Pain in animals

Last updated

A Galapagos shark hooked by a fishing boat Carcharhinus galapagensis hooked.jpg
A Galapagos shark hooked by a fishing boat

Pain negatively affects the health and welfare of animals. [1] "Pain" is defined by the International Association for the Study of Pain as "an unpleasant sensory and emotional experience associated with actual or potential tissue damage, or described in terms of such damage." [2] Only the animal experiencing the pain can know the pain's quality and intensity, and the degree of suffering. It is harder, if even possible, for an observer to know whether an emotional experience has occurred, especially if the sufferer cannot communicate. [3] Therefore, this concept is often excluded in definitions of pain in animals, such as that provided by Zimmerman: "an aversive sensory experience caused by actual or potential injury that elicits protective motor and vegetative reactions, results in learned avoidance and may modify species-specific behaviour, including social behaviour." [4] Nonhuman animals cannot report their feelings to language-using humans in the same manner as human communication, but observation of their behaviour provides a reasonable indication as to the extent of their pain. Just as with doctors and medics who sometimes share no common language with their patients, the indicators of pain can still be understood.

Contents

According to the U.S. National Research Council Committee on Recognition and Alleviation of Pain in Laboratory Animals, pain is experienced by many animal species, including mammals and possibly all vertebrates. [5] Overview of anatomy of the nervous system across animal kingdom indicates that, not only vertebrates, but also most invertebrates have the capacity to feel pain. [6]

The experience of pain

Although there are numerous definitions of pain, almost all involve two key components. First, nociception is required. [7] This is the ability to detect noxious stimuli which evoke a reflex response that rapidly moves the entire animal, or the affected part of its body, away from the source of the stimulus. The concept of nociception does not imply any adverse, subjective "feeling" – it is a reflex action. An example in humans would be the rapid withdrawal of a finger that has touched something hot – the withdrawal occurs before any sensation of pain is actually experienced.

The second component is the experience of "pain" itself, or suffering – the internal, emotional interpretation of the nociceptive experience. Again in humans, this is when the withdrawn finger begins to hurt, moments after the withdrawal. Pain is therefore a private, emotional experience. Pain cannot be directly measured in other animals, including other humans; responses to putatively painful stimuli can be measured, but not the experience itself. To address this problem when assessing the capacity of other species to experience pain, argument-by-analogy is used. This is based on the principle that if an animal responds to a stimulus in a similar way to ourselves, it is likely to have had an analogous experience.

Reflex response to painful stimuli

Reflex arc of a dog when its paw is stuck with a pin. The spinal cord responds to signals from receptors in the paw, producing a reflex withdrawal of the paw. This localized response does not involve brain processes that might mediate a consciousness of pain, though these might also occur. Anatomy and physiology of animals A reflex arc.jpg
Reflex arc of a dog when its paw is stuck with a pin. The spinal cord responds to signals from receptors in the paw, producing a reflex withdrawal of the paw. This localized response does not involve brain processes that might mediate a consciousness of pain, though these might also occur.

Nociception usually involves the transmission of a signal along nerve fibers from the site of a noxious stimulus at the periphery to the spinal cord. Although this signal is also transmitted on to the brain, a reflex response, such as flinching or withdrawal of a limb, is produced by return signals originating in the spinal cord. Thus, both physiological and behavioral responses to nociception can be detected, and no reference need be made to a conscious experience of pain. Based on such criteria, nociception has been observed in all major animal taxa. [7]

Awareness of pain

Nerve impulses from nociceptors may reach the brain, where information about the stimulus (e.g. quality, location, and intensity), and effect (unpleasantness) are registered. Though the brain activity involved has been studied, the brain processes underlying conscious awareness are not well known.

Adaptive value

The adaptive value of nociception is obvious; an organism detecting a noxious stimulus immediately withdraws the limb, appendage or entire body from the noxious stimulus and thereby avoids further (potential) injury. However, a characteristic of pain (in mammals at least) is that pain can result in hyperalgesia (a heightened sensitivity to noxious stimuli) and allodynia (a heightened sensitivity to non-noxious stimuli). When this heightened sensitisation occurs, the adaptive value is less clear. First, the pain arising from the heightened sensitisation can be disproportionate to the actual tissue damage caused. Second, the heightened sensitisation may also become chronic, persisting well beyond the tissues healing. This can mean that rather than the actual tissue damage causing pain, it is the pain due to the heightened sensitisation that becomes the concern. This means the sensitisation process is sometimes termed maladaptive. It is often suggested hyperalgesia and allodynia assist organisms to protect themselves during healing, but experimental evidence to support this has been lacking. [8] [9]

In 2014, the adaptive value of sensitisation due to injury was tested using the predatory interactions between longfin inshore squid (Doryteuthis pealeii) and black sea bass (Centropristis striata) which are natural predators of this squid. If injured squid are targeted by a bass, they began their defensive behaviours sooner (indicated by greater alert distances and longer flight initiation distances) than uninjured squid. If anaesthetic (1% ethanol and MgCl2) is administered prior to the injury, this prevents the sensitisation and blocks the behavioural effect. The authors claim this study is the first experimental evidence to support the argument that nociceptive sensitisation is actually an adaptive response to injuries. [10]

Argument-by-analogy

To assess the capacity of other species to consciously suffer pain we resort to argument-by-analogy. That is, if an animal responds to a stimulus the way a human does, it is likely to have had an analogous experience. If we stick a pin in a chimpanzee's finger and she rapidly withdraws her hand, we use argument-by-analogy and infer that like us, she felt pain. It might be argued that consistency requires us to infer, also, that a cockroach experiences conscious pain when it writhes after being stuck with a pin. The usual counter-argument is that although the physiology of consciousness is not understood, it clearly involves complex brain processes not present in relatively simple organisms. [11] Other analogies have been pointed out. For example, when given a choice of foods, rats [12] and chickens [13] with clinical symptoms of pain will consume more of an analgesic-containing food than animals not in pain. Additionally, the consumption of the analgesic carprofen in lame chickens was positively correlated to the severity of lameness, and consumption resulted in an improved gait. Such anthropomorphic arguments face the criticism that physical reactions indicating pain may be neither the cause nor result of conscious states, and the approach is subject to criticism of anthropomorphic interpretation. For example, a single-celled organism such as an amoeba may writhe after being exposed to noxious stimuli despite the absence of nociception.

History

The idea that animals might not experience pain or suffering as humans do traces back at least to the 17th-century French philosopher, René Descartes, who argued that animals lack consciousness. [14] [15] [16] Researchers remained unsure into the 1980s as to whether animals experience pain, and veterinarians trained in the U.S. before 1989 were simply taught to ignore animal pain. [17] In his interactions with scientists and other veterinarians, Bernard Rollin was regularly asked to "prove" that animals are conscious, and to provide "scientifically acceptable" grounds for claiming that they feel pain. [17] Some authors say that the view that animals feel pain differently is now a minority view. [14] Academic reviews of the topic are more equivocal, noting that, although it is likely that some animals have at least simple conscious thoughts and feelings, [18] some authors continue to question how reliably animal mental states can be determined. [15] [19]

In different species

The ability to experience pain in an animal, or another human for that matter, cannot be determined directly but it may be inferred through analogous physiological and behavioral reactions. [20] Although many animals share similar mechanisms of pain detection to those of humans, have similar areas of the brain involved in processing pain, and show similar pain behaviours, it is notoriously difficult to assess how animals actually experience pain. [21]

Nociception

Nociceptive nerves, which preferentially detect (potential) injury-causing stimuli, have been identified in a variety of animals, including invertebrates. The medicinal leech, Hirudo medicinalis, and sea slug are classic model systems for studying nociception. [21] Many other vertebrate and invertebrate animals also show nociceptive reflex responses similar to our own.

Pain

Many animals also exhibit more complex behavioural and physiological changes indicative of the ability to experience pain: they eat less food, their normal behaviour is disrupted, their social behaviour is suppressed, they may adopt unusual behaviour patterns, they may emit characteristic distress calls, experience respiratory and cardiovascular changes, as well as inflammation and release of stress hormones. [21]

Some criteria that may indicate the potential of another species to feel pain include: [22]

  1. Has a suitable nervous system and sensory receptors
  2. Physiological changes to noxious stimuli
  3. Displays protective motor reactions that might include reduced use of an affected area such as limping, rubbing, holding or autotomy
  4. Has opioid receptors and shows reduced responses to noxious stimuli when given analgesics and local anaesthetics
  5. Shows trade-offs between stimulus avoidance and other motivational requirements
  6. Shows avoidance learning
  7. High cognitive ability and sentience

Vertebrates

Fish

A typical human cutaneous nerve contains 83% C type trauma receptors (the type responsible for transmitting signals described by humans as excruciating pain); the same nerves in humans with congenital insensitivity to pain have only 24-28% C type receptors. [23] The rainbow trout has about 5% C type fibres, while sharks and rays have 0%. [24] Nevertheless, fish have been shown to have sensory neurons that are sensitive to damaging stimuli and are physiologically identical to human nociceptors. [25] Behavioural and physiological responses to a painful event appear comparable to those seen in amphibians, birds, and mammals, and administration of an analgesic drug reduces these responses in fish. [26]

Animal welfare advocates have raised concerns about the possible suffering of fish caused by angling. Some countries, e.g. Germany, have banned specific types of fishing, and the British RSPCA now formally prosecutes individuals who are cruel to fish. [27]

Invertebrates

Though it has been argued that most invertebrates do not feel pain, [28] [29] [30] there is some evidence that invertebrates, especially the decapod crustaceans (e.g. crabs and lobsters) and cephalopods (e.g. octopuses), exhibit behavioural and physiological reactions indicating they may have the capacity for this experience. [11] [31] [32] Nociceptors have been found in nematodes, annelids and mollusks. [33] Insects also usually possess nociceptors. [34] In vertebrates, endogenous opioids are neurochemicals that moderate pain by interacting with opiate receptors. Opioid peptides and opiate receptors occur naturally in nematodes, [35] [36] mollusks, [37] [38] insects [39] [40] and crustaceans. [41] [42] The presence of opioids in crustaceans has been interpreted as an indication that lobsters may be able to experience pain, although it has been claimed "at present no certain conclusion can be drawn". [43]

One suggested reason for rejecting a pain experience in invertebrates is that invertebrate brains are too small. However, brain size does not necessarily equate to complexity of function. [44] Moreover, weight for body-weight, the cephalopod brain is in the same size bracket as the vertebrate brain, smaller than that of birds and mammals, but as big as or bigger than most fish brains. [45] [46] Remarkably, as demonstrated by cognitive tests, intelligence of cephalopods is comparable to that of five-year-old human children. [47]

Since September 2010, all cephalopods being used for scientific purposes in the EU are protected by EU Directive 2010/63/EU which states "...there is scientific evidence of their [cephalopods] ability to experience pain, suffering, distress and lasting harm. [48] In the UK, animal protection legislation [49] means that cephalopods used for scientific purposes must be killed humanely, according to prescribed methods (known as "Schedule 1 methods of euthanasia") known to minimise suffering. [50]

In animal farming

Over 80 billions of land animals are slaughtered for meat every year. Land animals slaughtered for meat - Our World in Data.png
Over 80 billions of land animals are slaughtered for meat every year.

In 2023, it is estimated that 74% of all land livestock are factory farmed. In the United States, 99% of all livestock was estimated in 2017 to be factory farmed. [53] Factory farming, or intensive animal farming, is characterized by densely confined animals [53] and comes with a range of issues, including:

Despite their vast numbers, factory farmed animals are relatively ignored. Species that appear more different from humans, such as fish or insects, are often particularly overlooked. [63] [64] One proposed solution to reduce farmed animal suffering is to develop plant-based and cultured alternatives to animal products. [65]

In medicine and research

Veterinary medicine

Veterinary medicine uses, for actual or potential animal pain, the same analgesics and anesthetics as used in humans. [66]

Dolorimetry

Dolorimetry (dolor: Latin: pain, grief) is the measurement of the pain response in animals, including humans. It is practiced occasionally in medicine, as a diagnostic tool, and is regularly used in research into the basic science of pain, and in testing the efficacy of analgesics.

The intense sociality of humans and the readiness with which they perceive, and identify with, manifestations of physical pain in others have made the study of pain notoriously difficult to quantify. Indeed, many investigators of animal pain shy away from use of the word "pain" in published research. They consider the term to be unscientific and grounded in human emotion, preferring others such as "stress" or "avoidance". As the subjective experience of animals is very resistant to rational assessment, the subjective difference between their painless reflex responses to noxious stimuli (nociception) and pain as humans understand it has been nearly impossible to determine conclusively.

For this reason essentially all scientific research into the nature of animal pain has depended upon so-called pain proxies. These include obvious behavioral changes—shying away, stamping, vocalization, ear cues etc.— as well as subtler changes, as when injured chickens or rats choose feed that has been laced with an analgesic over feed that has not. Most prized by scientists are the quantifiable physiological changes such as elevated heart rate or stress hormone serum concentrations. These physiological proxies are valued because their assessments are carried out by machines and do not rely on humans to determine the magnitude of the variable under study. This is seldom the case for behavioral pain proxies, which are most often scored by a researcher on some numerical scale ranging from "no response" to "intense response". [67]

Dolormetric methods in animals

Nonhuman animal pain measurement techniques include the paw pressure test, tail flick test, hot plate test and grimace scales. Grimace scales are used to assess post-operative and disease pain in mammals. Scales have been developed for ten mammalian species such as mice, rats, and rabbits. [68] Dale Langford established and published the Mouse Grimace Scale in 2010, [69] with Susana Sotocinal inventing the Rat Grimace Scale a year later in 2011. [70] Using video stills from recorders, researchers can track changes in an animal's positioning of ears and whiskers, orbital tightening, and bulging or flattening of the nose area, and match these images against the images in the grimace scale. [71] Laboratory researcher and veterinarians may use the grimace scales to evaluate when to administer analgesia to an animal or whether severity of pain warrants a humane endpoint (euthanasia) for the animal in a study.

Laboratory animals

Animals are kept in laboratories for a wide range of reasons, some of which may involve pain, suffering or distress, whilst others (e.g. many of those involved in breeding) will not. The extent to which animal testing causes pain and suffering in laboratory animals is the subject of much debate. [72] Marian Stamp Dawkins defines "suffering" in laboratory animals as the experience of one of "a wide range of extremely unpleasant subjective (mental) states." [73] The U.S. National Research Council has published guidelines on the care and use of laboratory animals, [74] as well as a report on recognizing and alleviating pain in vertebrates. [75] The United States Department of Agriculture defines a "painful procedure" in an animal study as one that would "reasonably be expected to cause more than slight or momentary pain or distress in a human being to which that procedure was applied." [76] Some critics argue that, paradoxically, researchers raised in the era of increased awareness of animal welfare may be inclined to deny that animals are in pain simply because they do not want to see themselves as people who inflict it. [77] PETA however argues that there is no doubt about animals in laboratories being inflicted with pain. [78] In the UK, animal research likely to cause "pain, suffering, distress or lasting harm" is regulated by the Animals (Scientific Procedures) Act 1986 and research with the potential to cause pain is regulated by the Animal Welfare Act of 1966 in the US.

In the U.S., researchers are not required to provide laboratory animals with pain relief if the administration of such drugs would interfere with their experiment. Laboratory animal veterinarian Larry Carbone writes, "Without question, present public policy allows humans to cause laboratory animals unalleviated pain. The AWA, the Guide for the Care and Use of Laboratory Animals, and current Public Health Service policy all allow for the conduct of what are often called 'Category E' studies – experiments in which animals are expected to undergo significant pain or distress that will be left untreated because treatments for pain would be expected to interfere with the experiment." [79]

Severity scales

Eleven countries have national classification systems of pain and suffering experienced by animals used in research: Australia, Canada, Finland, Germany, The Republic of Ireland, The Netherlands, New Zealand, Poland, Sweden, Switzerland, and the UK. The US also has a mandated national scientific animal-use classification system, but it is markedly different from other countries in that it reports on whether pain-relieving drugs were required and/or used. [80] The first severity scales were implemented in 1986 by Finland and the UK. The number of severity categories ranges between 3 (Sweden and Finland) and 9 (Australia). In the UK, research projects are classified as "mild", "moderate", and "substantial" in terms of the suffering the researchers conducting the study say they may cause; a fourth category of "unclassified" means the animal was anesthetized and killed without recovering consciousness. It should be remembered that in the UK system, many research projects (e.g. transgenic breeding, feeding distasteful food) will require a license under the Animals (Scientific Procedures) Act 1986, but may cause little or no pain or suffering. In December 2001, 39 percent (1,296) of project licenses in force were classified as "mild", 55 percent (1,811) as "moderate", two percent (63) as "substantial", and 4 percent (139) as "unclassified". [81] In 2009, of the project licenses issued, 35 percent (187) were classified as "mild", 61 percent (330) as "moderate", 2 percent (13) as "severe" and 2 percent (11) as unclassified. [82]

In the US, the Guide for the Care and Use of Laboratory Animals defines the parameters for animal testing regulations. It states, "The ability to experience and respond to pain is widespread in the animal kingdom...Pain is a stressor and, if not relieved, can lead to unacceptable levels of stress and distress in animals." [83] The Guide states that the ability to recognize the symptoms of pain in different species is essential for the people caring for and using animals. Accordingly, all issues of animal pain and distress, and their potential treatment with analgesia and anesthesia, are required regulatory issues for animal protocol approval.

See also

Related Research Articles

In physiology, nociception, also nocioception; from Latin nocere 'to harm/hurt') is the sensory nervous system's process of encoding noxious stimuli. It deals with a series of events and processes required for an organism to receive a painful stimulus, convert it to a molecular signal, and recognize and characterize the signal to trigger an appropriate defensive response.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Pain</span> Type of distressing feeling

Pain is a distressing feeling often caused by intense or damaging stimuli. The International Association for the Study of Pain defines pain as "an unpleasant sensory and emotional experience associated with, or resembling that associated with, actual or potential tissue damage."

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Sentience</span> Ability to experience feelings and sensations

Sentience is the ability to experience feelings and sensations. It may not necessarily imply higher cognitive functions such as awareness, reasoning, or complex thought processes. Sentience is an important concept in ethics, as the ability to experience happiness or suffering often forms a basis for determining which entities deserve moral consideration, particularly in utilitarianism.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Nociceptor</span> Sensory neuron that detects pain

A nociceptor is a sensory neuron that responds to damaging or potentially damaging stimuli by sending "possible threat" signals to the spinal cord and the brain. The brain creates the sensation of pain to direct attention to the body part, so the threat can be mitigated; this process is called nociception.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Sensory neuron</span> Nerve cell that converts environmental stimuli into corresponding internal stimuli

Sensory neurons, also known as afferent neurons, are neurons in the nervous system, that convert a specific type of stimulus, via their receptors, into action potentials or graded receptor potentials. This process is called sensory transduction. The cell bodies of the sensory neurons are located in the dorsal root ganglia of the spinal cord.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Opiorphin</span> Endogenous chemical compound first isolated from human saliva

Opiorphin is an endogenous chemical compound first isolated from human saliva. Initial research with mice shows the compound has a painkilling effect greater than that of morphine. It works by stopping the normal breakup of enkephalins, natural pain-killing opioids in the spinal cord. It is a relatively simple molecule consisting of a five-amino acid polypeptide, Gln-Arg-Phe-Ser-Arg (QRFSR).

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Pain in fish</span>

Fish fulfill several criteria proposed as indicating that non-human animals experience pain. These fulfilled criteria include a suitable nervous system and sensory receptors, opioid receptors and reduced responses to noxious stimuli when given analgesics and local anaesthetics, physiological changes to noxious stimuli, displaying protective motor reactions, exhibiting avoidance learning and making trade-offs between noxious stimulus avoidance and other motivational requirements.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Pain in crustaceans</span> Ethical debate

There is a scientific debate which questions whether crustaceans experience pain. It is a complex mental state, with a distinct perceptual quality but also associated with suffering, which is an emotional state. Because of this complexity, the presence of pain in an animal, or another human for that matter, cannot be determined unambiguously using observational methods, but the conclusion that animals experience pain is often inferred on the basis of likely presence of phenomenal consciousness which is deduced from comparative brain physiology as well as physical and behavioural reactions.

Pain in babies, and whether babies feel pain, has been a large subject of debate within the medical profession for centuries. Prior to the late nineteenth century it was generally considered that babies hurt more easily than adults. It was only in the last quarter of the 20th century that scientific techniques finally established babies definitely do experience pain – probably more than adults – and developed reliable means of assessing and of treating it. As recently as 1999, it was widely believed by medical professionals that babies could not feel pain until they were a year old, but today it is believed newborns and likely even fetuses beyond a certain age can experience pain.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Tail flick test</span> Pain response test

The tail flick test is a test of the pain response in animals, similar to the hot plate test. It is used in basic pain research and to measure the effectiveness of analgesics, by observing the reaction to heat. It was first described by D'Amour and Smith in 1941.

The hot plate test is a test of the pain response in animals, similar to the tail flick test. Both hot plate and tail-flick methods are used generally for centrally acting analgesic, while peripherally acting drugs are ineffective in these tests but sensitive to acetic acid-induced writhing test.

A nociception assay evaluates the ability of an animal, usually a rodent, to detect a noxious stimulus such as the feeling of pain, caused by stimulation of nociceptors. These assays measure the existence of pain through behaviors such as withdrawal, licking, immobility, and vocalization. The sensation of pain is not a unitary concept; therefore, a researcher must be conscious as to which nociception assay to use.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Pain in invertebrates</span> Contentious issue

Pain in invertebrates is a contentious issue. Although there are numerous definitions of pain, almost all involve two key components. First, nociception is required. This is the ability to detect noxious stimuli which evokes a reflex response that moves the entire animal, or the affected part of its body, away from the source of the stimulus. The concept of nociception does not necessarily imply any adverse, subjective feeling; it is a reflex action. The second component is the experience of "pain" itself, or suffering—i.e., the internal, emotional interpretation of the nociceptive experience. Pain is therefore a private, emotional experience. Pain cannot be directly measured in other animals, including other humans; responses to putatively painful stimuli can be measured, but not the experience itself. To address this problem when assessing the capacity of other species to experience pain, argument-by-analogy is used. This is based on the principle that if a non-human animal's responses to stimuli are similar to those of humans, it is likely to have had an analogous experience. It has been argued that if a pin is stuck in a chimpanzee's finger and they rapidly withdraw their hand, then argument-by-analogy implies that like humans, they felt pain. It has been questioned why the inference does not then follow that a cockroach experiences pain when it writhes after being stuck with a pin. This argument-by-analogy approach to the concept of pain in invertebrates has been followed by others.

Animal welfare science is the scientific study of the welfare of animals as pets, in zoos, laboratories, on farms and in the wild. Although animal welfare has been of great concern for many thousands of years in religion and culture, the investigation of animal welfare using rigorous scientific methods is a relatively recent development. The world's first Professor of Animal Welfare Science, Donald Broom, was appointed by Cambridge University (UK) in 1986.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Three Rs (animal research)</span> Principles for ethical use of animals in science

The Three Rs (3Rs) are guiding principles for more ethical use of animals in product testing and scientific research. They were first described by W. M. S. Russell and R. L. Burch in 1959. The 3Rs are:

  1. Replacement:methods which avoid the use of animals in research
  2. Reduction: use of methods that enable researchers to minimise the number of animals necessary to obtain reliable and useful information.
  3. Refinement: use of methods that alleviate or minimize potential pain, suffering, distress, or lasting harm and improve welfare for the animals used.
<span class="mw-page-title-main">Maria Carmela Lico</span> Italian-Brazilian physiologist

Maria Carmela Lico or Licco (1927–1985) spent most of her research life as a physiologist studying the neural mechanisms of pain at the Department of Physiology of the Faculdade de Medicina de Ribeirão Preto (Brazil). Lico produced important insights on the descending control of nociception by limbic structures, specially the septal nuclei.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Pain in amphibians</span> Ethical issue

Pain is an aversive sensation and feeling associated with actual, or potential, tissue damage. It is widely accepted by a broad spectrum of scientists and philosophers that non-human animals can perceive pain, including pain in amphibians.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Grimace scale</span> Method of assessing pain in non-human animals

The grimace scale (GS), sometimes called the grimace score, is a method of assessing the occurrence or severity of pain experienced by non-human animals according to objective and blinded scoring of facial expressions, as is done routinely for the measurement of pain in non-verbal humans. Observers score the presence or prominence of "facial action units" (FAU), e.g. Orbital Tightening, Nose Bulge, Ear Position and Whisker Change. These are scored by observing the animal directly in real-time, or post hoc from photographs or screen-grabs from videos. The facial expression of the animals is sometimes referred to as the pain face.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Pain in cephalopods</span> Contentious issue

Pain in cephalopods is a contentious issue. Pain is a complex mental state, with a distinct perceptual quality but also associated with suffering, which is an emotional state. Because of this complexity, the presence of pain in non-human animals, or another human for that matter, cannot be determined unambiguously using observational methods, but the conclusion that animals experience pain is often inferred on the basis of likely presence of phenomenal consciousness which is deduced from comparative brain physiology as well as physical and behavioural reactions.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Chris Sherwin</span> English veterinary scientist (1962–2017)

Christopher M. Sherwin was an English veterinary scientist and senior research fellow at the University of Bristol Veterinary School in Lower Langford, Somerset. He specialised in applied ethology, the study of the behaviour of animals in the context of their interactions with humans, and of how to balance the animals' needs with the demands placed on them by humans.

References

  1. Mathews, Karol; Kronen, Peter W; Lascelles, Duncan; Nolan, Andrea; Robertson, Sheilah; Steagall, Paulo VM; Wright, Bonnie; Yamashita, Kazuto (20 May 2014). "Guidelines for Recognition, Assessment and Treatment of Pain". Journal of Small Animal Practice. 55 (6): E10–E68. doi:10.1111/jsap.12200. ISSN   0022-4510. PMID   24841489.
  2. "IASP Pain Terminology". iasp-pain.org. Archived from the original on 9 November 2017. Retrieved 3 May 2018.
  3. Wright, Andrew. "A Criticism of the IASP's Definition of Pain". Journal of Consciousness Studies. Archived from the original on 22 August 2016. Retrieved 30 October 2017.
  4. Zimmerman, M (1986). "Physiological mechanisms of pain and its treatment". Klinische Anaesthesiol Intensivether. 32: 1–19.
  5. National Research Council (US) Committee on Recognition and Alleviation of Pain in Laboratory Animals (2009). "Recognition and Alleviation of Pain in Laboratory Animals". National Center for Biotechnology Information. Archived from the original on 24 June 2017. Retrieved 14 February 2015.
  6. Ermak, Gennady (2022). Plant-Based, Meat-Based and Between: Ways of Eating for Your Health and Our World. KDP. pp. 55–65. ISBN   979-8785908680.
  7. 1 2 Sneddon, L.U. (2004). "Evolution of nociception in vertebrates: comparative analysis of lower vertebrates". Brain Research Reviews. 46 (2): 123–130. doi:10.1016/j.brainresrev.2004.07.007. PMID   15464201. S2CID   16056461.
  8. Price, T.J. & Dussor, G. (2014). "Evolution: the advantage of 'maladaptive'pain plasticity". Current Biology. 24 (10): R384–R386. Bibcode:2014CBio...24.R384P. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2014.04.011. PMC   4295114 . PMID   24845663.
  9. "maladaptive pain". Oxford Reference. Retrieved 9 June 2024.
  10. Crook, R.J., Dickson, K., Hanlon, R.T. and Walters, E.T. (2014). "Nociceptive sensitization reduces predation risk". Current Biology. 24 (10): 1121–1125. Bibcode:2014CBio...24.1121C. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2014.03.043 . PMID   24814149.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  11. 1 2 Sherwin, C.M. (2001). Can invertebrates suffer? Or, how robust is argument-by-analogy? Animal Welfare, 10(supplement): 103-118
  12. Colpaert, F.C.; Tarayre, J.P.; Alliaga, M.; Slot, L.A.B.; Attal, N.; Koek, W. (2001). "Opiate self-administration as a measure of chronic nociceptive pain in arthritic rats". Pain. 91 (1–2): 33–45. doi:10.1016/s0304-3959(00)00413-9. PMID   11240076. S2CID   24858615.
  13. Danbury, T.C.; Weeks, C.A.; Chambers, J.P.; Waterman-Pearson, A.E.; Kestin, S.C. (2000). "Self-selection of the analgesic drug carprofen by lame broiler chickens". Veterinary Record. 146 (11): 307–311. doi:10.1136/vr.146.11.307. PMID   10766114. S2CID   35062797.
  14. 1 2 Carbone, Larry. '"What Animal Want: Expertise and Advocacy in Laboratory Animal Welfare Policy. Oxford University Press, 2004, p. 149.
  15. 1 2 The Ethics of research involving animals Nuffield Council on Bioethics, Accessed 27 February 2008 Archived 27 February 2008 at the Wayback Machine
  16. Talking Point on the use of animals in scientific research, EMBO Reports 8, 6, 2007, pp. 521–525
  17. 1 2 Rollin, Bernard. The Unheeded Cry: Animal Consciousness, Animal Pain, and Science. New York: Oxford University Press, 1989, pp. xii, 117-118, cited in Carbone 2004, p. 150.
  18. Griffin, DR; Speck, GB (2004). "New evidence of animal consciousness" (PDF). Animal Cognition. 7 (1): 5–18. doi:10.1007/s10071-003-0203-x. PMID   14658059. S2CID   8650837. Archived from the original (PDF) on 21 January 2013.
  19. Allen C (1998). "Assessing animal cognition: ethological and philosophical perspectives" (PDF). J. Anim. Sci. 76 (1): 42–7. doi:10.2527/1998.76142x. PMID   9464883.[ permanent dead link ]
  20. Abbott FV, Franklin KB, Westbrook RF (January 1995). "The formalin test: scoring properties of the first and second phases of the pain response in rats". Pain. 60 (1): 91–102. doi:10.1016/0304-3959(94)00095-V. PMID   7715946. S2CID   35448280.
  21. 1 2 3 Sneddon, Lynne. "Can animals feel pain?". PAIN. Archived from the original on 13 April 2012. Retrieved 18 March 2012.
  22. Elwood, R.W.; Barr, S.; Patterson, L. (2009). "Pain and stress in crustaceans?". Applied Animal Behaviour Science. 118 (3): 128–136. doi:10.1016/j.applanim.2009.02.018.
  23. Rose, JD; Arlinghaus, R; Cooke, SJ; Diggles, BK; Sawynok, W; Stevens, ED; Wynne, CDL (2012). "Can fish really feel pain?" (PDF). Fish and Fisheries. 15 (1): 97–133. doi:10.1111/faf.12010. Archived (PDF) from the original on 4 March 2016.
  24. Snow, P.J.; Plenderleith, M.B.; Wright, L.L. (1993). "Quantitative study of primary sensory neurone populations of three species of elasmobranch fish". Journal of Comparative Neurology. 334 (1): 97–103. doi:10.1002/cne.903340108. PMID   8408762. S2CID   32762031.
  25. L.U. Sneddon; et al. (2003). "Do fishes have nociceptors? Evidence for the evolution of a vertebrate sensory system". Proc Biol Sci. 270 (1520): 1115–21. doi:10.1098/rspb.2003.2349. PMC   1691351 . PMID   12816648.
  26. Sneddon L (2009). "Pain and Distress in Fish". Ilar J. 50 (4): 338–342. doi: 10.1093/ilar.50.4.338 . PMID   19949250.
  27. Leake, J. (14 March 2004). "Anglers to Face RSPCA Check". The Sunday Times. Archived from the original on 23 September 2015. Retrieved 15 September 2015.
  28. Eisemann C, Jorgensen W, Rice D, Cribb M, Zalucki M, Merritt B, Webb P (1984). "Do insects feel pain? - A biological view" (PDF). Experientia. 40 (2): 164–167. doi:10.1007/bf01963580. S2CID   3071. Archived from the original (PDF) on 13 June 2013.
  29. "Do Invertebrates Feel Pain?" Archived 6 January 2010 at the Wayback Machine , The Senate Standing Committee on Legal and Constitutional Affairs, The Parliament of Canada Web Site, accessed 11 June 2008.
  30. Jane A. Smith (1991). "A question of pain in invertebrates". ILAR Journal. 33 (1–2). Archived from the original on 8 October 2011.
  31. Elwood, R.W. (2011). "Pain and suffering in invertebrates?" (PDF). Institute of Laboratory Animal Resources Journal. 52 (2): 175–84. doi: 10.1093/ilar.52.2.175 . PMID   21709310. Archived from the original (PDF) on 7 April 2012.
  32. Fiorito, G. (1986). "Is there pain in invertebrates?". Behavioural Processes. 12 (4): 383–388. doi:10.1016/0376-6357(86)90006-9. PMID   24924695. S2CID   26181117.
  33. St John Smith, E.; Lewin, G.R. (2009). "Nociceptors: a phylogenetic view". Journal of Comparative Physiology A. 195 (12): 1089–1106. doi:10.1007/s00359-009-0482-z. PMC   2780683 . PMID   19830434.
  34. Reynolds, Matt (16 March 2023). "Insect Farming Is Booming. But Is It Cruel?". Wired. ISSN   1059-1028 . Retrieved 28 June 2024.
  35. Wittenburg, N.; Baumeister, R. (1999). "Thermal avoidance in Caenorhabditis elegans: an approach to the study of nociception". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA. 96 (18): 10477–10482. Bibcode:1999PNAS...9610477W. doi: 10.1073/pnas.96.18.10477 . PMC   17914 . PMID   10468634.
  36. Pryor, S.C., Nieto, F., Henry, S. and Sarfo, J. (2007). "The effect of opiates and opiate antagonists on heat latency response in the parasitic nematode Ascaris suum". Life Sciences. 80 (18): 1650–1655. doi:10.1016/j.lfs.2007.01.011. PMID   17363006.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  37. Dalton, L.M.; Widdowson, P.S. (1989). "The involvement of opioid peptides in stress-induced analgesia in the slug Arion ater". Peptides. 10 (1): 9–13. doi:10.1016/0196-9781(89)90067-3. PMID   2568626. S2CID   26432057.
  38. Kavaliers, M.; Ossenkopp, K.-P. (1991). "Opioid systems and magnetic field effects in the land snail, Cepaea nemoralis". Biological Bulletin. 180 (2): 301–309. doi:10.2307/1542401. JSTOR   1542401. PMID   29304689.
  39. Dyakonova, V.E.; Schurmann, F.; Sakharov, D.A. (1999). "Effects of serotonergic and opioidergic drugs on escape behaviors and social status of male crickets". Naturwissenschaften. 86 (9): 435–437. Bibcode:1999NW.....86..435D. doi:10.1007/s001140050647. PMID   10501691. S2CID   9466150.
  40. Zabala, N.; Gomez, M. (1991). "Morphine analgesia, tolerance and addiction in the cricket, Pteronemobius". Pharmacology Biochemistry and Behavior. 40 (4): 887–891. doi:10.1016/0091-3057(91)90102-8. PMID   1816576. S2CID   24429475.
  41. Lozada, M.; Romano, A.; Maldonado, H. (1988). "Effect of morphine and naloxone on a defensive response of the crab Chasmagnathus granulatus". Pharmacology Biochemistry and Behavior. 30 (3): 635–640. doi:10.1016/0091-3057(88)90076-7. PMID   3211972. S2CID   45083722.
  42. Maldonado, H.; Miralto, A. (1982). "Effects of morphine and naloxone on a defensive response of the mantis shrimp (Squilla mantis)". Journal of Comparative Physiology A. 147 (4): 455–459. doi:10.1007/bf00612010. S2CID   3013237.
  43. L. Sømme (2005). "Sentience and pain in invertebrates: Report to Norwegian Scientific Committee for Food Safety". Norwegian University of Life Sciences, Oslo.
  44. Chittka, L.; Niven, J. (2009). "Are Bigger Brains Better?". Current Biology. 19 (21): R995–R1008. Bibcode:2009CBio...19.R995C. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2009.08.023 . PMID   19922859. S2CID   7247082.
  45. "Cephalopod brain size". malankazlev.com. Retrieved 8 April 2020.
  46. Packard, A (1972). "Cephalopods and fish: the limits of convergence". Biological Reviews. 47 (2): 241–307 [266–7]. doi:10.1111/j.1469-185X.1972.tb00975.x. S2CID   85088231.
  47. Ermak, Gennady (2022). Plant-Based, Meat-Based and Between: Ways of Eating for Your Health and Our World. KDP. p. 62. ISBN   979-8785908680.
  48. "Directive 2010/63/EU of the European Parliament and of the Council". Official Journal of the European Union. Article 1, 3(b). Retrieved 17 April 2016.
  49. "Animals (Scientific Protection) Act 1986". Archived from the original on 12 April 2016. Retrieved 18 April 2016.
  50. "The Animals (Scientific Procedures) Act 1986 Amendment Regulations 2012". Archived from the original on 11 February 2016. Retrieved 15 April 2016.
  51. "More than 80 billion land animals are slaughtered for meat every year". Our World in Data. Retrieved 12 September 2024.
  52. Bolotnikova, Marina (7 August 2024). "How Factory Farming Ends". Vox. Retrieved 12 September 2024.
  53. 1 2 Ritchie, Hannah; Roser, Max (24 February 2024). "How many animals are factory-farmed?". Our World in Data.
  54. Torrella, Kenny (10 August 2021). "The fight over cage-free eggs and bacon in California, explained". Vox. Retrieved 12 September 2024.
  55. Torrella, Kenny (22 November 2023). "How America broke the turkey". Vox. Retrieved 12 September 2024.
  56. Williams, Zoe (9 March 2020). "Beak-trimming and brutality: is it time to stop buying brown eggs?". The Guardian. ISSN   0261-3077 . Retrieved 12 September 2024.
  57. Matthews, Dylan (22 November 2019). "An easy way to make piglet lives better". Vox. Retrieved 12 September 2024.
  58. "Allegations of animal cruelty and a bestiality charge at Victorian piggery". ABC News. 11 March 2024. Retrieved 12 September 2024.
  59. Ferrara, Cecilia; Nelson, Catherine (19 January 2019). "The curse of tail-docking: the painful truth about Italy's pigs". The Guardian. ISSN   0261-3077 . Retrieved 12 September 2024.
  60. Torrella, Kenny (25 March 2022). "Gene editing could upend the future of factory farming — for better or worse". Vox. Retrieved 12 September 2024.
  61. Vidal, John (18 October 2021). "Factory farms of disease: how industrial chicken production is breeding the next pandemic". The Guardian. ISSN   0261-3077 . Retrieved 12 September 2024.
  62. 1 2 3 Jacobs, Andrew (29 December 2020). "Is Dairy Farming Cruel to Cows?". The New York Times.
  63. Woodruff, Michael (3 July 2020). "Fish are nothing like us, except that they are sentient beings". Aeon. Retrieved 19 September 2024.
  64. Reynolds, Matt (16 March 2023). "Insect Farming Is Booming. But Is It Cruel?". Wired. ISSN   1059-1028 . Retrieved 6 June 2024.
  65. Piper, Kelsey (15 November 2018). "We could end factory farming this century". Vox. Retrieved 12 September 2024.
  66. Viñuela-Fernández I, Jones E, Welsh EM, Fleetwood-Walker SM (September 2007). "Pain mechanisms and their implication for the management of pain in farm and companion animals". Vet. J. 174 (2): 227–39. doi:10.1016/j.tvjl.2007.02.002. PMID   17553712.
  67. Danbury, T. C.; Weeks, C. A.; Waterman-Pearson, A. E.; Kestin, S. C.; Chambers, J. P. (March 2000). "Self-selection of the analgesic drug carprofen by lame broiler chickens". Veterinary Record. 146 (11): 307–311. doi:10.1136/vr.146.11.307. PMID   10766114. S2CID   35062797.
  68. Mogil, Jeffrey S.; Pang, Daniel S. J.; Silva Dutra, Gabrielle Guanaes; Chambers, Christine T. (1 September 2020). "The development and use of facial grimace scales for pain measurement in animals". Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews. 116: 480–493. doi:10.1016/j.neubiorev.2020.07.013. ISSN   0149-7634. PMID   32682741. S2CID   220575703.
  69. Langford, Dale J.; Bailey, Andrea L.; Chanda, Mona Lisa; Clarke, Sarah E.; Drummond, Tanya E.; Echols, Stephanie; Glick, Sarah; Ingrao, Joelle; Klassen-Ross, Tammy; LaCroix-Fralish, Michael L.; Matsumiya, Lynn (2010). "Coding of facial expressions of pain in the laboratory mouse". Nature Methods. 7 (6): 447–449. doi:10.1038/nmeth.1455. ISSN   1548-7105. PMID   20453868. S2CID   16703705.
  70. Sotocina, Susana G; Sorge, Robert E; Zaloum, Austin; Tuttle, Alexander H; Martin, Loren J; Wieskopf, Jeffrey S; Mapplebeck, Josiane CS; Wei, Peng; Zhan, Shu; Zhang, Shuren; McDougall, Jason J (5 August 2011). "The Rat Grimace Scale: A Partially Automated Method for Quantifying Pain in the Laboratory Rat via Facial Expressions". Molecular Pain. 7: 1744–8069–7-55. doi: 10.1186/1744-8069-7-55 . ISSN   1744-8069. PMC   3163602 . PMID   21801409.
  71. "Grimace scales". National Centre for the Replacement Refinement and Reduction of Animals in Research (NC3Rs). Retrieved 10 December 2020.
  72. Duncan, IJ; Petherick, JC (December 1991). "The implications of cognitive processes for animal welfare". J. Anim. Sci. 69 (12): 5017–22. doi:10.2527/1991.69125017x. PMID   1808195.[ permanent dead link ]; Curtis, SE; Stricklin, WR (1991). "The importance of animal cognition in agricultural animal production systems: an overview". J. Anim. Sci. 69 (12): 5001–7. doi:10.2527/1991.69125001x. PMID   1808193.[ permanent dead link ]
  73. Stamp Dawkins, Marian. "Scientific Basis for Assessing Suffering in Animals," in Singer, Peter. In Defense of Animals: The Second Wave. Blackwell, 2006. p. 28.
  74. Committee for the Update of the Guide for the Care and Use of Laboratory Animals, ed. (2011). Guide for the Care and Use of Laboratory Animals (Report) (8th ed.). The National Academies Press. Archived from the original on 1 August 2013.
  75. National Research Council, Division on Earth and Life Studies, Committee on Recognition and Alleviation of Pain in Laboratory Animals (2009). Recognition and Alleviation of Pain in Laboratory Animals (PDF) (Report). The National Academies Press. Archived from the original (PDF) on 3 November 2013.{{cite report}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  76. Animal Welfare; Definitions for and Reporting of Pain and Distress" Archived 6 October 2014 at the Wayback Machine , Animal Welfare Information Center Bulletin, Summer 2000, Vol. 11 No. 1-2, United States Department of Agriculture.
  77. Carbone 2004, p. 151.
  78. "Cruelty to Animals in Laboratories". peta.org. 22 June 2010. Archived from the original on 2 November 2013. Retrieved 3 May 2018.
  79. Carbone, L (7 September 2011). "Pain in Laboratory Animals: The Ethical and Regulatory Imperatives". PLOS ONE. 6 (9): e21578. Bibcode:2011PLoSO...621578C. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0021578 . PMC   3168441 . PMID   21915253.
  80. Fenwick, N.; Ormandy, E.; Gauthier, C.; Griffin, G. (2011). "Classifying the severity of scientific animal use: a review of international systems". Animal Welfare. 20 (2): 281–301. doi:10.1017/S0962728600002761. S2CID   70934694.
  81. Ryder, Richard D. "Speciesism in the laboratory, " in Singer, Peter. In Defense of Animals: The Second Wave. Blackwell, 2006. p. 99.
  82. "Home Office Statistics". Archived from the original on 22 September 2011. Retrieved 31 October 2011.
  83. Guide for the Care and Use of Laboratory Animals, ILAR, National Research Council, 1996 copyright, p. 64