Civil disobedience

Last updated

Civil disobedience is the active, and professed refusal of a citizen to obey certain laws, demands, orders or commands of a government (or any other authority). By some definitions, civil disobedience has to be nonviolent to be called "civil". Hence, civil disobedience is sometimes equated with peaceful protests or nonviolent resistance. [1] [2] Henry David Thoreau's essay Resistance to Civil Government, published posthumously as Civil Disobedience , popularized the term in the US, although the concept itself has been practiced longer before.

Contents

Various forms of civil disobedience have been used by prominent activists such as American women's suffrage leader Susan B. Anthony in the late 19th century, Egyptian nationalist Saad Zaghloul during the 1910s, and Indian nationalist Mahatma Gandhi in 1920s British India as part of his leadership of the Indian independence movement. Martin Luther King Jr.'s and James Bevel's peaceful nonviolent protests during the civil rights movement in the 1960s United States sometimes contained important aspects of civil disobedience. Although civil disobedience is rarely justifiable in court, [3] King regarded civil disobedience to be a display and practice of reverence for law: "Any man who breaks a law that conscience tells him is unjust and willingly accepts the penalty by staying in jail to arouse the conscience of the community on the injustice of the law is at that moment expressing the very highest respect for the law." [4]

History

An early depiction of civil disobedience is in Sophocles' play Antigone , in which Antigone, one of the daughters of former King of Thebes, Oedipus, defies Creon, the current King of Thebes, who is trying to stop her from giving her brother Polynices a proper burial. She gives a stirring speech in which she tells him that she must obey her conscience rather than human law. She is not at all afraid of the death he threatens her with (and eventually carries out), but she is afraid of how her conscience will smite her if she does not do this. [5]

Conrad Grebel and Anabaptists advocated civil disobedience to oppression. [6] Étienne de La Boétie's thought developed in his work Discours de la servitude volontaire ou le Contr'un (1552) was also taken up by many movements of civil disobedience, which drew from the concept of rebellion to voluntary servitude the foundation of its instrument of struggle. Étienne de La Boétie was one of the first to theorize and propose the strategy of non-cooperation, and thus a form of nonviolent disobedience, as a really effective weapon.

In the lead-up to the Glorious Revolution in Britain—when the 1689 Bill of Rights was documented, the last Catholic monarch was deposed, and male and female joint-co-monarchs elevated—the English Midland Enlightenment developed a manner of voicing objection to a law viewed as illegitimate and then taking the consequences of the law. (For example, they might refuse to swear allegiance to the king, and, as a consequence, accept the prison sentence legally and normally meted out to people who refused to take this oath.) This was focused on the illegitimacy of laws claimed to be "divine" in origin, both the "divine rights of kings" and "divine rights of man", and the legitimacy of laws acknowledged to be made by human beings. [7] [8] [9] [ relevant? ]

Following the Peterloo massacre of 1819, the poet Percy Shelley wrote the political poem The Mask of Anarchy later that year, that begins with the images of what he thought to be the unjust forms of authority of his time—and then imagines the stirrings of a new form of social action. According to Ashton Nichols, it is perhaps the first modern statement of the principle of nonviolent protest. [10] A version was taken up by the author Henry David Thoreau in his essay Civil Disobedience, and later by Gandhi in his doctrine of Satyagraha . [10] Gandhi's Satyagraha was partially influenced and inspired by Shelley's nonviolence in protest and political action. [11] In particular, it is known that Gandhi often quoted Shelley's Mask of Anarchy to vast audiences during the campaign for a free India. [10] [12]

Thoreau's 1849 essay Civil Disobedience , originally titled "Resistance to Civil Government", has had a wide influence on many later practitioners of civil disobedience. The driving idea behind the essay is that citizens are morally responsible for their support of aggressors, even when such support is required by law. In the essay, Thoreau explained his reasons for having refused to pay taxes as an act of protest against slavery and against the Mexican–American War. He writes,

If I devote myself to other pursuits and contemplations, I must first see, at least, that I do not pursue them sitting upon another man's shoulders. I must get off him first, that he may pursue his contemplations too. See what gross inconsistency is tolerated. I have heard some of my townsmen say, "I should like to have them order me out to help put down an insurrection of the slaves, or to march to Mexico;—see if I would go;" and yet these very men have each, directly by their allegiance, and so indirectly, at least, by their money, furnished a substitute.

By the 1850s, a range of minority groups in the United States: African Americans, Jews, Seventh Day Baptists, Catholics, anti-prohibitionists, racial egalitarians, and others—employed civil disobedience to combat a range of legal measures and public practices that to them promoted ethnic, religious, and racial discrimination. Pro Public and typically peaceful resistance to political power remained an integral tactic in modern American minority rights politics. [13]

In Ireland starting from 1879 the Irish "Land War" intensified when Irish nationalist leader Charles Stewart Parnell, in a speech in Ennis proposed that when dealing with tenants who take farms where another tenant was evicted, rather than resorting to violence, everyone in the locality should shun them. Following this Captain Charles Boycott, the land agent of an absentee landlord in County Mayo, Ireland, was subject to social ostracism organized by the Irish Land League in 1880. Boycott attempted to evict eleven tenants from his land. While Parnell's speech did not refer to land agents or landlords, the tactic was applied to Boycott when the alarm was raised about the evictions. Despite the short-term economic hardship to those undertaking this action, Boycott soon found himself isolated – his workers stopped work in the fields and stables, as well as in his house. Local businessmen stopped trading with him, and the local postman refused to deliver mail. The movement spread throughout Ireland and gave rise to the term to Boycott, and eventually led to legal reform and support for Irish independence. [14]

Egypt saw a massive implementation on a nation-wide movement starting 1914 and peaking in 1919 as the Egyptian Revolution of 1919. This was then adopted by other peoples who campaigned against European colonial rule from 1920 onwards. [15] Zaghloul Pasha, considered the mastermind behind this massive civil disobedience, was a native middle-class, Azhar graduate, political activist, judge, parliamentary and ex-cabinet minister whose leadership brought Christian and Muslim communities together as well as women into the massive protests. Along with his companions of Wafd Party, who have achieved an independence of Egypt and a first constitution in 1923. Civil disobedience is one of the many ways people have revolted against what they deem to be unfair laws. It has been used in many nonviolent resistance movements in India (Mahatma Gandhi's campaigns for independence from the British Empire), in Czechoslovakia's Velvet Revolution, in early stages of the Bangladeshi independence movement against Pakistani colonialism and in East Germany to oust their Stalinist government. [16] In South Africa during the leftist campaign against the far-right Apartheid regime, in the American civil rights movement against Jim Crow laws, in the Singing Revolution to bring independence to the Baltic countries from the Soviet Union, and more recently with the 2003 Rose Revolution in Georgia, the 2004 Orange Revolution [17] and the 2013–2014 Euromaidan revolution in Ukraine, the 2016–2017 Candlelight Revolution in South Korea, and the 2020–2021 Belarusian protests, among many other various movements worldwide.

Etymology

Henry David Thoreau's classic essay Civil Disobedience inspired Martin Luther King Jr. and many other activists. Benjamin D. Maxham - Henry David Thoreau - Restored - greyscale - straightened.jpg
Henry David Thoreau's classic essay Civil Disobedience inspired Martin Luther King Jr. and many other activists.

Henry David Thoreau's 1849 essay "Resistance to Civil Government" was eventually renamed "Essay on Civil Disobedience". After his landmark lectures were published in 1866, the term began to appear in numerous sermons and lectures relating to slavery and the war in Mexico. [18] [19] [20] [21] Thus, by the time Thoreau's lectures were first published under the title "Civil Disobedience", in 1866, four years after his death, the term had achieved fairly widespread usage.

It has been argued that the term "civil disobedience" has always suffered from ambiguity and in modern times, become utterly debased. Marshall Cohen notes, "It has been used to describe everything from bringing a test-case in the federal courts to taking aim at a federal official. Indeed, for Vice President Spiro Agnew it has become a code-word describing the activities of muggers, arsonists, draft evaders, campaign hecklers, campus militants, anti-war demonstrators, juvenile delinquents and political assassins." [22]

LeGrande writes that

the formulation of a single all-encompassing definition of the term is extremely difficult, if not impossible. In reviewing the voluminous literature on the subject, the student of civil disobedience rapidly finds himself surrounded by a maze of semantical problems and grammatical niceties. Like Alice in Wonderland, he often finds that specific terminology has no more (or no less) meaning than the individual orator intends it to have.

He encourages a distinction between lawful protest demonstration, nonviolent civil disobedience, and violent civil disobedience. [23]

In a letter to P. K. Rao, dated 10 September 1935, Gandhi disputes that his idea of civil disobedience was derived from the writings of Thoreau: [24]

The statement that I had derived my idea of Civil Disobedience from the writings of Thoreau is wrong. The resistance to authority in South Africa was well advanced before I got the essay ... When I saw the title of Thoreau's great essay, I began to use his phrase to explain our struggle to the English readers. But I found that even "Civil Disobedience" failed to convey the full meaning of the struggle. I therefore adopted the phrase "Civil Resistance."

Theories

In seeking an active form of civil disobedience, one may choose to deliberately break certain laws, such as by forming a peaceful blockade or occupying a facility illegally, [25] though sometimes violence has been known to occur. Often there is an expectation to be attacked or even beaten by the authorities. Protesters often undergo training in advance on how to react to arrest or to attack.

Civil disobedience is usually defined as pertaining to a citizen's relation to the state and its laws, as distinguished from a constitutional impasse, in which two public agencies, especially two equally sovereign branches of government, conflict. For instance, if the head of government of a country were to refuse to enforce a decision of that country's highest court, it would not be civil disobedience, since the head of government would act in his or her capacity as public official rather than private citizen. [26]

This definition is disputed by Thoreau's political philosophy on the conscience vs. the collective. The person is the final judge of right and wrong. More than this, since only people act, only a person can act unjustly. When the government knocks on the door, it is a person in the form of a postman or tax collector whose hand hits the wood. Before Thoreau's imprisonment, when a confused taxman had wondered aloud about how to handle his refusal to pay, Thoreau had advised, "Resign". If a man chose to be an agent of injustice, then Thoreau insisted on confronting him with the fact that he was making a choice. He admits that government may express the will of the majority but it may also express nothing more than the will of elite politicians. Even a good form of government is "liable to be abused and perverted before the people can act through it". If a government did express the voice of most people, this would not compel the obedience of those who disagree with what is said. The majority may be powerful but it is not necessarily right. [27]

In his 1971 book, A Theory of Justice , John Rawls described civil disobedience as "a public, non-violent, conscientious yet political act contrary to law usually done with the aim of bringing about change in the law or policies of the government". [28]

Ronald Dworkin held that there are three types of civil disobedience:

Some theories of civil disobedience hold that civil disobedience is only justified against governmental entities. Brownlee argues that disobedience in opposition to the decisions of non-governmental agencies such as trade unions, banks, and private universities can be justified if it reflects "a larger challenge to the legal system that permits those decisions to be taken". The same principle, she argues, applies to breaches of law in protest against international organizations and foreign governments. [30]

It is usually recognized that lawbreaking, if it is not done publicly, at least must be publicly announced to constitute civil disobedience. But Stephen Eilmann argues that if it is necessary to disobey rules that conflict with morality, we might ask why disobedience should take the form of public civil disobedience rather than simply covert lawbreaking. If a lawyer wishes to help a client overcome legal obstacles to securing their natural rights, he might, for instance, find that assisting in fabricating evidence or committing perjury is more effective than open disobedience. This assumes that common morality does not have a prohibition on deceit in such situations. [31] The Fully Informed Jury Association's publication "A Primer for Prospective Jurors" notes, "Think of the dilemma faced by German citizens when Hitler's secret police demanded to know if they were hiding a Jew in their house." [32] By this definition, civil disobedience could be traced back to the Book of Exodus, where Shiphrah and Puah refused a direct order of Pharaoh but misrepresented how they did it. (Exodus 1: 15–19) [33]

Violent vs. nonviolent

There have been debates as to whether civil disobedience must necessarily be non-violent. Black's Law Dictionary includes nonviolence in its definition of civil disobedience. Christian Bay's encyclopedia article states that civil disobedience requires "carefully chosen and legitimate means", but holds that they do not have to be non-violent. [34] It has been argued that, while both civil disobedience and civil rebellion are justified by appeal to constitutional defects, rebellion is much more destructive; therefore, the defects justifying rebellion must be much more serious than those justifying disobedience, and if one cannot justify civil rebellion, then one cannot justify a civil disobedient's use of force and violence and refusal to submit to arrest. Civil disobedients' refraining from violence is also said to help preserve society's tolerance of civil disobedience. [35]

The philosopher H. J. McCloskey argues that "if violent, intimidatory, coercive disobedience is more effective, it is, other things being equal, more justified than less effective, nonviolent disobedience." [36] In his best-selling Disobedience and Democracy: Nine Fallacies on Law and Order, [37] Howard Zinn takes a similar position; Zinn states that while the goals of civil disobedience are generally nonviolent,

in the inevitable tension accompanying the transition from a violent world to a non-violent one, the choice of means will almost never be pure, and will involve such complexities that the simple distinction between violence and non-violence does not suffice as a guide ... the very acts with which we seek to do good cannot escape the imperfections of the world we are trying to change. [38]

Zinn rejects any "easy and righteous dismissal of violence", noting that Thoreau, the popularizer of the term civil disobedience, approved of the armed insurrection of John Brown. He also notes that some major civil disobedience campaigns which have been classified as non-violent, such as the Birmingham campaign, have actually included elements of violence. [39] [40]

Revolutionary vs. non-revolutionary

Non-revolutionary civil disobedience is a simple disobedience of laws on the grounds that they are judged "wrong" by a person's conscience, or as part of an effort to render certain laws ineffective, to cause their repeal, or to exert pressure to get one's political wishes on some other issue. Revolutionary civil disobedience is more of an active attempt to overthrow a government (or to change cultural traditions, social customs or religious beliefs). Revolution does not have to be political, i.e. "cultural revolution", it simply implies sweeping and widespread change to a section of the social fabric. [41] Gandhi's acts have been described as revolutionary civil disobedience. [26] It has been claimed that the Hungarians under Ferenc Deák directed revolutionary civil disobedience against the Austrian government. [42] Thoreau also wrote of civil disobedience accomplishing "peaceable revolution". [43] Howard Zinn, Harvey Wheeler, and others have identified the right espoused in the US Declaration of Independence to "alter or abolish" an unjust government to be a principle of civil disobedience. [40] [44]

Collective vs. solitary

The earliest recorded incidents of collective civil disobedience took place during the Roman Empire. [45] Unarmed Jews gathered in the streets to prevent the installation of pagan images in the Temple in Jerusalem. [46] [ original research? ] In modern times, some activists who commit civil disobedience as a group collectively refuse to sign bail until certain demands are met, such as favourable bail conditions, or the release of all the activists. This is a form of jail solidarity. [47] [ page needed ] There have also been many instances of solitary civil disobedience, such as that committed by Thoreau, but these sometimes go unnoticed. Thoreau, at the time of his arrest, was not yet a well-known author, and his arrest was not covered in any newspapers in the days, weeks and months after it happened. The tax collector who arrested him rose to higher political office, and Thoreau's essay was not published until after the end of the Mexican War. [48]

Choices

Action

Civil disobedients have chosen a variety of different illegal acts. Hugo A. Bedau writes,

There is a whole class of acts, undertaken in the name of civil disobedience, which, even if they were widely practiced, would in themselves constitute hardly more than a nuisance (e.g. trespassing at a nuclear-missile installation) ... Such acts are often just a harassment and, at least to the bystander, somewhat inane ... The remoteness of the connection between the disobedient act and the objectionable law lays such acts open to the charge of ineffectiveness and absurdity.

Bedau also notes, though, that the very harmlessness of such entirely symbolic illegal protests toward public policy goals may serve a propaganda purpose. [42] Some civil disobedients, such as the proprietors of illegal medical cannabis dispensaries and Voice in the Wilderness, which brought medicine to Iraq without the permission of the US government, directly achieve a desired social goal (such as the provision of medication to the sick) while openly breaking the law. Julia Butterfly Hill lived in Luna, a 180-foot (55 m)-tall, 600-year-old California Redwood tree for 738 days, preventing its felling.

In cases where the criminalized behaviour is pure speech, civil disobedience can consist simply of engaging in the forbidden speech. An example is WBAI's broadcasting of the bit "Filthy Words" from a George Carlin comedy album, which eventually led to the 1978 Supreme Court case of FCC v. Pacifica Foundation . Threatening government officials is a way to express defiance toward the government and unwillingness to stand for its policies. For example, a supporter of some tax deniers in New Hampshire, Edward and Elaine Brown, was arrested for allegedly telling the local city councillors to "Wise up or die." [49]

More generally, protesters of particular victimless crimes often see fit to openly commit that crime. Laws against public nudity, for instance, have been protested by going naked in public, and laws against cannabis consumption have been protested by openly possessing it and using it at cannabis rallies. [50]

Some forms of civil disobedience, such as illegal boycotts, refusals to pay taxes, draft dodging, distributed denial-of-service attacks, and sit-ins, make it more difficult for a system to function. In this way, they might be considered coercive; coercive disobedience has the effect of exposing the enforcement of laws and policies, and it has even operated as an aesthetic strategy in contemporary art practice. [51] Brownlee notes that "although civil disobedients are constrained in their use of coercion by their conscientious aim to engage in moral dialogue, nevertheless they may find it necessary to employ limited coercion to get their issue onto the table". [30] The Plowshares organization temporarily closed GCSB Waihopai by padlocking the gates and using sickles to deflate one of the large domes covering two satellite dishes.

Electronic civil disobedience can include web site defacements, redirects, denial-of-service attacks, information theft and data leaks, illegal web site parodies, virtual sit-ins, and virtual sabotage. It is distinct from other kinds of hacktivism in that the perpetrator openly reveals his identity. Virtual actions rarely succeed in completely shutting down their targets, but they often generate media attention. [52]

Dilemma actions are designed to create a "response dilemma" for public authorities "by forcing them to either concede some public space to protesters or make themselves look absurd or heavy-handed by acting against the protest." [53]

Response to punishment

As civil disobedience is intentionally breaking the law, people engaging in civil disobedience can expect to be arrested, criminally charged, tried, and legally punished for breaking the law. Protestors have to make choices about how to respond to each of these results.

Al Sharpton, a civil rights and social justice activist, says that civil disobedients "must be prepared to say the cause is more important than my freedom" and not incorrectly believe themselves to have legal immunity or feel a sense of entitlement to break laws without being subject to the ordinary legal punishments for breaking those laws. [54]

Arrest strategies

A police officer speaks with a demonstrator at a union picket, explaining that she will be arrested if she does not leave the street. The demonstrator was arrested moments later. Police officer speaking to demonstrator during civil disobedience action.jpg
A police officer speaks with a demonstrator at a union picket, explaining that she will be arrested if she does not leave the street. The demonstrator was arrested moments later.

Some disciplines of civil disobedience hold that the protester must submit to arrest and cooperate with the authorities. Others advocate falling limp or resisting arrest, especially when it will hinder the police from effectively responding to a mass protest.

Many of the same decisions and principles that apply in other criminal investigations and arrests arise also in civil disobedience cases. For example, the suspect may need to decide whether to grant a consent search of his property and whether to talk to police officers. It is generally agreed within the legal community, [55] and is often believed within the activist community, that a suspect's talking to criminal investigators can serve no useful purpose and may be harmful. Some civil disobedients are compelled to respond to investigators' questions, sometimes by a misunderstanding of the legal ramifications or a fear of seeming rude. [56] Also, some civil disobedients seek to use the arrest as an opportunity to make an impression on the officers. Thoreau wrote,

My civil neighbor, the tax-gatherer, is the very man I have to deal with—for it is, after all, with men and not with parchment that I quarrel—and he has voluntarily chosen to be an agent of the government. How shall he ever know well that he is and does as an officer of the government, or as a man, until he is obliged to consider whether he will treat me, his neighbor, for whom he has respect, as a neighbor and well-disposed man, or as a maniac and disturber of the peace, and see if he can get over this obstruction to his neighborliness without a ruder and more impetuous thought or speech corresponding with his action. [43]

Trial strategies

Some civil disobedients feel it is incumbent upon them to accept punishment because of their belief in the validity of the social contract, which is held to bind all to obey the laws that a government meeting certain standards of legitimacy has established, or else suffer the penalties set out in the law. Other civil disobedients who favour the existence of government still do not believe in the legitimacy of their particular government or do not believe in the legitimacy of a particular law it has enacted. Anarchistic civil disobedients do not believe in the legitimacy of any government, so see no need to accept punishment for a violation of criminal law.

Pleading guilty

An important decision for civil disobedients is whether to plead guilty. There is much debate on this point, as some believe that it is a civil disobedient's duty to submit to the punishment prescribed by law, while others believe that defending oneself in court will increase the possibility of changing the unjust law. [57] It has also been argued that either choice is compatible with the spirit of civil disobedience. ACT UP's Civil Disobedience Training handbook states that a civil disobedient who pleads guilty is essentially stating, "Yes, I committed the act of which you accuse me. I don't deny it; in fact, I am proud of it. I feel I did the right thing by violating this particular law; I am guilty as charged", but that pleading not guilty sends a message of, "Guilt implies wrong-doing. I feel I have done no wrong. I may have violated some specific laws, but I am guilty of doing no wrong. I, therefore, plead not guilty." A plea of no contest is sometimes regarded as a compromise between the two. [58] One defendant accused of illegally protesting nuclear power, when asked to enter his plea, stated, "I plead for the beauty that surrounds us"; [59] this is known as a "creative plea", and will usually be interpreted as a plea of not guilty. [60]

When the Committee for Non-Violent Action sponsored a protest in August 1957, at the Camp Mercury nuclear test site near Las Vegas, Nevada, 13 of the protesters attempted to enter the test site knowing that they faced arrest. At an announced time, one by one they crossed a line and were immediately arrested. They were put on a bus and taken to the Nye County seat of Tonopah, Nevada, and arraigned for trial before the local Justice of the Peace, that afternoon. A civil rights attorney, Francis Heisler, had volunteered to defend the accused, advising them to plead nolo contendere rather than guilty or not guilty. They were found guilty and given suspended sentences, conditional on not reentering the test site. [61]

Howard Zinn writes,

There may be many times when protesters choose to go to jail, as a way of continuing their protest, as a way of reminding their countrymen of injustice. But that is different than the notion that they must go to jail as part of a rule connected with civil disobedience. The key point is that the spirit of protest should be maintained all the way, whether it is done by remaining in jail, or by evading it. To accept jail penitently as an accession to "the rules" is to switch suddenly to a spirit of subservience, to demean the seriousness of the protest ... In particular, the neo-conservative insistence on a guilty plea should be eliminated. [62]

Sometimes the prosecution proposes a plea bargain to civil disobedients, as in the case of the Camden 28, in which the defendants were offered an opportunity to plead guilty to one misdemeanour count and receive no jail time. [63] In some mass arrest situations, the activists decide to use solidarity tactics to secure the same plea bargain for everyone. [60]

But some activists have opted to enter a blind plea, pleading guilty without any plea agreement in place. Mahatma Gandhi pleaded guilty and told the court, "I am here to ... submit cheerfully to the highest penalty that can be inflicted upon me for what in law is a deliberate crime and what appears to me to be the highest duty of a citizen." [64]

Allocution

Some civil disobedience defendants choose to make a defiant speech, or a speech explaining their actions, in allocution. [65] In U.S. v. Burgos-Andujar, a defendant who was involved in a movement to stop military exercises by trespassing on US Navy property argued to the court in allocution that "the ones who are violating the greater law are the members of the Navy". As a result, the judge increased her sentence from 40 to 60 days. This action was upheld because, according to the US Court of Appeals for the First Circuit, her statement suggested a lack of remorse, an attempt to avoid responsibility for her actions, and even a likelihood of repeating her illegal actions. [66] Some of the other allocution speeches given by the protesters complained about mistreatment from government officials. [67]

Tim DeChristopher gave an allocution statement to the court describing the US as "a place where the rule of law was created through acts of civil disobedience" and arguing, "Since those bedrock acts of civil disobedience by our founding fathers, the rule of law in this country has continued to grow closer to our shared higher moral code through the civil disobedience that drew attention to legalized injustice." [68]

Trial strategies

Steven Barkan writes that if defendants plead not guilty, "they must decide whether their primary goal will be to win an acquittal and avoid imprisonment or a fine, or to use the proceedings as a forum to inform the jury and the public of the political circumstances surrounding the case and their reasons for breaking the law via civil disobedience." A technical defence may enhance the chances for acquittal but increase the possibility of additional proceedings and of reduced press coverage. During the Vietnam War era, the Chicago Eight used a political defence, but Benjamin Spock used a technical defence. [69] In countries such as the United States, whose laws guarantee the right to a jury trial but do not excuse lawbreaking for political purposes, some civil disobedients seek jury nullification. Over the years, this has been made more difficult by court decisions such as Sparf v. United States , which held that the judge need not inform jurors of their nullification prerogative, and United States v. Dougherty , which held that the judge need not allow defendants to openly seek jury nullification.

British judge Lord Hoffman writes that "In deciding whether or not to impose punishment, the most important consideration would be whether it would do more harm than good. This means that the objector has no right not to be punished. It is a matter for the state (including the judges) to decide on utilitarian grounds whether to do so or not." [70] Hoffman also asserted that while the "rules of the game" for civil disobedients were to remain non-violent while breaking the law, the authorities must recognize that demonstrators are acting out of their conscience in pursuit of democracy. "When it comes to punishment, the court should take into account their personal convictions", he said. [71]

Choices made by society

In addition to legal action, civil disobedients may be affected socially. For example, student protesters may be suspended or expelled from school. [72] [73] [74] Civil disobedients may be disowned by or become estranged from their families. [74] Some employers may prefer to hire people who did not engage in civil disobedience [72] [75] or fire employees who do. [76] [77]

Governments have generally not recognized the legitimacy of civil disobedience or viewed political objectives as an excuse for breaking the law. Specifically, the law usually distinguishes between criminal motive and criminal intent; the offender's motives or purposes may be admirable and praiseworthy, but his intent may still be criminal. [78] For example, a protester may be motivated by a desire to increase awareness about an injustice and intend to block traffic on a street, and it is the intention, rather than the motivation, that is criminally significant. Hence the saying that "if there is any possible justification of civil disobedience, it must come from outside the legal system." [79]

One theory is that, while disobedience may be helpful, any great amount of it undermines the law by encouraging general disobedience which is neither conscientious nor of social benefit. Therefore, conscientious lawbreakers must be punished. [80]

Courts have distinguished between two types of civil disobedience: "Indirect civil disobedience involves violating a law which is not, itself, the object of protest, whereas direct civil disobedience involves protesting the existence of a particular law by breaking that law." [81]

During the Vietnam War, courts typically refused to excuse the perpetrators of illegal protests from punishment on the basis of their challenging the legality of the Vietnam War; the courts ruled it was a political question. [82] The necessity defence has sometimes been used as a shadow defence by civil disobedients to deny guilt without denouncing their politically motivated acts, and to present their political beliefs in the courtroom. [83] Court cases such as United States v. Schoon have greatly curtailed the availability of the political necessity defence. [84] Likewise, when Carter Wentworth was charged for his role in the Clamshell Alliance's 1977 illegal occupation of the Seabrook Station Nuclear Power Plant, the judge instructed the jury to disregard his competing harms defence, and he was found guilty. [85] Fully Informed Jury Association activists have sometimes handed out educational leaflets inside courthouses despite admonitions not to; according to the association, many of them have escaped prosecution because "prosecutors have reasoned (correctly) that if they arrest fully informed jury leafleters, the leaflets will have to be given to the leafleter's own jury as evidence." [86]

Along with giving the offender his just deserts, achieving crime control via incapacitation and deterrence is a major goal of criminal punishment. [87] [88] Brownlee says "Bringing in deterrence at the level of justification detracts from the law's engagement in a moral dialogue with the offender as a rational person because it focuses attention on the threat of punishment and not the moral reasons to follow this law." [30]

Actions that are outside of civil disobedience

Michael Bayles argues that if a person violates a law to create a test case as to the constitutionality of a law, and then wins his case, then that act did not constitute civil disobedience. [89]

Breaking the law for self-gratification, as in the case of a cannabis user who does not direct his act at securing the repeal of amendment of the law, is not civil disobedience. [90] Likewise, a protester who attempts to escape punishment by committing the crime covertly and avoiding attribution, or by denying having committed the crime, or by fleeing the jurisdiction, is generally not called a civil disobedient.

See also

Related Research Articles

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Satyagraha</span> Form of nonviolent resistance practised during British colonial rule in India

Satyāgraha, or "holding firmly to truth", or "truth force", is a particular form of nonviolent resistance or civil resistance. Someone who practises satyagraha is a satyagrahi.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Nonviolence</span> Principle or practice of not causing harm to others

Nonviolence is the personal practice of not causing harm to others under any condition. It may come from the belief that hurting people, animals and/or the environment is unnecessary to achieve an outcome and it may refer to a general philosophy of abstention from violence. It may be based on moral, religious or spiritual principles, or the reasons for it may be strategic or pragmatic. Failure to distinguish between the two types of nonviolent approaches can lead to distortion in the concept's meaning and effectiveness, which can subsequently result in confusion among the audience. Although both principled and pragmatic nonviolent approaches preach for nonviolence, they may have distinct motives, goals, philosophies, and techniques. However, rather than debating the best practice between the two approaches, both can indicate alternative paths for those who do not want to use violence.

Anarcho-pacifism, also referred to as anarchist pacifism and pacifist anarchism, is an anarchist school of thought that advocates for the use of peaceful, non-violent forms of resistance in the struggle for social change. Anarcho-pacifism rejects the principle of violence which is seen as a form of power and therefore as contradictory to key anarchist ideals such as the rejection of hierarchy and dominance. Many anarcho-pacifists are also Christian anarchists, who reject war and the use of violence.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Protest</span> Public expression of objection, typically political

A protest is a public act of objection, disapproval or dissent against political advantage. Protests can be thought of as acts of cooperation in which numerous people cooperate by attending, and share the potential costs and risks of doing so. Protests can take many different forms, from individual statements to mass political demonstrations. Protesters may organize a protest as a way of publicly making their opinions heard in an attempt to influence public opinion or government policy, or they may undertake direct action in an attempt to enact desired changes themselves. When protests are part of a systematic and peaceful nonviolent campaign to achieve a particular objective, and involve the use of pressure as well as persuasion, they go beyond mere protest and may be better described as civil resistance or nonviolent resistance.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Gene Sharp</span> American political scientist (1928–2018)

Gene Sharp was an American political scientist. He was the founder of the Albert Einstein Institution, a non-profit organization dedicated to advancing the study of nonviolent action, and professor of political science at the University of Massachusetts Dartmouth. He was known for his extensive writings on nonviolent struggle, which have influenced numerous anti-government resistance movements around the world.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Salt March</span> 1930 Indian protest led by Mahatma Gandhi

The Salt march, also known as the Salt Satyagraha, Dandi March, and the Dandi Satyagraha, was an act of nonviolent civil disobedience in colonial India, led by Mahatma Gandhi. The 24-day march lasted from 12 March 1930 to 6 April 1930 as a direct action campaign of tax resistance and nonviolent protest against the British salt monopoly. Another reason for this march was that the Civil Disobedience Movement needed a strong inauguration that would inspire more people to follow Gandhi's example. Gandhi started this march with 78 of his trusted volunteers. The march spanned 387 kilometres (240 mi), from Sabarmati Ashram to Dandi, which was called Navsari at that time. Growing numbers of Indians joined them along the way. When Gandhi broke the British Raj salt laws at 8:30 am on 6 April 1930, it sparked large-scale acts of civil disobedience against the salt laws by millions of Indians.

<i>Civil Disobedience</i> (Thoreau) 1849 essay by Henry David Thoreau

Resistance to Civil Government, also called On the Duty of Civil Disobedience or Civil Disobedience for short, is an essay by American transcendentalist Henry David Thoreau that was first published in 1849. In it, Thoreau argues that individuals should not permit governments to overrule or atrophy their consciences, and that they have a duty to avoid allowing such acquiescence to enable the government to make them the agents of injustice. Thoreau was motivated in part by his repulsion of slavery and the Mexican–American War (1846–1848).

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Tax resistance</span> Refusal to pay a tax in opposition to a government or policy, rather than taxation itself

Tax resistance is the refusal to pay tax because of opposition to the government that is imposing the tax, or to government policy, or as opposition to taxation in itself. Tax resistance is a form of direct action and, if in violation of the tax regulations, also a form of civil disobedience.

A nonviolent revolution is a revolution conducted primarily by unarmed civilians using tactics of civil resistance, including various forms of nonviolent protest, to bring about the departure of governments seen as entrenched and authoritarian without the use or threat of violence. While many campaigns of civil resistance are intended for much more limited goals than revolution, generally a nonviolent revolution is characterized by simultaneous advocacy of democracy, human rights, and national independence in the country concerned.

<i>The Masque of Anarchy</i> 1832 poem by Percy Bysshe Shelley

The Masque of Anarchy is a British political poem written in 1819 by Percy Bysshe Shelley following the Peterloo Massacre of that year. In his call for freedom, it is perhaps the first modern statement of the principle of nonviolent resistance.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Gandhism</span> Body of ideas inspired by Mahatma Gandhi

Gandhism is a body of ideas that describes the inspiration, vision, and the life work of Mohandas K. Gandhi. It is particularly associated with his contributions to the idea of nonviolent resistance, sometimes also called civil resistance.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Quit India speech</span> 1942 Indian-independence speech by Mahatma Gandhi

The Quit India speech was given by Mahatma Gandhi on the eve of the Quit India Movement, 8 August 1942. His address was issued shortly before midnight, at the Gowalia Tank Maidan park in Bombay, which has since been renamed August Kranti Maidan.

Civil resistance is a form of political action that relies on the use of nonviolent resistance by ordinary people to challenge a particular power, force, policy or regime. Civil resistance operates through appeals to the adversary, pressure and coercion: it can involve systematic attempts to undermine or expose the adversary's sources of power. Forms of action have included demonstrations, vigils and petitions; strikes, go-slows, boycotts and emigration movements; and sit-ins, occupations, constructive program, and the creation of parallel institutions of government.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Nonviolent resistance</span> Act of protest through nonviolent means

Nonviolent resistance, or nonviolent action, sometimes called civil resistance, is the practice of achieving goals such as social change through symbolic protests, civil disobedience, economic or political noncooperation, satyagraha, constructive program, or other methods, while refraining from violence and the threat of violence. This type of action highlights the desires of an individual or group that feels that something needs to change to improve the current condition of the resisting person or group.

Different Muslim movements through history had linked pacifism with Muslim theology. However, warfare has been an integral part of Islamic history both for the defense and the spread of the faith since the time of Muhammad.

Libertarian civil disobedience dates back at least as far as Henry David Thoreau, who was arrested for refusing to pay the poll tax. Dick Clark opines, "I do not think that most libertarians ought to pull up stakes and abandon their gainful employment only to throw their bodies into the cogs of the state. However, when the state comes roaring towards your home, it is heroism to dig in, stand firm, and resist for as long as possible." Manuel Lora has argued against libertarian "martyrdom." It has been argued that a libertarian civil disobedient "should not plead guilty, but should defend himself in court, in order to allow the possibility of changing the unjust law."

The following are examples of civil disobedience.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Direct action</span> Method of activism

Direct action is a term for economic and political behavior in which participants use agency—for example economic or physical power—to achieve their goals. The aim of direct action is to either obstruct a certain practice or to solve perceived problems.

<span class="mw-page-title-main">Diversity of tactics</span> Social phenomenon

Diversity of tactics is a phenomenon wherein a social movement makes periodic use of force for disruptive or defensive purposes, stepping beyond the limits of nonviolent resistance, but also stopping short of total militarization. It also refers to the theory which asserts this to be the most effective strategy of civil disobedience for social change. Diversity of tactics may promote nonviolent tactics, or armed resistance, or a range of methods in between, depending on the level of repression the political movement is facing. It sometimes claims to advocate for "forms of resistance that maximize respect for life".

Tax resistance in the United States has been practiced at least since colonial times, and has played important parts in American history.

References

  1. Violent Civil Disobedience and Willingness to Accept Punishment, vol. 8, Essays in Philosophy, June 2007, archived from the original on 13 June 2010, retrieved 12 March 2015
  2. John Morreall (1976), "The justifiability of violent civil disobedience", Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 6 (1): 35–47, doi:10.1080/00455091.1976.10716975, JSTOR   40230600, S2CID   152691269
  3. Steven L. Emanuel (January 2007), Criminal Law, Aspen, ISBN   9780735558182
  4. Brooks, Ned. "Meet The Press: Martin Luther King, Jr. on the Selma March". NBC Learn. NBCUniversal Media. Archived from the original on 5 July 2018. Retrieved 22 November 2017.
  5. Sophocle's Antigone Archived 11 May 2011 at the Wayback Machine , Project Gutenberg, F. Storr translation, 1912, Harvard University Press
  6. Adolf, A. (2013). Peace: A World History. Polity Press. p. 117. ISBN   978-0-7456-5459-1 . Retrieved 24 January 2023.
  7. Douglas R. Burgess, Jr., The Politics of Piracy: Crime and Civil Disobedience in Colonial America (University Press of New England, 2014). ISBN   9781611685275
  8. Jack Greene, "Empire and Identity from the Glorious Revolution to the American Revolution", in P.J. Marshal, ed., Oxford History of the British Empire, vol. 2 (Oxford University Press, 2001), 208–30
  9. Greene, Jack. Negotiated Authorities: Essays in Colonial Political and Constitutional History (Charlottesville: Univ. Press of VA, 1994).
  10. 1 2 3 Archived 5 January 2011 at the Wayback Machine
  11. Thomas Weber, Gandhi as Disciple and Mentor, Cambridge University Press, 2004, pp. 28–29.
  12. Weber, p. 28.
  13. Volk, Kyle G. (2014). Moral Minorities and the Making of American Democracy. New York: Oxford University Press.[ page needed ]
  14. Marlow, Joyce (1973). Captain Boycott and the Irish. André Deutsch. pp. 133–142. ISBN   978-0-233-96430-0.
  15. Zunes, Stephen (1999:42), Nonviolent Social Movements: A Geographical Perspective, Blackwell Publishing{{citation}}: CS1 maint: numeric names: authors list (link)
  16. Michael Lerner, Tikkun reader
  17. "The Orange Revolution". Time . 12 December 2004. Archived from the original on 10 April 2010. Retrieved 30 April 2010.
  18. "The Gospel Applied to the Fugitive Slave Law" (1851). a sermon, by Oliver Stearns
  19. "The Higher Law", in Its Application to the Fugitive Slave Bill: ... by John Newell and John Chase Lord (1851)
  20. The Limits of Civil Disobedience: A Sermon ..., by Nathaniel Hall (1851)
  21. The Duty and Limitations of Civil Disobedience: A Discourse, by Samuel Colcord Bartlett (1853)
  22. Marshall Cohen (Spring 1969), Civil Disobedience in a Constitutional Democracy, vol. 10, The Massachusetts Review, pp. 211–226
  23. J. L. LeGrande (September 1967), "Nonviolent Civil Disobedience and Police Enforcement Policy", The Journal of Criminal Law, Criminology, and Police Science, 58 (3), Northwestern University: 393–404, doi:10.2307/1141639, JSTOR   1141639, archived from the original on 19 July 2018, retrieved 20 April 2018
  24. Letter to P.K. Rao, Servants of India Society, 10 September 1935, Letter quoted in Louis Fischer's, The Life of Mahatma Gandhi, Part I, Chapter 11, pp. 87–88.
  25. ACLU of Oregon (October 2017), Your Right To Protest
  26. 1 2 Rex Martin (January 1970), Civil Disobedience, vol. 80, Ethics, pp. 123–139
  27. McElroy, Wendy. "Henry Thoreau and 'Civil Disobedience'". thoreau.eserver.org. Future of Freedom Foundation. Archived from the original on 18 September 2015. Retrieved 5 September 2015.
  28. Hayley Bennett, Alexandra Macmillan, Rhys Jones, Alison Blaiklock and John McMillan, "Should health professionals participate in civil disobedience in response to the climate change health emergency?", The Lancet , volume 395, issue 10220, pages 304-308, 25 January 2020 (and references cited).
  29. Ken Kress and Scott W. Anderson (Spring 1989), Dworkin in Transition, vol. 37, The American Journal of Comparative Law, pp. 337–351
  30. 1 2 3 Kimberley Brownlee (9 November 2006), "The communicative aspects of civil disobedience and lawful punishment", Criminal Law and Philosophy, 1 (2): 179, doi:10.1007/s11572-006-9015-9, S2CID   145019882
  31. Stephen Ellmann; Luban, David (January 1990), "Lawyering for Justice in a Flawed Democracy", Columbia Law Review, 90 (1): 116–190, doi:10.2307/1122838, JSTOR   1122838
  32. A Primer for Prospective Jurors (PDF), Fully Informed Jury Association, archived from the original (PDF) on 25 August 2013, retrieved 28 June 2013
  33. Magonet, Jonathan (1992) Bible Lives (London: SCM), 8
  34. Bay, Christian, Civil Disobedience, vol. II, International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, pp. 473–486
  35. Stuart M. Brown Jr., Civil Disobedience, vol. 58, The Journal of Philosophy
  36. H. J. McCloskey (June 1980), "Conscientious Disobedience of the Law: Its Necessity, Justification, and Problems to Which it Gives Rise", Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 40 (4): 536–557, doi:10.2307/2106847, JSTOR   2106847
  37. Davis D. Joyce, Howard Zinn: A Radical American Vision (Prometheus, 2003), 102–103. Joyce notes that Disobedience and Democracy sold 75,000 copies in the late 1960s and was Zinn's best-selling book prior to A People's History of the United States
  38. Howard Zinn, Disobedience and Democracy: Nine Fallacies on Law and Order (South End Press edition, 2002), 39–41
  39. Zinn, Disobedience, 47
  40. 1 2 "Howard Zinn, "Introduction" for The Higher Law: Thoreau on Civil Disobedience and Reform, Wendell Glick, ed., (Princeton University Press, 2004)". Archived from the original on 1 April 2015.
  41. Harry Prosch (April 1967), Toward an Ethics of Civil Disobedience, vol. 77, Ethics, pp. 176–192
  42. 1 2 Hugo A. Bedau (12 October 1961), "On Civil Disobedience", The Journal of Philosophy, 58 (21): 653–665, doi:10.2307/2023542, JSTOR   2023542
  43. 1 2 Thoreau, Henry David. Civil Disobedience .
  44. "Harvey Wheeler: The Constitutionality of Civil Disobedience". Archived from the original on 27 March 2015. Retrieved 6 May 2015.
  45. "Civil Disobedience | Encyclopedia.com". www.encyclopedia.com. Retrieved 10 July 2022.
  46. "Civil Disobedience". McGill Law Journal. Retrieved 10 July 2022.
  47. P Herngren (1993), Path of Resistance (PDF), The Practice of Civil Disobedience, archived from the original (PDF) on 28 July 2011
  48. Gross, Robert A. (October 2005), Quiet War With The State; Henry David Thoreau and Civil Disobedience., The Yale Review, pp. 1–17
  49. Brown case e-mails investigated, Union-Leader, 21 June 2007, archived from the original on 19 October 2007, retrieved 19 July 2010
  50. Clark, Dick (22 April 2008), Civil Disobedience and the Libertarian Division of Labor, LewRockwell.com, archived from the original on 20 March 2022
  51. Steinberg, Monica (3 July 2021). "Coercive Disobedience: Art and Simulated Transgression". Art Journal. 80 (3): 78–99. doi:10.1080/00043249.2021.1920288. ISSN   0004-3249. S2CID   237576098.
  52. Jeffrey S. Juris (2005), "The New Digital Media and Activist Networking within Anti-Corporate Globalization Movements", Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 597 (Cultural Production in a Digital Age): 189–208, doi:10.1177/0002716204270338, JSTOR   25046069, S2CID   145327747
  53. Laura Moth, Today's Zaman, 19 June 2013, A standing dilemma in Taksim
  54. Peters, Jeremy W. (4 June 2024). "Students Want Charges Dropped. What Is the Right Price for Protests?". The New York Times. ISSN   0362-4331 . Retrieved 29 July 2024.
  55. Watts v. Indiana , 338 U.S. 49 (1949)
  56. John Griffiths and Richard E. Ayres (December 1967), "A Postscript to the Miranda Project: Interrogation of Draft Protestors", The Yale Law Journal, 77 (2): 300–319, doi:10.2307/795080, JSTOR   795080, archived from the original on 18 December 2015, retrieved 27 July 2019
  57. Rules for Engaging in Civil Disobedience, Free State Project, archived from the original on 13 June 2010, retrieved 17 July 2010
  58. Civil Disobedience Training (PDF), ACT UP, 2003, archived (PDF) from the original on 22 June 2010, retrieved 17 July 2010
  59. Hurst, John (1978), "A-plant protesters being freed", Los Angeles Times
  60. 1 2 National Lawyers Guild, LA Chapter, Questions and Answers about Civil Disobedience and the Legal Process (PDF), archived from the original (PDF) on 27 July 2011
  61. Canada, Public Safety (21 December 2018). "The Social Reintegration of Offenders and Crime Prevention". www.publicsafety.gc.ca. Retrieved 10 July 2022.
  62. Howard Zinn, Disobedience and Disorder: Nine Fallacies on Law and Order, cited in Paul F. Power (March 1970), On Civil Disobedience in Recent American Democratic Thought, vol. 64, The American Political Science Review, p. 40
  63. Mirelle Cohen (October 2007), "The Camden 28 (review)", Teaching Sociology, 35 (4): 391–392, doi:10.1177/0092055x0703500423, S2CID   144154349
  64. Nick Gier (15 January 2006), Three Principles of Civil Disobedience: Thoreau, Gandhi, and King, Lewiston Morning Tribune
  65. Pestorius, Margaret (18 February 2020). "Your Activist Speech in Court". The Commons Social Change Library. Retrieved 12 August 2024.
  66. United States of America v. Norma Burgos-Andjar, 275F.3d23 .
  67. "Allocution". prosario-2000.0catch.com. Archived from the original on 16 November 2018. Retrieved 12 January 2019.
  68. "Tim DeChristopher's statement to the court". 28 July 2011. Archived from the original on 13 October 2015. Retrieved 2 September 2015.
  69. Steven E. Barkan (October 1979), Strategic, Tactical and Organizational Dilemmas of the Protest Movement against Nuclear Power, vol. 27, Social Problems, pp. 19–37
  70. Judgments – Sepet (FC) and Another (FC) (Appellants) v. Secretary of State for the Home Department (Respondent), 20 March 2003, archived from the original on 9 October 2017, retrieved 30 August 2017
  71. Ho, Joyce (4 December 2014). "Punish surrendering Occupy protesters leniently, Hong Kong top court judge urges". South China Morning Post . Archived from the original on 8 May 2019. Retrieved 30 May 2020.
  72. 1 2 Paul, Pamela (30 May 2024). "And Now, a Real-World Lesson for Student Activists". The New York Times. ISSN   0362-4331 . Retrieved 29 July 2024.
  73. Gecker, Jocelyn (28 April 2024). "College protesters want 'amnesty.' At stake: Tuition, legal charges, grades and graduation". AP News. Retrieved 29 July 2024.
  74. 1 2 Hall, Mitchell K. (20 May 2009). Vietnam War Era: People and Perspectives. Bloomsbury Publishing USA. p. 190. ISBN   978-1-59884-130-5. activists who participated in nonviolent civil disobedience faced...university administrators who expelled them, parents who disowned them, and other students who shunned them.
  75. Schwartz, Rafi (15 May 2024). "Are campus protesters jeopardizing their employment futures?". theweek. Retrieved 29 July 2024.
  76. Tenbarge, Kat (17 October 2023). "Law firm rescinds job offers to Harvard students over Israel letters". NBC News. Retrieved 29 July 2024.
  77. Grant, Nico (18 April 2024). "Google Fires 28 Employees Involved in Protest of Israeli Cloud Contract". The New York Times. ISSN   0362-4331 . Retrieved 29 July 2024.
  78. Thomas Morawetz (Summer 1986), Reconstructing the Criminal Defenses: The Significance of Justification, vol. 77, The Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, pp. 277–307
  79. Arthur W. Munk (September 1971), Civil Disobedience: Conscience, Tactics, and the Law, vol. 397, Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, pp. 211–212
  80. Robert T. Hall (January 1971), Legal Toleration of Civil Disobedience, vol. 81, Ethics, pp. 128–142
  81. U.S. v. Schoon , 939F2d826 (29 July 1991).
  82. Hughes, Graham (1968), Civil Disobedience and the Political Question Doctrine, vol. 43, N.Y.U. L. Rev., p. 1, archived from the original on 5 July 2018, retrieved 30 May 2020
  83. Steven M. Bauer and Peter J. Eckerstrom (May 1987), The State Made Me Do It: The Applicability of the Necessity Defense to Civil Disobedience, vol. 39, Stanford Law Review, pp. 1173–1200
  84. James L. Cavallaro Jr. (January 1993), The Demise of the Political Necessity Defense: Indirect Civil Disobedience and United States v. Schoon, vol. 81, California Law Review, pp. 351–385
  85. Robert Surbrug, Beyond Vietnam: The Politics of Protest in Massachusetts, 1974–1990
  86. "If You are Facing Charges" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 20 August 2010. Retrieved 19 July 2010.
  87. 18 U.S.C.   § 3553
  88. 3. The Basic Approach (Policy Statement), 2009 Federal Sentencing Guidelines Manual, archived from the original on 19 June 2010
  89. Michael Bayles (September 1970), The Justifiability of Civil Disobedience, vol. 24, The Review of Metaphysics, pp. 3–20
  90. Leslie J. Macfarlane (October 1968), Justifying Political Disobedience, vol. 79, Ethics, pp. 24–55

Further reading