority theoretical interpretation of Mohist consequentialist ethics in Sinology, often intersecting with Chinese Legalism. Sinologist Fraser of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy interprets Mohist consequentialism, dating back to the 5th century BC, as the "world's earliest form of consequentialism, a remarkably sophisticated version based on a plurality of intrinsic goods taken as constitutive of human welfare". An ancient Chinese State consequentialist might evaluate the moral worth of an action based on how it contributes to the basic goods of a more particular entity: a state, with social order, material wealth, and population growth valued by both Mohists and "Legalists" like Shang Yang. The term has also been applied to the political philosophy of the Confucian philosopher Xunzi.
Fa is a concept in Chinese philosophy that concerns aspects of ethics, logic, and law. It can be accurately translated as 'law' in some contexts, but as a 'model' or 'standard' for behavior in most ancient texts, namely the Mozi, with prominent examples including the performance of carpentry. Although theoretically earlier, Fa comes to prominence in the Mohist school of thought. An administrative use of fa (models) is prominently elaborated in Legalism, but figures in the school of names also used fa (models) for litigation. Given it's broadness, use of the term fa even included medical models (theories).
Gongsun Hong was a senior official in the Western Han dynasty under Emperor Wu. Together with the more famous Confucian scholar Dong Zhongshu, Gongsun was one of the earliest proponents of Confucianism, setting in motion its emergence under the Han court. The ideals and decrees both promoted would come to be seen as values-in-themselves, becoming the "basic elements, or even hallmarks" of Confucianism, although not necessarily officially during his lifetime. While first proposed and more ardently promoted by Dong, the national academy and Imperial examination, then considered radical, did not come into existence until they were supported by the more successful Gongsun. Their establishment set a precedent that would last into the twentieth century.
{{citation}}
: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)Smith, Kidder (2003). "Sima Tan and the Invention of Daoism, "Legalism," et cetera". The Journal of Asian Studies . 62 (1): 129–156. doi:10.2307/3096138. JSTOR 3096138.