Medium essentialism

Last updated

Medium essentialism is a philosophical theory stating that each artform has its own distinctive medium, and that the essence of such an artform is dependent on its particular medium. [1] In practice, the theory argues that every artwork should manifest its essential properties, those which no other artform can employ. The theory relies on the presumption that every artform has a unique medium, and is divided into two main interpretations. The ‘limitation’ interpretation of medium essentialism argues that, due to their medium, some artforms should be constrained in their aspirations. The ‘productive’ interpretation reasons that a work's medium determines what content or style will function best, and that practitioners should pursue ventures aligning with the nature of this chosen medium. [1] Clement Greenberg is a prolific medium-essentialist in relation to modernist art, proposing that artists such as Jackson Pollock are successful because they properly exploit elements of their chosen medium, such as a painting's physical flatness. [2] However, medium essentialism was most propagated by film practitioners throughout the twentieth century, as it legitimised cinema as an artform for the first time. [3] Previously, film had been regarded as merely a recorded representation of a written play. [4] It is therefore most discussed today by film theorists, stemming from the work of critics such as André Bazin. [5] Regardless of the interpretation favoured, what constitutes a film's medium, and therefore essential meaning, has been heavily debated, [6] and has prompted the creation of several sub-theories. The theory has been widely discussed among contemporary film theorists [7] and has featured in the Anthology of the Philosophy of Film and Motion Pictures. [8]

Contents

Whilst medium essentialism is not merely a subcategory of the Essentialism theory, [6] it is relevant to the notion that certain characteristics are integral to every entity's purpose and identity. [9] Non-essentialism rejects the existence of such an 'essence'. Non-essentialism has been the view preferred by scholars such as Noël Carroll, criticising medium essentialism in relation to film. [10]

Dream medium essentialism

Theatrical release poster for The Love Light, a 1921 silent drama film that Langer argues demonstrates the movement of mainstream film from simple entertainment into an artform. The-Love-Light-Poster.jpg
Theatrical release poster for The Love Light, a 1921 silent drama film that Langer argues demonstrates the movement of mainstream film from simple entertainment into an artform.

The sub-theory of dream medium essentialism states that a film's essence is dependent upon its medium, adding that a film's medium is to be found in its creator's intention or ‘dream’. [11] Susanne K. Langer, in her book 'Feeling and Form,' posited this idea. [12] Langer reasoned that film had become its own medium through its use of 'the dream mode', or a direct visual portrayal of an artist's intentions and/or imagination. She pinpointed the time during which cinema began to classify itself as an artform as the early 1920s. She cited films such as The Love Light and The Blacksmith as demonstrating a shift from practitioners creating humorous entertainment or historically accurate texts, to an expression of artistic intentions that result in film being classified as a "new poetic mode." [12] Langer stated that, "The most noteworthy formal characteristic of dream" is that the dreamer "is always at the center of it", [13] the dreamer in this case representing a filmmaker. Langer proposed that a film's essence is determined by its medium (medium essentialism), and that its medium is determined by the 'dream' of its creator, director or practitioner.

Noël Carroll, however, rejects both medium essentialism and Langer's definition of a film's medium as constituted by its creator's 'dream'. [9] Carroll rebukes Langer's statement that the dreamer is 'always at the centre of' the film and that that proves the 'dream' as constituting a film's meaning/essence. He proposes that the "film viewer is not in the center of the array. She is typically off to one side." [1]  However, Livingston proposes that Carroll misreads Langer's argument, when it actually refers to the film creator - not the film consumer. [6] Carroll also quotes fellow anti-essentialist critic Stanley Cavell, who argues that dreams are often "boring narratives...their skimpy surface out of all proportion with their riddle interest and their effect on the dreamer." [14]

Photography medium essentialism

Roger Scruton's 'Philosophy of Representation' also agrees with the premise of medium essentialism in relation to film. [15] However, he proposes that since a photograph is transparent, it cannot constitute the essence of a work as it cannot express thought about its subject. [16] This argument relies on the presumption that every artform must be defined by an intention or thought, and not merely its physical substance. This perspective posits that the medium and essence of a photo or film-based artwork must be determined non-materially. [17] Numerically, his argument is as follows:

  1. A text's 'essence' must express an opinion regarding its subject.
  2. Photography is a transparent representation, and cannot express opinion of any sort.
  3. Film is, at its most essential, a photograph of a dramatic representation, and does not contain opinion.
  4. The essence of a film cannot lie in its material photography. [17]

Whilst not detailing the place that a film's medium (and therefore essence) should be found in, Scruton's theory rules out any physical location that a film's medium and essence could be found in. [18] It thereby indirectly supports dream medium essentialism.

Balázs' Requirement of Intention

Hungarian film critic and aesthete Bela Balazs, c. 1910s. Balazs was a key proponent of the idea that a film's physical material alone cannot constitute its essence or medium. Balazs Bela.jpg
Hungarian film critic and aesthete Béla Balázs, c. 1910s. Balázs was a key proponent of the idea that a film's physical material alone cannot constitute its essence or medium.

In addition to Scruton's proposition, Béla Balázs argued that as a film's physical constitution is transparent, it cannot carry any meaning about its content. [20] Balázs proposes, therefore, that an artform's essence must carry an intention about its subject - and this intention cannot be found within a film's photographic or audio elements. [19] For example, whilst a musical composition or an oil painting provides an opinion about its subject (due to the intention required by creating an artwork from scratch), a photograph cannot in itself contain artistic intention without additional elements being considered, such as a directorial vision or lighting.

Editing medium essentialism

Soviet theorists Dziga Vertov, Vsevolod Pudovkin and Sergei Eisenstein also concur with medium essentialism, adding that a film's medium (and therefore essence) lies in its editing. [21] Pudovkin's essay 'The Plastic Material' (1929) proposes that the manipulation of celluloid (or in the twenty-first century, digital editing) is what defines a film's medium. [21] This process would involve the physical alteration of photographic material, as well as intellectual engagement with what images a film should contain, in relation to the artistic intention of the filmmaker. [22] For example, a work's essence would be constituted by its medium, which is made up of the editing involved in filmwork. This editing, in turn, is fulfilled by physical editing of collected material, as well as a consideration of how that material fits with the overarching intention of the filmmaker. This intention may be related to a plot, or a broader artistic vision. [21] Concerned with a film's materiality, Pudovkin's interpretation of medium essentialism is agreed upon by later publications, including David Rodowick's The Virtual Life of Film (2007), Mary Ann Doane's The Emergence of Cinematic Time (2002), and Phil Rosen's Change Mummified (2001). [21]

Vertov added to this sub-theory, arguing that editing techniques constitute the film's semiotic system, [23] which contains the visual and auditory editing that manipulate recorded images - to the extent that they can create a sequence that has a particular outcome for the film holistically, as an artform in itself. [23] Eisenstein was also a proponent of editing medium essentialism, and within his essay 'Montage of Attractions', reiterated the idea that sound and image editing can be so transformative for the film and the narrative it tells that editing may be considered the essence of a film. [24] He proposed that montage was the defining characteristic of a film's medium and essence, [24] which is necessarily brought about by editing. He proposes that montage cannot simply be found in film and other photographic mediums such as Japanese pictographic writing, but also in natural phenomena like human perception more generally. Eisenstein claims that the medium of film, and the montage it contains, is a satisfaction of the human desire for an artform that contains this montage. [24]

Reality medium essentialism

Stanley Cavell proposes that a film's essence is defined by its medium, and that that medium lies partly within a film's portrayal of an illusion of reality, "Not by literally presenting us with a world, but by permitting us to view it unseen […] we are displaced from our natural habitation within it, placed at a distance from it." [25] Cavell proposed that a film's medium lies in its projection of reality, [26] a notion that is heavily contested by scholars such as Noël Carroll, as his argument relies on the premise that a film's value is determined by how well it represents reality for audiences. Cavell has an almost non-essential conception of a film's medium, [25] yet still subscribes to medium essentialism. [7] He argues a film's medium lies not within its physical material, but by the way in which it represents reality through an artform's ongoing re-invention. [27] Using the example of a 1975 Russian art film, Mirror, Cavell proposes that a filmmaker's accurate portrayal of reality from the perspective of a certain protagonist is what constitutes a film's medium, and therefore essence. [25]

Criticism

Noel Carroll, a prominent critic of medium essentialism in relation to film (pictured in 2005). Noel Carroll (2005).jpg
Noël Carroll, a prominent critic of medium essentialism in relation to film (pictured in 2005).

Medium essentialism has been criticised as heavily as it has been praised, [28] with many considering the theory 'narrow'. [29] Most critics of the idea reject the premise that every artform has a distinctive medium which necessarily determines its essence. [1]

V.F. Perkins was one of the first critics of the theory, who in the 1970s proposed that no one aspect of the film medium (photographic production, specifically) is superior to its counterparts (such as artistic intention or soundtrack). [30]

Noël Carroll is regarded as the most comprehensive critic of the theory. [30] His argument, within 'Theorising the Moving Image,' holds that medium essentialism is an inaccurate way to evaluate a work - as it requires the distillation of a film to one medium, when a film is constituted by not one, but several mediums. These mediums may include editing, lighting, narrative, photography, colour, and artistic intention. [31] The notion of a film as not containing one medium but several, can be interpreted in any number of ways, with some defining medium as an artist's intention and photography, others by audio editing, narrative, and artistic intention. Carroll takes issue with the presumptions held by medium essentialism, that each artform holds a unique medium, that that medium determines an arform's essence, and that an artform's content is determined by that medium. [32] Carroll argues that theorists must "forget the medium" [33] to understand the aesthetic possibilities that film contains, and criticises the essentialist arguments of works such as Siegfried Kracauer's 'Theory of Film', which avoided an exploration of the essence of film, yet still was preoccupied with a film-specific aesthetic as a result of the film medium, and nothing else. [34]

Similarly, Robert Sinnerbrink within 'New Philosophies of Film: Thinking Images' argues that a film contains a multitude of elements, whilst medium essentialism requires a single, prescriptive and rigid one. [7] Drawing from Cinema 1: The Movement Image, which was the first published consolidation of film theory, [35] Sinnerbrink proposes that each film's "movement-image" [36] or how a figure is created through the continuity of their movement, is that which defines it, in combination with a number of other elements. [7] This position, therefore, denounces the idea that an artform's essence is determined by one specific medium. Citing the example of Derek Jarman's Blue (1993), Sinnerbrink argues that the film's engaging voiceover narration, effective use of colour, exciting background music and plot cannot be distilled into a single 'relevant medium'. [37]

Jacques Rancière is also a critic of medium essentialism, proposing that no film has an essence particular to its medium, and that any essence or single medium cannot be determined by any film in cinematic history. [38] Reiterating the unsolvable conflict between 'visual spectacle' and 'narrative content' faced by critics when attempting to distill film into a single essential medium, [38] Rancière states that 'essentialising' the film medium often comes at the price of being unable to see the film as a whole, as a 'corpus'. [38]

Related Research Articles

Film theory is a set of scholarly approaches within the academic discipline of film or cinema studies that began in the 1920s by questioning the formal essential attributes of motion pictures; and that now provides conceptual frameworks for understanding film's relationship to reality, the other arts, individual viewers, and society at large. Film theory is not to be confused with general film criticism, or film history, though these three disciplines interrelate.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Ontology</span> Philosophical study of being and existence

In metaphysics, ontology is the philosophical study of being. It investigates what types of entities exist, how they are grouped into categories, and how they are related to one another on the most fundamental level. Ontologists often try to determine what the categories or highest kinds are and how they form a system of categories that encompasses the classification of all entities. Commonly proposed categories include substances, properties, relations, states of affairs, and events. These categories are characterized by fundamental ontological concepts, including particularity and universality, abstractness and concreteness, or possibility and necessity. Of special interest is the concept of ontological dependence, which determines whether the entities of a category exist on the most fundamental level. Disagreements within ontology are often about whether entities belonging to a certain category exist and, if so, how they are related to other entities.

<i>Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus</i> 1921 philosophical work by Ludwig Wittgenstein

The Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus is the only book-length philosophical work by the Austrian philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein that was published during his lifetime. The project had a broad goal: to identify the relationship between language and reality, and to define the limits of science. Wittgenstein wrote the notes for the Tractatus while he was a soldier during World War I and completed it during a military leave in the summer of 1918. It was originally published in German in 1921 as Logisch-Philosophische Abhandlung. In 1922 it was published together with an English translation and a Latin title, which was suggested by G. E. Moore as homage to Baruch Spinoza's Tractatus Theologico-Politicus (1670).

Essentialism is the view that objects have a set of attributes that are necessary to their identity. In early Western thought, Plato's idealism held that all things have such an "essence"—an "idea" or "form". In Categories, Aristotle similarly proposed that all objects have a substance that, as George Lakoff put it, "make the thing what it is, and without which it would be not that kind of thing". The contrary view—non-essentialism—denies the need to posit such an "essence".

Nothing, no-thing, or no thing, is the complete absence of anything as the opposite of something and an antithesis of everything. The concept of nothing has been a matter of philosophical debate since at least the 5th century BC. Early Greek philosophers argued that it was impossible for nothing to exist. The atomists allowed nothing but only in the spaces between the invisibly small atoms. For them, all space was filled with atoms. Aristotle took the view that there exists matter and there exists space, a receptacle into which matter objects can be placed. This became the paradigm for classical scientists of the modern age like Newton. Nevertheless, some philosophers, like Descartes, continued to argue against the existence of empty space until the scientific discovery of a physical vacuum.

Serene Velocity is a 1970 American experimental short film directed by Ernie Gehr. Gehr filmed it in the basement hallway of a Binghamton University academic building, using a static camera position and changing only the focal length of the camera. It is recognized as a key work of structural filmmaking and has been inducted into the U.S. National Film Registry.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Arthur Danto</span> American art critic and philosopher (1924–2013)

Arthur Coleman Danto was an American art critic, philosopher, and professor at Columbia University. He was best known for having been a long-time art critic for The Nation and for his work in philosophical aesthetics and philosophy of history, though he contributed significantly to a number of fields, including the philosophy of action. His interests included thought, feeling, philosophy of art, theories of representation, philosophical psychology, Hegel's aesthetics, and the philosophers Friedrich Nietzsche and Jean-Paul Sartre.

This is an alphabetical index of articles about aesthetics.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">David Bordwell</span> American film scholar (1947–2024)

David Jay Bordwell was an American film theorist and film historian. After receiving his PhD from the University of Iowa in 1973, he wrote more than fifteen volumes on the subject of cinema including Narration in the Fiction Film (1985), Ozu and the Poetics of Cinema (1988), Making Meaning (1989), and On the History of Film Style (1997).

Espen Hammer is Professor of Philosophy at Temple University. Focusing on modern European thought from Kant and Hegel to Adorno and Heidegger, Hammer’s research includes critical theory, Wittgenstein and ordinary language philosophy, phenomenology, German idealism, social and political theory, and aesthetics. He has also written widely on the philosophy of literature and taken a special interest in the question of temporality.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Noël Carroll</span> American philosopher

Noël Carroll is an American philosopher considered to be one of the leading figures in contemporary philosophy of art. Although Carroll is best known for his work in the philosophy of film, he has also published journalism, works on philosophy of art generally, theory of media, and also philosophy of history. As of 2012, he is a distinguished professor of philosophy at the CUNY Graduate Center.

Linguistic film theory is a form of film theory that studies the aesthetics of films by investigating the concepts and practices that comprise the experience and interpretation of movies.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Film</span> Visual art consisting of moving images

A film – also called a movie, motion picture, moving picture, picture, photoplay or (slang) flick – is a work of visual art that simulates experiences and otherwise communicates ideas, stories, perceptions, feelings, beauty, or atmosphere through the use of moving images. These images are generally accompanied by sound and, more rarely, other sensory stimulations. The word "cinema", short for cinematography, is often used to refer to filmmaking and the film industry, and the art form that is the result of it. Films can vary in genre, style, length and format, and they are typically produced for entertainment, education, cultural expression, or commercialpurposes. They are usually shown in theaters, on television, or via streaming platforms.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Susanne Langer</span> American philosopher, known for theories on the influences of art on the mind

Susanne Katherina Langer was an American philosopher, writer, and educator known for her theories on the influences of art on the mind. She was one of the earliest American women to achieve an academic career in philosophy and the first woman to be professionally recognized as an American philosopher. Langer is best remembered for her 1942 book Philosophy in a New Key which was followed by a sequel Feeling and Form: A Theory of Art in 1953. In 1960, Langer was elected a Fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences.

The philosophy of film is a branch of aesthetics within the discipline of philosophy that seeks to understand the most basic questions about film. Philosophy of film has significant overlap with film theory, a branch of film studies.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Trick film</span> Short silent films designed to feature innovative special effects

In the early history of cinema, trick films were short silent films designed to feature innovative special effects.

A theory of art is intended to contrast with a definition of art. Traditionally, definitions are composed of necessary and sufficient conditions and a single counterexample overthrows such a definition. Theorizing about art, on the other hand, is analogous to a theory of a natural phenomenon like gravity. In fact, the intent behind a theory of art is to treat art as a natural phenomenon that should be investigated like any other. The question of whether one can speak of a theory of art without employing a concept of art is also discussed below.

Cynthia A. Freeland is an American philosopher of art. She has published three monographs, over two dozen articles, and edited several books. She is emeritus professor of philosophy at the University of Houston. She was the president of the American Society of Aesthetics until 2017. She has been awarded a fellowship from the National Endowment for the Humanities in 2003 for a research project on Fakes and Forgeries. Her book But is it Art? (2001) has been translated into fourteen languages and was republished as part of the Oxford Very Short Introductions series. She talked about her book Portraits&Persons with Nigel Warburton on the Philosophy Bites podcast. She was interviewed by Hans Maes for the book Conversations on Art and Aesthetics (2017) which includes a photograph of her by American photographer Steve Pyke.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">David Macarthur</span> Australian philosopher

David Macarthur is an Australian philosopher and Professor of Philosophy at the University of Sydney who works primarily on skepticism, metaphysical quietism, pragmatism, liberal naturalism and philosophy of art. He has taken up these and other themes in articles on the philosophy of Stanley Cavell, Hilary Putnam, Richard Rorty and Ludwig Wittgenstein.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">William Rothman</span> American film theorist and critic

William Rothman is an American film theorist and critic. Since receiving his Ph.D. in philosophy from Harvard University in 1974, he has authored numerous books, including Hitchcock: The Murderous Gaze (1982), The “I” of the Camera: Essays in Film Criticism, History and Aesthetic (1988), and Tuitions and Intuitions: Essays at the Intersection of Film Criticism and Philosophy (2019). He was "part of a modern wave of thinkers to apply questions of philosophy to the medium of movies" during the 1980s, and his work contributed to the emergence of the sub-discipline that has come to be known as “film-philosophy.” Rothman has also written on aspects of film theory and on the writings of Stanley Cavell, an American philosopher who made film a major focus of his work. He is currently Professor of Cinematic Arts in the School of Communication at the University of Miami.

References

  1. 1 2 3 4 Choi, Jinhee; Carroll, Noel (2005). Philosophy of Film and Motion Pictures: An Anthology. Oxford, United Kingdom: John Wiley and Sons Ltd. pp. 113–115. ISBN   1405120274.
  2. Schreyach, Michael (Spring 2015). "Re-created Flatness: Hans Hofmann's Concept of the Picture Plane as a Medium of Expression". The Journal of Aesthetic Education. 49 (1): 57. doi:10.5406/jaesteduc.49.1.0044. S2CID   13600078.
  3. Choi, Jinhee; Carroll, Noel (2005). Philosophy of Film and Motion Pictures: An Anthology. Oxford, United Kingdom: John Wiley and Sons Ltd. p. 59. ISBN   1405120274.
  4. Bordwell, David; Thompson, Kristin (2003). Film History: An Introduction . New York, USA: McGraw-Hill Company Inc. pp.  13. ISBN   9780070384293.
  5. Crawford, Donald (July 1969). "Reviewed Work: What Is Cinema? by André Bazin, Hugh Gray". Journal of Aesthetic Education. 3 (3): 159–161. doi:10.2307/3331711. JSTOR   3331711.
  6. 1 2 3 Livingston, Paisley; Plantinga, Carl (2012). The Routledge Companion to Philosophy and Film. Taylor & Francis. p. 205. ISBN   9781281838032. OCLC   830038431.
  7. 1 2 3 4 Sinnerbrink, Robert (2011). New Philosophies of Film : Thinking Images . Continuum. pp.  23–24. ISBN   9781441122575. OCLC   1043047181.
  8. Choi, Jinhee; Carroll, Noel (2005). Philosophy of Film and Motion Pictures: An Anthology. Oxford, United Kingdom: John Wiley and Sons Ltd. ISBN   1405120274.
  9. 1 2 Cartwright, Richard L. (1968). "Some Remarks on Essentialism". The Journal of Philosophy. 65 (20): 615–626. doi:10.2307/2024315. JSTOR   2024315.
  10. Choi, Jinhee; Carroll, Noel (2005). Philosophy of Film and Motion Pictures: An Anthology. Oxford, United Kingdom: John Wiley and Sons Ltd. p. 114. ISBN   1405120274.
  11. 1 2 Langer, Susanne K. (1979). Reflections on art: a source book of writings by artists, critics, and philosophers. Arno Press. p. 62. ISBN   0405106114. OCLC   470851789.
  12. 1 2 Langer, Susanne (1977). Feeling and Form. Pearson. pp. 4–14. ISBN   0023675004.
  13. Choi, Jinhee; Carroll, Noel (2005). Philosophy of Film and Motion Pictures: An Anthology. Oxford, United Kingdom: John Wiley and Sons Ltd. p. 59. ISBN   1405120274.
  14. Choi, Jinhee; Carroll, Noel (2005). Philosophy of Film and Motion Pictures: An Anthology. Oxford, United Kingdom: John Wiley and Sons Ltd. pp. 61. ISBN   1405120274.
  15. Choi, Jinhee; Carroll, Noel (2005). Philosophy of Film and Motion Pictures: An Anthology. Oxford, United Kingdom: John Wiley and Sons Ltd. pp. 8. ISBN   1405120274.
  16. Sinnerbrink, Robert (2018). New Philosophies of Film : Thinking Images . Continuum. pp.  41. ISBN   9781441122575. OCLC   1043047181.
  17. 1 2 Jarvie, Ian (August 1995). "Sir Karl Popper (1902–94): Essentialism And Historicism In Film Methodology". Historical Journal of Film, Radio and Television. 15 (2): 301–305. doi:10.1080/01439689500260181.
  18. Choi, Jinhee; Carroll, Noel (2005). Philosophy of Film and Motion Pictures: An Anthology. Oxford, United Kingdom: John Wiley and Sons Ltd. pp. 8–16. ISBN   1405120274.
  19. 1 2 Cooper, Sarah (1971). The Soul of Film Theory. pp. 57–58. ISBN   9780230365131. OCLC   825047285.
  20. Koch, Gertrud; Hansen, Miriam (1987). "Bela Balazs: The Physiognomy of Things". New German Critique (40): 167–177. doi:10.2307/488137. ISSN   0094-033X. JSTOR   488137.
  21. 1 2 3 4 Dalle Vacche, Angela (2012). Film, Art, New Media: Museum Without Walls?. New York, USA: Springer. p. 154. ISBN   978-1137026132.
  22. Dalle Vacche, Angela (2012). Film, Art, New Media: Museum Without Walls?. New York, USA: Springer. pp. 155–156. ISBN   978-1137026132.
  23. 1 2 MICHELSON, Annette, and Kevin O’Brien (1985). Kino-eye: The Writings of Dziga Vertov. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
  24. 1 2 3 Walley, Jonathan (2003). "The Material of Film and the Idea of Cinema: Contrasting Practices in Sixties and Seventies Avant-Garde Film". October. 103: 15–30. doi:10.1162/016228703762874197. ISSN   0162-2870. S2CID   57563100.
  25. 1 2 3 Cavell, Stanley (1971). The World Viewed: Reflections on the Ontology of Film . Harvard University, USA: Harvard University Press. pp.  40–41. ISBN   9780674961968.
  26. Cavell, Stanley (1971). The World Viewed: Reflections on the Ontology of Film . Harvard University, USA: Harvard University Press. pp.  166. ISBN   9780674961968.
  27. Sinnerbrink, Robert (2011). New Philosophies of Film : Thinking Images . Continuum. pp.  28. ISBN   9781441122575. OCLC   1043047181.
  28. Nannicelli, Ted (2016). Appreciating the Art of Television: a Philosophical Perspective. Taylor & Francis. p. 53. ISBN   9781315732633. OCLC   1009105087.
  29. Schreyach, Michael (Spring 2015). "Re-created Flatness: Hans Hofmann's Concept of the Picture Plane as a Medium of Expression". The Journal of Aesthetic Education. 49 (1): 58. doi:10.5406/jaesteduc.49.1.0044. S2CID   13600078.
  30. 1 2 Sinnerbrink, Robert (2011). New Philosophies of Film: Thinking Images. Bloomsbury, UK: Bloomsbury Publishing. p. 21. ISBN   978-1441146199.
  31. Choi, Jinhee; Carroll, Noel (2005). Philosophy of Film and Motion Pictures: An Anthology. Oxford, United Kingdom: John Wiley and Sons Ltd. pp. 68–74. ISBN   1405120274.
  32. Sinnerbrink, Robert (2011). New Philosophies of Film : Thinking Images. Continuum. pp. 21. ISBN   9781441122575. OCLC   1043047181.
  33. Sankowski, Edward (Spring 2006). "Film Studies, the Moving Image, and Noël Carroll". Journal of Aesthetic Education. 40 (1): 104–110. doi:10.1353/jae.2006.0009. S2CID   191491971 via JSTOR.
  34. Schlüpmann, Heide; Y. Levin, Thomas (Winter 1987). "Phenomenology of Film: On Siegfried Kracauer's Writings of the 1920s". New German Critique. 40: 98–99 via JSTOR.
  35. Phil Powrie, Keith Reader (2002). French Cinema: A Student's Guide, Oxford University Press(US), p77. ISBN   0-340-76004-4.
  36. Chris Gehman, Steve Reinke (2005). The Sharpest Point: animation at the end of cinema, YYZ Books, p12. ISBN   0-920397-32-8.
  37. Sinnerbrink, Robert (2018). New Philosophies of Film : Thinking Images. Continuum. p. 22-23. ISBN   9781441122575. OCLC   1043047181.
  38. 1 2 3 Sinnerbrink, Robert (2018). New Philosophies of Film : Thinking Images. Continuum. p. 100-102. ISBN   9781441122575. OCLC   1043047181.