Gleason's theorem

Last updated

In mathematical physics, Gleason's theorem shows that the rule one uses to calculate probabilities in quantum physics, the Born rule, can be derived from the usual mathematical representation of measurements in quantum physics together with the assumption of non-contextuality. Andrew M. Gleason first proved the theorem in 1957, [1] answering a question posed by George W. Mackey, an accomplishment that was historically significant for the role it played in showing that wide classes of hidden-variable theories are inconsistent with quantum physics. Multiple variations have been proven in the years since. Gleason's theorem is of particular importance for the field of quantum logic and its attempt to find a minimal set of mathematical axioms for quantum theory.

Contents

Statement of the theorem

Conceptual background

In quantum mechanics, each physical system is associated with a Hilbert space. For the purposes of this overview, the Hilbert space is assumed to be finite-dimensional. In the approach codified by John von Neumann, a measurement upon a physical system is represented by a self-adjoint operator on that Hilbert space sometimes termed an "observable". The eigenvectors of such an operator form an orthonormal basis for the Hilbert space, and each possible outcome of that measurement corresponds to one of the vectors comprising the basis. A density operator is a positive-semidefinite operator on the Hilbert space whose trace is equal to 1. In the language of von Weizsäcker, a density operator is a "catalogue of probabilities": for each measurement that can be defined, the probability distribution over the outcomes of that measurement can be computed from the density operator. [2] The procedure for doing so is the Born rule, which states that where is the density operator, and is the projection operator onto the basis vector corresponding to the measurement outcome .

The Born rule associates a probability with each unit vector in the Hilbert space, in such a way that these probabilities sum to 1 for any set of unit vectors comprising an orthonormal basis. Moreover, the probability associated with a unit vector is a function of the density operator and the unit vector, and not of additional information like a choice of basis for that vector to be embedded in. Gleason's theorem establishes the converse: all assignments of probabilities to unit vectors (or, equivalently, to the operators that project onto them) that satisfy these conditions take the form of applying the Born rule to some density operator. Gleason's theorem holds if the dimension of the Hilbert space is 3 or greater; counterexamples exist for dimension 2.

Deriving the state space and the Born rule

The probability of any outcome of a measurement upon a quantum system must be a real number between 0 and 1 inclusive, and in order to be consistent, for any individual measurement the probabilities of the different possible outcomes must add up to 1. Gleason's theorem shows that any function that assigns probabilities to measurement outcomes, as identified by projection operators, must be expressible in terms of a density operator and the Born rule. This gives not only the rule for calculating probabilities, but also determines the set of possible quantum states.

Let be a function from projection operators to the unit interval with the property that, if a set of projection operators sum to the identity matrix (that is, if they correspond to an orthonormal basis), then

Such a function expresses an assignment of probability values to the outcomes of measurements, an assignment that is "noncontextual" in the sense that the probability for an outcome does not depend upon which measurement that outcome is embedded within, but only upon the mathematical representation of that specific outcome, i.e., its projection operator. [3] [4] :§1.3 [5] :§2.1 [6] Gleason's theorem states that for any such function , there exists a positive-semidefinite operator with unit trace such that

Both the Born rule and the fact that "catalogues of probability" are positive-semidefinite operators of unit trace follow from the assumptions that measurements are represented by orthonormal bases, and that probability assignments are "noncontextual". In order for Gleason's theorem to be applicable, the space on which measurements are defined must be a real or complex Hilbert space, or a quaternionic module. [a] (Gleason's argument is inapplicable if, for example, one tries to construct an analogue of quantum mechanics using p-adic numbers.)

History and outline of Gleason's proof

Gleason in 1959 GleasonAndrewMattei Berlin1959.jpg
Gleason in 1959

In 1932, John von Neumann also managed to derive the Born rule in his textbook Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics . However, the assumptions on which von Neumann built his no hidden variables proof were rather strong and eventually regarded to not be well-motivated. [14] Specifically, von Neumann assumed that the probability function must be linear on all observables, commuting or non-commuting. His proof was derided by John Bell as "not merely false but foolish!". [15] [16] Gleason, on the other hand, did not assume linearity, but merely additivity for commuting projectors together with noncontextuality, assumptions seen as better motivated and more physically meaningful. [16] [17]

By the late 1940s, George Mackey had grown interested in the mathematical foundations of quantum physics, wondering in particular whether the Born rule was the only possible rule for calculating probabilities in a theory that represented measurements as orthonormal bases on a Hilbert space. [18] [19] Mackey discussed this problem with Irving Segal at the University of Chicago, who in turn raised it with Richard Kadison, then a graduate student. Kadison showed that for 2-dimensional Hilbert spaces there exists a probability measure that does not correspond to quantum states and the Born rule. Gleason's result implies that this only happens in dimension 2. [19]

Gleason's original proof proceeds in three stages. [20] :§2 In Gleason's terminology, a frame function is a real-valued function on the unit sphere of a Hilbert space such that whenever the vectors comprise an orthonormal basis. A noncontextual probability assignment as defined in the previous section is equivalent to a frame function. [b] Any such measure that can be written in the standard way, that is, by applying the Born rule to a quantum state, is termed a regular frame function. Gleason derives a sequence of lemmas concerning when a frame function is necessarily regular, culminating in the final theorem. First, he establishes that every continuous frame function on the Hilbert space is regular. This step makes use of the theory of spherical harmonics. Then, he proves that frame functions on have to be continuous, which establishes the theorem for the special case of . This step is regarded as the most difficult of the proof. [21] [22] Finally, he shows that the general problem can be reduced to this special case. Gleason credits one lemma used in this last stage of the proof to his doctoral student Richard Palais. [1] :fn 3

Robin Lyth Hudson described Gleason's theorem as "celebrated and notoriously difficult". [23] Cooke, Keane and Moran later produced a proof that is longer than Gleason's but requires fewer prerequisites. [21]

Implications

Gleason's theorem highlights a number of fundamental issues in quantum measurement theory. As Fuchs argues, the theorem "is an extremely powerful result", because "it indicates the extent to which the Born probability rule and even the state-space structure of density operators are dependent upon the theory's other postulates". In consequence, quantum theory is "a tighter package than one might have first thought". [24] :94–95 Various approaches to rederiving the quantum formalism from alternative axioms have, accordingly, employed Gleason's theorem as a key step, bridging the gap between the structure of Hilbert space and the Born rule. [c]

Hidden variables

Moreover, the theorem is historically significant for the role it played in ruling out the possibility of certain classes of hidden variables in quantum mechanics. A hidden-variable theory that is deterministic implies that the probability of a given outcome is always either 0 or 1. For example, a Stern–Gerlach measurement on a spin-1 atom will report that the atom's angular momentum along the chosen axis is one of three possible values, which can be designated , and . In a deterministic hidden-variable theory, there exists an underlying physical property that fixes the result found in the measurement. Conditional on the value of the underlying physical property, any given outcome (for example, a result of ) must be either impossible or guaranteed. But Gleason's theorem implies that there can be no such deterministic probability measure. The mapping is continuous on the unit sphere of the Hilbert space for any density operator . Since this unit sphere is connected, no continuous probability measure on it can be deterministic. [26] :§1.3 Gleason's theorem therefore suggests that quantum theory represents a deep and fundamental departure from the classical intuition that uncertainty is due to ignorance about hidden degrees of freedom. [27] More specifically, Gleason's theorem rules out hidden-variable models that are "noncontextual". Any hidden-variable model for quantum mechanics must, in order to avoid the implications of Gleason's theorem, involve hidden variables that are not properties belonging to the measured system alone but also dependent upon the external context in which the measurement is made. This type of dependence is often seen as contrived or undesirable; in some settings, it is inconsistent with special relativity. [27] [28]

In the Bloch sphere representation of a qubit, each point on the unit sphere stands for a pure state. All other density matrices correspond to points in the interior. Bloch sphere.svg
In the Bloch sphere representation of a qubit, each point on the unit sphere stands for a pure state. All other density matrices correspond to points in the interior.

To construct a counterexample for 2-dimensional Hilbert space, known as a qubit, let the hidden variable be a unit vector in 3-dimensional Euclidean space. Using the Bloch sphere, each possible measurement on a qubit can be represented as a pair of antipodal points on the unit sphere. Defining the probability of a measurement outcome to be 1 if the point representing that outcome lies in the same hemisphere as and 0 otherwise yields an assignment of probabilities to measurement outcomes that obeys Gleason's assumptions. However, this probability assignment does not correspond to any valid density operator. By introducing a probability distribution over the possible values of , a hidden-variable model for a qubit that reproduces the predictions of quantum theory can be constructed. [27] [29]

Gleason's theorem motivated later work by John Bell, Ernst Specker and Simon Kochen that led to the result often called the Kochen–Specker theorem, which likewise shows that noncontextual hidden-variable models are incompatible with quantum mechanics. As noted above, Gleason's theorem shows that there is no probability measure over the rays of a Hilbert space that only takes the values 0 and 1 (as long as the dimension of that space exceeds 2). The Kochen–Specker theorem refines this statement by constructing a specific finite subset of rays on which no such probability measure can be defined. [27] [30] The fact that such a finite subset of rays must exist follows from Gleason's theorem by way of a logical compactness argument, but this method does not construct the desired set explicitly. [20] :§1 In the related no-hidden-variables result known as Bell's theorem, the assumption that the hidden-variable theory is noncontextual instead is replaced by the assumption that it is local. The same sets of rays used in Kochen–Specker constructions can also be employed to derive Bell-type proofs. [27] [31] [32]

Pitowsky uses Gleason's theorem to argue that quantum mechanics represents a new theory of probability, one in which the structure of the space of possible events is modified from the classical, Boolean algebra thereof. He regards this as analogous to the way that special relativity modifies the kinematics of Newtonian mechanics. [4] [5]

The Gleason and Kochen–Specker theorems have been cited in support of various philosophies, including perspectivism, constructive empiricism and agential realism. [33] [34] [35]

Quantum logic

Gleason's theorem finds application in quantum logic, which makes heavy use of lattice theory. Quantum logic treats the outcome of a quantum measurement as a logical proposition and studies the relationships and structures formed by these logical propositions. They are organized into a lattice, in which the distributive law, valid in classical logic, is weakened, to reflect the fact that in quantum physics, not all pairs of quantities can be measured simultaneously. [36] The representation theorem in quantum logic shows that such a lattice is isomorphic to the lattice of subspaces of a vector space with a scalar product. [5] :§2 Using Solèr's theorem, the (skew) field K over which the vector space is defined can be proven, with additional hypotheses, to be either the real numbers, complex numbers, or the quaternions, as is needed for Gleason's theorem to hold. [12] :§3 [37] [38]

By invoking Gleason's theorem, the form of a probability function on lattice elements can be restricted. Assuming that the mapping from lattice elements to probabilities is noncontextual, Gleason's theorem establishes that it must be expressible with the Born rule.

Generalizations

Gleason originally proved the theorem assuming that the measurements applied to the system are of the von Neumann type, i.e., that each possible measurement corresponds to an orthonormal basis of the Hilbert space. Later, Busch [39] and independently Caves et al. [24] :116 [40] proved an analogous result for a more general class of measurements, known as positive-operator-valued measures (POVMs). The set of all POVMs includes the set of von Neumann measurements, and so the assumptions of this theorem are significantly stronger than Gleason's. This made the proof of this result simpler than Gleason's, and the conclusions stronger. Unlike the original theorem of Gleason, the generalized version using POVMs also applies to the case of a single qubit. [41] [42] Assuming noncontextuality for POVMs is, however, controversial, as POVMs are not fundamental, and some authors defend that noncontextuality should be assumed only for the underlying von Neumann measurements. [43] Gleason's theorem, in its original version, does not hold if the Hilbert space is defined over the rational numbers, i.e., if the components of vectors in the Hilbert space are restricted to be rational numbers, or complex numbers with rational parts. However, when the set of allowed measurements is the set of all POVMs, the theorem holds. [40] :§3.D

The original proof by Gleason was not constructive: one of the ideas on which it depends is the fact that every continuous function defined on a compact space attains its minimum. Because one cannot in all cases explicitly show where the minimum occurs, a proof that relies upon this principle will not be a constructive proof. However, the theorem can be reformulated in such a way that a constructive proof can be found. [20] [44]

Gleason's theorem can be extended to some cases where the observables of the theory form a von Neumann algebra. Specifically, an analogue of Gleason's result can be shown to hold if the algebra of observables has no direct summand that is representable as the algebra of 2×2 matrices over a commutative von Neumann algebra (i.e., no direct summand of type I2). In essence, the only barrier to proving the theorem is the fact that Gleason's original result does not hold when the Hilbert space is that of a qubit. [45]

Notes

  1. For additional discussion on this point, see Piron, [7] :§6 Drisch, [8] Horwitz and Biedenharn, [9] Razon and Horwitz, [10] Varadarajan, [11] :83 Cassinelli and Lahti, [12] :§2 and Moretti and Oppio. [13]
  2. Gleason allows for the possibility that a frame function is normalized to a constant other than 1, but focusing on the case of "unit weight" as done here does not result in any loss of generality.
  3. This is discussed by Barnum et al., [3] Cassinelli and Lahti, [12] :§2 Stairs, [25] and Wilce. [26] :§1.4

Related Research Articles

The mathematical formulations of quantum mechanics are those mathematical formalisms that permit a rigorous description of quantum mechanics. This mathematical formalism uses mainly a part of functional analysis, especially Hilbert spaces, which are a kind of linear space. Such are distinguished from mathematical formalisms for physics theories developed prior to the early 1900s by the use of abstract mathematical structures, such as infinite-dimensional Hilbert spaces, and operators on these spaces. In brief, values of physical observables such as energy and momentum were no longer considered as values of functions on phase space, but as eigenvalues; more precisely as spectral values of linear operators in Hilbert space.

In physics, the no-cloning theorem states that it is impossible to create an independent and identical copy of an arbitrary unknown quantum state, a statement which has profound implications in the field of quantum computing among others. The theorem is an evolution of the 1970 no-go theorem authored by James Park, in which he demonstrates that a non-disturbing measurement scheme which is both simple and perfect cannot exist. The aforementioned theorems do not preclude the state of one system becoming entangled with the state of another as cloning specifically refers to the creation of a separable state with identical factors. For example, one might use the controlled NOT gate and the Walsh–Hadamard gate to entangle two qubits without violating the no-cloning theorem as no well-defined state may be defined in terms of a subsystem of an entangled state. The no-cloning theorem concerns only pure states whereas the generalized statement regarding mixed states is known as the no-broadcast theorem.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Quantum entanglement</span> Correlation between quantum systems

Quantum entanglement is the phenomenon of a group of particles being generated, interacting, or sharing spatial proximity in such a way that the quantum state of each particle of the group cannot be described independently of the state of the others, including when the particles are separated by a large distance. The topic of quantum entanglement is at the heart of the disparity between classical and quantum physics: entanglement is a primary feature of quantum mechanics not present in classical mechanics.

Bell's theorem is a term encompassing a number of closely related results in physics, all of which determine that quantum mechanics is incompatible with local hidden-variable theories, given some basic assumptions about the nature of measurement. "Local" here refers to the principle of locality, the idea that a particle can only be influenced by its immediate surroundings, and that interactions mediated by physical fields cannot propagate faster than the speed of light. "Hidden variables" are supposed properties of quantum particles that are not included in quantum theory but nevertheless affect the outcome of experiments. In the words of physicist John Stewart Bell, for whom this family of results is named, "If [a hidden-variable theory] is local it will not agree with quantum mechanics, and if it agrees with quantum mechanics it will not be local."

In quantum mechanics, a density matrix is a matrix that describes an ensemble of physical systems as quantum states. It allows for the calculation of the probabilities of the outcomes of any measurements performed upon the systems of the ensemble using the Born rule. It is a generalization of the more usual state vectors or wavefunctions: while those can only represent pure states, density matrices can also represent mixed ensembles. Mixed ensembles arise in quantum mechanics in two different situations:

  1. when the preparation of the systems lead to numerous pure states in the ensemble, and thus one must deal with the statistics of possible preparations, and
  2. when one wants to describe a physical system that is entangled with another, without describing their combined state; this case is typical for a system interacting with some environment. In this case, the density matrix of an entangled system differs from that of an ensemble of pure states that, combined, would give the same statistical results upon measurement.

In quantum mechanics, wave function collapse, also called reduction of the state vector, occurs when a wave function—initially in a superposition of several eigenstates—reduces to a single eigenstate due to interaction with the external world. This interaction is called an observation and is the essence of a measurement in quantum mechanics, which connects the wave function with classical observables such as position and momentum. Collapse is one of the two processes by which quantum systems evolve in time; the other is the continuous evolution governed by the Schrödinger equation.

Quantum indeterminacy is the apparent necessary incompleteness in the description of a physical system, that has become one of the characteristics of the standard description of quantum physics. Prior to quantum physics, it was thought that

In physics, the principle of locality states that an object is influenced directly only by its immediate surroundings. A theory that includes the principle of locality is said to be a "local theory". This is an alternative to the concept of instantaneous, or "non-local" action at a distance. Locality evolved out of the field theories of classical physics. The idea is that for a cause at one point to have an effect at another point, something in the space between those points must mediate the action. To exert an influence, something, such as a wave or particle, must travel through the space between the two points, carrying the influence.

In quantum physics, a measurement is the testing or manipulation of a physical system to yield a numerical result. A fundamental feature of quantum theory is that the predictions it makes are probabilistic. The procedure for finding a probability involves combining a quantum state, which mathematically describes a quantum system, with a mathematical representation of the measurement to be performed on that system. The formula for this calculation is known as the Born rule. For example, a quantum particle like an electron can be described by a quantum state that associates to each point in space a complex number called a probability amplitude. Applying the Born rule to these amplitudes gives the probabilities that the electron will be found in one region or another when an experiment is performed to locate it. This is the best the theory can do; it cannot say for certain where the electron will be found. The same quantum state can also be used to make a prediction of how the electron will be moving, if an experiment is performed to measure its momentum instead of its position. The uncertainty principle implies that, whatever the quantum state, the range of predictions for the electron's position and the range of predictions for its momentum cannot both be narrow. Some quantum states imply a near-certain prediction of the result of a position measurement, but the result of a momentum measurement will be highly unpredictable, and vice versa. Furthermore, the fact that nature violates the statistical conditions known as Bell inequalities indicates that the unpredictability of quantum measurement results cannot be explained away as due to ignorance about "local hidden variables" within quantum systems.

In the mathematical study of logic and the physical analysis of quantum foundations, quantum logic is a set of rules for manip­ulation of propositions inspired by the structure of quantum theory. The formal system takes as its starting point an obs­ervation of Garrett Birkhoff and John von Neumann, that the structure of experimental tests in classical mechanics forms a Boolean algebra, but the structure of experimental tests in quantum mechanics forms a much more complicated structure.

In the interpretation of quantum mechanics, a local hidden-variable theory is a hidden-variable theory that satisfies the principle of locality. These models attempt to account for the probabilistic features of quantum mechanics via the mechanism of underlying, but inaccessible variables, with the additional requirement that distant events be statistically independent.

In quantum mechanics, the Kochen–Specker (KS) theorem, also known as the Bell–KS theorem, is a "no-go" theorem proved by John S. Bell in 1966 and by Simon B. Kochen and Ernst Specker in 1967. It places certain constraints on the permissible types of hidden-variable theories, which try to explain the predictions of quantum mechanics in a context-independent way. The version of the theorem proved by Kochen and Specker also gave an explicit example for this constraint in terms of a finite number of state vectors.

The Born rule is a postulate of quantum mechanics that gives the probability that a measurement of a quantum system will yield a given result. In one commonly used application, it states that the probability density for finding a particle at a given position is proportional to the square of the amplitude of the system's wavefunction at that position. It was formulated and published by German physicist Max Born in July, 1926.

In theoretical physics, quantum nonlocality refers to the phenomenon by which the measurement statistics of a multipartite quantum system do not allow an interpretation with local realism. Quantum nonlocality has been experimentally verified under a variety of physical assumptions.

The Koopman–von Neumann (KvN) theory is a description of classical mechanics as an operatorial theory similar to quantum mechanics, based on a Hilbert space of complex, square-integrable wavefunctions. As its name suggests, the KvN theory is loosely related to work by Bernard Koopman and John von Neumann in 1931 and 1932, respectively. As explained in this entry, however, the historical origins of the theory and its name are complicated.

The Pusey–Barrett–Rudolph (PBR) theorem is a no-go theorem in quantum foundations due to Matthew Pusey, Jonathan Barrett, and Terry Rudolph in 2012. It has particular significance for how one may interpret the nature of the quantum state.

Quantum contextuality is a feature of the phenomenology of quantum mechanics whereby measurements of quantum observables cannot simply be thought of as revealing pre-existing values. Any attempt to do so in a realistic hidden-variable theory leads to values that are dependent upon the choice of the other (compatible) observables which are simultaneously measured. More formally, the measurement result of a quantum observable is dependent upon which other commuting observables are within the same measurement set.

Quantum foundations is a discipline of science that seeks to understand the most counter-intuitive aspects of quantum theory, reformulate it and even propose new generalizations thereof. Contrary to other physical theories, such as general relativity, the defining axioms of quantum theory are quite ad hoc, with no obvious physical intuition. While they lead to the right experimental predictions, they do not come with a mental picture of the world where they fit.

A generalized probabilistic theory (GPT) is a general framework to describe the operational features of arbitrary physical theories. A GPT must specify what kind of physical systems one can find in the lab, as well as rules to compute the outcome statistics of any experiment involving labeled preparations, transformations and measurements. The framework of GPTs has been used to define hypothetical non-quantum physical theories which nonetheless possess quantum theory's most remarkable features, such as entanglement or teleportation. Notably, a small set of physically motivated axioms is enough to single out the GPT representation of quantum theory.

Quantum Theory: Concepts and Methods is a 1993 quantum physics textbook by Israeli physicist Asher Peres. Well-regarded among the physics community, it is known for unconventional choices of topics to include.

References

  1. 1 2 Gleason, Andrew M. (1957). "Measures on the closed subspaces of a Hilbert space". Indiana University Mathematics Journal . 6 (4): 885–893. doi: 10.1512/iumj.1957.6.56050 . MR   0096113.
  2. Drieschner, M.; Görnitz, Th.; von Weizsäcker, C. F. (1988-03-01). "Reconstruction of abstract quantum theory". International Journal of Theoretical Physics . 27 (3): 289–306. Bibcode:1988IJTP...27..289D. doi:10.1007/bf00668895. ISSN   0020-7748. S2CID   122866239.
  3. 1 2 Barnum, H.; Caves, C. M.; Finkelstein, J.; Fuchs, C. A.; Schack, R. (2000-05-08). "Quantum probability from decision theory?". Proceedings of the Royal Society of London A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences . 456 (1997): 1175–1182. arXiv: quant-ph/9907024 . Bibcode:2000RSPSA.456.1175B. CiteSeerX   10.1.1.769.8732 . doi:10.1098/rspa.2000.0557. ISSN   1364-5021. S2CID   11563591.
  4. 1 2 Pitowsky, Itamar (2003). "Betting on the outcomes of measurements: a Bayesian theory of quantum probability". Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics . 34 (3): 395–414. arXiv: quant-ph/0208121 . Bibcode:2003SHPMP..34..395P. doi:10.1016/S1355-2198(03)00035-2.
  5. 1 2 3 Pitowsky, Itamar (2006). "Quantum mechanics as a theory of probability". In Demopoulos, William; Pitowsky, Itamar (eds.). Physical Theory and its Interpretation: Essays in Honor of Jeffrey Bub. Springer. p. 213. arXiv: quant-ph/0510095 . Bibcode:2005quant.ph.10095P. ISBN   9781402048760. OCLC   917845122.
  6. Kunjwal, Ravi; Spekkens, Rob W. (2015-09-09). "From the Kochen–Specker theorem to noncontextuality inequalities without assuming determinism". Physical Review Letters . 115 (11): 110403. arXiv: 1506.04150 . Bibcode:2015PhRvL.115k0403K. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.115.110403. PMID   26406812. S2CID   10308680.
  7. Piron, C. (1972-10-01). "Survey of general quantum physics". Foundations of Physics . 2 (4): 287–314. Bibcode:1972FoPh....2..287P. doi:10.1007/bf00708413. ISSN   0015-9018. S2CID   123364715.
  8. Drisch, Thomas (1979-04-01). "Generalization of Gleason's theorem". International Journal of Theoretical Physics . 18 (4): 239–243. Bibcode:1979IJTP...18..239D. doi:10.1007/bf00671760. ISSN   0020-7748. S2CID   121825926.
  9. Horwitz, L. P.; Biedenharn, L. C. (1984). "Quaternion quantum mechanics: Second quantization and gauge fields". Annals of Physics . 157 (2): 432–488. Bibcode:1984AnPhy.157..432H. doi:10.1016/0003-4916(84)90068-x.
  10. Razon, Aharon; Horwitz, L. P. (1991-08-01). "Projection operators and states in the tensor product of quaternion Hilbert modules". Acta Applicandae Mathematicae . 24 (2): 179–194. doi:10.1007/bf00046891. ISSN   0167-8019. S2CID   119666741.
  11. Varadarajan, Veeravalli S. (2007). Geometry of Quantum Theory (2nd ed.). Springer Science+Business Media. ISBN   978-0-387-96124-8. OCLC   764647569.
  12. 1 2 3 Cassinelli, G.; Lahti, P. (2017-11-13). "Quantum mechanics: why complex Hilbert space?". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A . 375 (2106): 20160393. Bibcode:2017RSPTA.37560393C. doi: 10.1098/rsta.2016.0393 . ISSN   1364-503X. PMID   28971945.
  13. Moretti, Valter; Oppio, Marco (2018-10-16). "The Correct Formulation of Gleason's Theorem in Quaternionic Hilbert Spaces". Annales Henri Poincaré . 19 (11): 3321–3355. arXiv: 1803.06882 . Bibcode:2018AnHP...19.3321M. doi:10.1007/s00023-018-0729-8. S2CID   53630146.
  14. Bell, John (1966). "On the Problem of Hidden Variables in Quantum Mechanics". Reviews of Modern Physics . 38 (3): 447. Bibcode:1966RvMP...38..447B. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.38.447. OSTI   1444158.
  15. Bub, Jeffrey (2010). "Von Neumann's 'No Hidden Variables' Proof: A Re-Appraisal". Foundations of Physics . 40 (9–10): 1333–1340. arXiv: 1006.0499 . Bibcode:2010FoPh...40.1333B. doi:10.1007/s10701-010-9480-9. S2CID   118595119.
  16. 1 2 Mermin, N. David; Schack, Rüdiger (2018). "Homer nodded: von Neumann's surprising oversight". Foundations of Physics . 48 (9): 1007–1020. arXiv: 1805.10311 . Bibcode:2018FoPh...48.1007M. doi:10.1007/s10701-018-0197-5. S2CID   118951033.
  17. Peres, Asher (1992). "An experimental test for Gleason's theorem". Physics Letters A . 163 (4): 243–245. Bibcode:1992PhLA..163..243P. doi:10.1016/0375-9601(92)91005-C.
  18. Mackey, George W. (1957). "Quantum Mechanics and Hilbert Space". The American Mathematical Monthly . 64 (8P2): 45–57. doi:10.1080/00029890.1957.11989120. JSTOR   2308516.
  19. 1 2 Chernoff, Paul R. "Andy Gleason and Quantum Mechanics" (PDF). Notices of the AMS . 56 (10): 1253–1259.
  20. 1 2 3 Hrushovski, Ehud; Pitowsky, Itamar (2004-06-01). "Generalizations of Kochen and Specker's theorem and the effectiveness of Gleason's theorem". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics . 35 (2): 177–194. arXiv: quant-ph/0307139 . Bibcode:2004SHPMP..35..177H. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2003.10.002. S2CID   15265001.
  21. 1 2 Cooke, Roger; Keane, Michael; Moran, William (1985). "An elementary proof of Gleason's theorem". Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society . 98 (1): 117–128. Bibcode:1985MPCPS..98..117C. doi:10.1017/S0305004100063313. S2CID   124627182.
  22. Pitowsky, Itamar (1998). "Infinite and finite Gleason's theorems and the logic of indeterminacy". Journal of Mathematical Physics . 39 (1): 218–228. Bibcode:1998JMP....39..218P. doi: 10.1063/1.532334 .
  23. Hudson, Robin Lyth (1986). "Geometry of quantum theory". The Mathematical Gazette . 70 (454): 332–333. doi:10.2307/3616230. JSTOR   3616230.
  24. 1 2 Fuchs, Christopher A. (2011). Coming of Age with Quantum Information: Notes on a Paulian Idea. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN   978-0-521-19926-1. OCLC   535491156.
  25. Stairs, Allen (2015). "Quantum Logic and Quantum Reconstruction". Foundations of Physics . 45 (10): 1351–1361. arXiv: 1501.05492 . Bibcode:2015FoPh...45.1351S. doi:10.1007/s10701-015-9879-4. S2CID   126435.
  26. 1 2 Wilce, A. (2021-08-10). "Quantum Logic and Probability Theory". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 ed.).
  27. 1 2 3 4 5 Mermin, N. David (1993-07-01). "Hidden variables and the two theorems of John Bell". Reviews of Modern Physics . 65 (3): 803–815. arXiv: 1802.10119 . Bibcode:1993RvMP...65..803M. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.65.803. S2CID   119546199.
  28. Shimony, Abner (1984). "Contextual Hidden Variable Theories and Bell's Inequalities". British Journal for the Philosophy of Science . 35 (1): 25–45. doi:10.1093/bjps/35.1.25.
  29. Harrigan, Nicholas; Spekkens, Robert W. (2010). "Einstein, incompleteness, and the epistemic view of quantum states". Foundations of Physics . 40 (2): 125–157. arXiv: 0706.2661 . Bibcode:2010FoPh...40..125H. doi:10.1007/s10701-009-9347-0. S2CID   32755624.
  30. Peres, Asher (1991). "Two simple proofs of the Kochen-Specker theorem". Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and General . 24 (4): L175–L178. Bibcode:1991JPhA...24L.175P. doi:10.1088/0305-4470/24/4/003. ISSN   0305-4470.
  31. Stairs, Allen (1983). "Quantum Logic, Realism, and Value Definiteness". Philosophy of Science . 50 (4): 578–602. doi:10.1086/289140. S2CID   122885859.
  32. Heywood, Peter; Redhead, Michael L. G. (1983). "Nonlocality and the Kochen–Specker paradox". Foundations of Physics . 13 (5): 481–499. Bibcode:1983FoPh...13..481H. doi:10.1007/BF00729511. S2CID   120340929.
  33. Edwards, David (1979). "The Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics". Synthese . 42: 1–70. doi:10.1007/BF00413704. S2CID   46969028.
  34. van Fraassen, Bas (1991). Quantum Mechanics: An Empiricist View . Clarendon Press. ISBN   9780198239802. OCLC   1005285550.
  35. Barad, Karen (2007). Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of Matter and Meaning. Duke University Press. ISBN   9780822339175. OCLC   894219980.
  36. Dvurecenskij, Anatolij (1992). Gleason's Theorem and Its Applications. Mathematics and its Applications, Vol. 60. Dordrecht: Kluwer Acad. Publ. p. 348. ISBN   978-0-7923-1990-0. OCLC   751579618.
  37. Baez, John C. (2010-12-01). "Solèr's Theorem". The n-Category Café . Retrieved 2017-04-24.
  38. Moretti, Valter; Oppio, Marco (2019-06-01). "Quantum theory in quaternionic Hilbert space: How Poincaré symmetry reduces the theory to the standard complex one". Reviews in Mathematical Physics . 31 (4): 1950013–502. arXiv: 1709.09246 . Bibcode:2019RvMaP..3150013M. doi:10.1142/S0129055X19500132. S2CID   119733863.
  39. Busch, Paul (2003). "Quantum States and Generalized Observables: A Simple Proof of Gleason's Theorem". Physical Review Letters . 91 (12): 120403. arXiv: quant-ph/9909073 . Bibcode:2003PhRvL..91l0403B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.91.120403. PMID   14525351. S2CID   2168715.
  40. 1 2 Caves, Carlton M.; Fuchs, Christopher A.; Manne, Kiran K.; Renes, Joseph M. (2004). "Gleason-Type Derivations of the Quantum Probability Rule for Generalized Measurements". Foundations of Physics . 34 (2): 193–209. arXiv: quant-ph/0306179 . Bibcode:2004FoPh...34..193C. doi:10.1023/B:FOOP.0000019581.00318.a5. S2CID   18132256.
  41. Spekkens, Robert W. (2014). "The Status of Determinism in Proofs of the Impossibility of a Noncontextual Model of Quantum Theory". Foundations of Physics . 44 (11): 1125–1155. arXiv: 1312.3667 . Bibcode:2014FoPh...44.1125S. doi:10.1007/s10701-014-9833-x. S2CID   118469528.
  42. Wright, Victoria J.; Weigert, Stephan (2019). "A Gleason-type theorem for qubits based on mixtures of projective measurements". Journal of Physics A . 52 (5): 055301. arXiv: 1808.08091 . Bibcode:2019JPhA...52e5301W. doi:10.1088/1751-8121/aaf93d. S2CID   119309162.
  43. Grudka, Andrzej; Kurzyński, Paweł (2008). "Is There Contextuality for a Single Qubit?". Physical Review Letters . 100 (16): 160401. arXiv: 0705.0181 . Bibcode:2008PhRvL.100p0401G. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.100.160401. PMID   18518167. S2CID   13251108.
  44. Richman, Fred; Bridges, Douglas (1999-03-10). "A Constructive Proof of Gleason's Theorem". Journal of Functional Analysis . 162 (2): 287–312. doi: 10.1006/jfan.1998.3372 . hdl: 2292/3547 .
  45. Hamhalter, Jan (2003-10-31). Quantum Measure Theory. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN   9781402017148. MR   2015280. OCLC   928681664. Zbl   1038.81003.